Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-rdxmf Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-22T04:40:58.800Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Responsibility, Tracing, and Consequences

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2020

Andrew C. Khoury*
Affiliation:
London School of Economics, Houghton Street, LondonWCA 2AE, UK

Extract

Some accounts of moral responsibility hold that an agent's responsibility is completely determined by some aspect of the agent's mental life at the time of action. For example, some hold that an agent is responsible if and only if there is an appropriate mesh among the agent's particular psychological elements. It is often objected that the particular features of the agent's mental life to which these theorists appeal (such as a particular structure or mesh) are not necessary for responsibility. This is because there appear to be cases in which an agent acts at an earlier time which causes her to lack the appropriate psychological features at some later time and yet, intuitively, she is responsible at that later time. Instead, it is thought, we must adopt a tracing principle that allows us to account for responsