Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-mkpzs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-27T04:30:34.091Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Skepticism Motivated: On the Skeptical Import of Motivated Reasoning

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  12 May 2020

J. Adam Carter*
Affiliation:
Philosophy, University of Glasgow, Glasgow, Scotland
Robin McKenna
Affiliation:
Philosophy, University of Liverpool, Liverpool, England
*
*Corresponding author: Email: [email protected]

Abstract

Empirical work on motivated reasoning suggests that our judgments are influenced to a surprising extent by our wants, desires, and preferences (Kahan 2016; Lord, Ross, and Lepper 1979; Molden and Higgins 2012; Taber and Lodge 2006). How should we evaluate the epistemic status of beliefs formed through motivated reasoning? For example, are such beliefs epistemically justified? Are they candidates for knowledge? In liberal democracies, these questions are increasingly controversial as well as politically timely (Beebe et al. 2018; Lynch Forthcoming, 2018; Slothuus and de Vreese 2010). And yet, the epistemological significance of motivated reasoning has been almost entirely ignored by those working in mainstream epistemology. We aim to rectify this oversight. Using politically motivated reasoning as a case study, we show how motivated reasoning gives rise to three distinct kinds of skeptical challenges. We conclude by showing how the skeptical import of motivated reasoning has some important ramifications for how we should think about the demands of intellectual humility.

Type
Article
Copyright
© The Author(s) 2020. Published by Canadian Journal of Philosophy

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Alston, William. 1985. “Concepts of Epistemic Justification.” The Monist 68 (1): 5789.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Audi, Robert. 1982. “Believing and Affirming.” Mind 91 (361): 115–20.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Avnur, Yuval, and Scott‐Kakures, Dion. 2015. “How Irrelevant Influences Bias Belief.” Philosophical Perspectives 29 (1): 739.10.1111/phpe.12060CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baron, Jonathan, and Jost, John T.. 2019. “False Equivalence: Are Liberals and Conservatives in the United States Equally Biased?” Perspectives on Psychological Science 14 (2): 292303.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Beebe, James R., Baghramian, Maria, Drury, Luke, and Dellsén, Finnur. 2018. “Divergent Perspectives on Expert Disagreement: Preliminary Evidence from Climate Science, Climate Policy.” https://arxiv.org/ftp/arxiv/papers/1802/1802.01889.pdf.Google Scholar
Bergmann, Michael. 2006. Justification without Awareness. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bondy, Patrick, and Carter, J. Adam. (2020). "The Superstitious Lawyer's Inference." In Well-Founded Belief: New Essays on the Epistemic Basing Relation, edited by Patrick Bondy and Carter, J. Adam. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Bradley, Gifford W. 1978. “Self-Serving Biases in the Attribution Process: A Reexamination of the Fact or Fiction Question.” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 36 (1): 5671.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brown, Roger. 1986. Social Psychology. 2nd ed. New York: Free Press.Google Scholar
Bullock, John G., Gerber, Alan S., and Hill, Seth J.. 2015. “Partisan Bias in Factual Beliefs about Politics.” Quarterly Journal of Political Science 10: 519–78.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burnstein, Eugene, and Vinokur, Amiram. 1977. “Persuasive Argumentation and Social Comparison as Determinants of Attitude Polarization.” Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 13 (4): 315–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carter, J. Adam, and Bondy, Patrick, eds. 2020. Well-Founded Belief: New Essays on the Epistemic Basing Relation. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Carter, J. Adam, and Pritchard, Duncan. "Cognitive Bias, Scepticism and Understanding." Explaining Understanding: New Perspectives from Epistemology and Philosophy of Science (2016): 272–91.Google Scholar
Carter, J. Adam, Kallestrup, Jesper, and Pritchard, Duncan. 2016. “Intellectual Humility.” Logos and Episteme 7 (7): 409–11.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Church, Ian M. 2017. “The Limitations of the Limitations-Owning Account of Intellectual Humility.” Philosophia 45 (3): 1077–84.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Church, Ian M., and Samuelson, Peter L.. 2017. Intellectual Humility: An Introduction to the Philosophy and Science. London: Bloomsbury Academic.Google Scholar
Cohen, G. A. 2001. If You’re an Egalitarian, How Come You’re So Rich ? Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Davis, John K. 2009. "Subjectivity, Judgment, and the Basing Relationship." Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 90 (1): 2140.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
DiPaolo, Joshua, and Simpson, Robert Mark. 2016. “Indoctrination Anxiety and the Etiology of Belief.” Synthese 193 (10): 3079–98.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ditto, Peter H., Scepansky, James A., Munro, Geoffrey D., Apanovitch, Anne Marie, and Lockhart, Lisa K.. 1998. “Motivated Sensitivity to Preference-Inconsistent Information.” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 75 (1): 5369.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ditto, Peter H., Liu, Brittany S., Clark, Cory J., Wojcik, Sean P., Chen, Eric E., Grady, Rebecca H., Celniker, Jared B., and Zinger, Joanne F.. 2019. “At Least Bias Is Bipartisan: A Meta-Analytic Comparison of Partisan Bias in Liberals and Conservatives.” Perspectives on Psychological Science 14 (2): 273–91.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Fischhoff, Baruch, and Beyth, Ruth. 1975. “‘I Knew It Would Happen.’” Organizational Behavior and Human Performance 13 (1): 116.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gampa, Anup, Wojcik, Sean, Motyl, Matt, Nosek, Brian, and Ditto, Peter. Forthcoming. “(Ideo)Logical Reasoning: Ideology Impairs Sound Reasoning.” Social Psychological and Personality Science. https://doi.org/10.1177/1948550619829059.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gigerenzer, Gerd. 2000. Simple Heuristics That Make Us Smart. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Ginet, Carl. 1985. “Contra Reliabilism.” The Monist 68 (2): 175–87.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldman, Alvin. 1988. "Strong and Weak justification." Philosophical Perspectives, 2: 5169.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gordon, Emma C. 2018. “Intellectual Humility, Spirituality and Counselling.” Journal of Psychology and Theology 49 (4). https://doi.org/10.1177/0091647118807185.Google Scholar
Graham, Peter J. 2012. “Epistemic Entitlement.” Noûs 46 (3): 449–82.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Greco, Dan. Forthcoming. “Climate Change and Cultural Cognition.Philosophy and Climate Change.Google Scholar
Greco, John. 2010. Achieving Knowledge: A Virtue-Theoretic Account of Epistemic Normativity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gunn, Hanna, Johnson, Casey Rebecca, Lynch, Michael P., and Sheff, Nathan. 2017. “Intellectual Humility.” In Oxford Bibliographies in Philosophy, edited by Pritchard, Duncan. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Harman, Gilbert H. 1970. “Knowledge, Reasons, and Causes.” Journal of Philosophy 67 (21): 841–55.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hodson, Gordon, and Busseri, Michael. 2012. “Bright Minds and Dark Attitudes: Lower Cognitive Ability Predicts Greater Prejudice through Right-Wing Ideology and Low Intergroup Contact.” Psychological Science 23 (2): 187–95.10.1177/0956797611421206CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Huemer, Michael. 2016. “Why People Are Irrational about Politic.” In Philosophy, Politics and Economics: An Anthology, edited by Brennan, Geoffrey, Munger, Michael C., and Sayre-McCord, Geoffrey, 456–67. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Jost, John T., Hennes, Erin P., and Lavine, Howard. 2013. “‘Hot’ Political Cognition: Its Self-, Group-, and System-Serving Purposes.” In The Oxford Handbook of Social Cognition, edited by Carlston, Dona, 851–75. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kahan, Dan. 2013. “Ideology, Motivated Reasoning, and Cognitive Reflection.” Judgment and Decision Making 8 (4): 407–24.Google Scholar
Kahan, Dan. 2014. “Making Climate-Science Communication Evidence-Based—All the Way Down.” In Culture, Politics and Climate Change, edited by Boykoff, M. and Crow, D., 203–20. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Kahan, Dan. 2016. “The Politically Motivated Reasoning Paradigm, Part 1: What Politically Motivated Reasoning Is and How to Measure It.” In Emerging Trends in the Social and Behavioral Sciences, 1–16. https://doi.org/10.1002/9781118900772.etrds0417.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kahan, Dan, Hoffman, David, Evans, Danieli, Devins, Neal, Lucci, Eugene, and Cheng, Katherine. 2016. “‘Ideology’ or ‘Situation Sense’? An Experimental Investigation of Motivated Reasoning and Professional Judgment.” University of Pennsylvania Law Review 164 (349): 349438.Google Scholar
Kahan, Dan, Jenkins-Smith, Hank, and Braman, Donald. 2011. “Cultural Cognition of Scientific Consensus.” Journal of Risk Research 14 (2): 147–74.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kallestrup, Jesper, and Pritchard, Duncan. 2012. “Robust Virtue Epistemology and Epistemic Anti-Individualism.” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 93 (1): 84103.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kallestrup, Jesper, and Pritchard, Duncan. 2014. “Virtue Epistemology and Epistemic Twin Earth.” European Journal of Philosophy 22 (3): 335–57.10.1111/j.1468-0378.2011.00495.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kallestrup, Jesper, and Pritchard, Duncan. 2016. “From Epistemic Anti-Individualism to Intellectual Humility.” Res Philosophica 93 (3): 533–52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kanazawa, Satoshi. 2010. “Why Liberals and Atheists Are More Intelligent.” Social Psychology Quarterly 73 (1): 3357.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kelly, Thomas. 2008. “Disagreement, Dogmatism, and Belief Polarization.” Journal of Philosophy 105 (10): 611–33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kidd, Ian James. 2016. “Intellectual Humility, Confidence, and Argumentation.” Topoi 35 (2): 395402.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Korcz, Keith. 2000. “The Causal-Doxastic Theory of the Basing Relation.” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 30 (4): 525–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kornblith, Hilary, 1999. "Distrusting Reason." Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 23 (1): 181–96.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kunda, Ziva. 1987. “Motivated Inference: Self-Serving Generation and Evaluation of Causal Theories.” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 53 (4): 636–47.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kunda, Ziva. 1990. “The Case for Motivated Reasoning.” Psychological Bulletin 108 (3): 480.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kvanvig, Jonathan. 2003. “Propositionalism and the Perspectival Character of Justification.” American Philosophical Quarterly 40 (1): 317.Google Scholar
Lackey, Jennifer. 2007a. “Norms of Assertion.” Noûs 41 (4): 594626.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lackey, Jennifer. 2007b. “Why We Don’t Deserve Credit for Everything We Know.” Synthese 158 (3): 345–61.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lackey, Jennifer. 2009. “Knowledge and Credit.” Philosophical Studies 142 (1): 2742.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, David. 1996. “Elusive Knowledge.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 74 (4): 549–67.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lord, Charles G., Ross, Lee, and Lepper, Mark R.. 1979. “Biased Assimiliation and Attitude Polarization: The Effects of Prior Theories on Subsequently Considered Evidence.” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 37 (11): 2098–109.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lynch, Michael P. Forthcoming. “Epistemic Humility, Epistemic Arrogance and Political Conviction.” Episteme.Google Scholar
Lynch, Michael P. 2018. “Epistemic Arrogance and Political Dissent.” In Voicing Dissent: The Ethics and Epistemology of Making Disagreement Public, edited by Johnson, Casey Rebecca, 129–39. London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lyons, Jack. Forthcoming. “Algorithm and Parameters: Solving the Generality Problem for Reliabilism.” Philosophical Review.Google Scholar
McCain, Kevin. 2012. “The Interventionist Account of Causation and the Basing Relation.” Philosophical Studies 159 (3): 357–82.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mercier, Hugo, and Sperber, Dan. 2017. The Enigma of Reason. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mogensen, Andreas L. 2016. “Contingency Anxiety and the Epistemology of Disagreement.” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 97 (4): 590611.10.1111/papq.12099CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Molden, Daniel C., and Higgins, E. Tory. 2012. “Motivated Thinking.” In The Oxford Handbook of Thinking and Reasoning, edited by Holyoak, Keith and Morrison, Robert, 390409.Google Scholar
Moser, Paul. 1989. Knowledge and Evidence. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
National Research Council Board on Radioactive Waste Management. 1990. “Rethinking High-Level Radioactive Waste Disposal: A Position Statement of the Board on Radioactive Waste Management.” Washington, DC: National Academy Press.Google Scholar
National Research Council Committee on Analysis of Global Change Assessments. 2007. “Analysis of Global Change Assessments: Lessons Learned.” Washington, DC: National Academies Press.Google Scholar
National Research Council Committee to Improve Research Information and Data on Firearms. 2004. “Firearms and Violence: A Critical Review.” Washington, DC: National Academies Press.Google Scholar
Plantinga, Alvin. 1993. Warrant: The Current Debate. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pollock, John L., and Cruz, Joseph. 1999. Contemporary Theories of Knowledge. Lanham, MA: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
Prior, Markus, Sood, Gaurav, and Khanna, Kabir. 2015. “You Cannot Be Serious: The Impact of Accuracy Incentives on Partisan Bias in Reports of Economic Perceptions.” Quarterly Journal of Political Science 10: 489518.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Redlawsk, David P. 2002. “Hot Cognition or Cool Consideration? Testing the Effects of Motivated Reasoning on Political Decision Making.” The Journal of Politics 64 (4): 1021–44.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rini, Regina. 2017. “Fake News and Partisan Epistemology.” Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 27 (S2): 4364.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ryle, Gilbert. 1945. “Knowing How and Knowing That.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 46: 116.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schoenfield, Miriam. 2013. “Permission to Believe: Why Permissivism Is True and What It Tells Us About Irrelevant Influences on Belief.” Noûs 47 (1): 193218.Google Scholar
Schwitzgebel, Eric. 2011. Perplexities of Consciousness. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sher, George. 2001. “But I Could Be Wrong.” Social Philosophy and Policy 18 (2): 64.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Slothuus, Rune, and de Vreese, Claes H.. 2010. “Political Parties, Motivated Reasoning, and Issue Framing Effects.” The Journal of Politics 72 (3): 630–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Simion, Mona. 2019. "Knowledge‐First Functionalism." Philosophical Issues 29 (1): 254–67.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sosa, Ernest. 2015. Judgment and Agency. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Srinivasan, Amia. 2015. “The Archimedean Urge.” Philosophical Perspectives 29 (1): 325–62.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Street, Sharon. 2006. “A Darwinian Dilemma for Realist Theories of Value.” Philosophical Studies 127 (1): 109–66.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Swain, Marshall. 1981. Reasons and Knowledge. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Taber, Charles S., and Lodge, Milton. 2006. “Motivated Skepticism in the Evaluation of Political Beliefs.” American Journal of Political Science 50 (3): 755–69.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tanesini, Alessandra. 2018. “Intellectual Humility as Attitude.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 96 (2): 399420.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tangney, June P. 2009. “Humility.” In Oxford Handbook of Positive Psychology, edited by Lopez, Shane P. and Snyder, C. R., 483–90. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Turri, John. 2010. “On the Relationship between Propositional and Doxastic Justification.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 80 (2): 312–26.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Turri, John. 2011. “Believing For a Reason.” Erkenntnis 74 (3): 383–97.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vavova, Katia. 2018. “Irrelevant Influences.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 96 (1): 134–52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Whitcomb, Dennis, Battaly, Heather, Baehr, Jason, and Howard-Snyder, Daniel. 2017. “Intellectual Humility: Owning Our Limitations.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 94 (3): 509–39.10.1111/phpr.12228CrossRefGoogle Scholar
White, Roger. 2010. “You Just Believe That Because …” Philosophical Perspectives 24 (1): 573615.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Worsnip, Alex. 2018. “The Obligation to Diversify One’s Sources: Against Epistemic Partisanship in the Consumption of News Media.” In Media Ethics: Free Speech and the Requirements of Democracy, edited by Fox, Carl and Saunders, Joe. Abingdon, UK: Routledge.Google Scholar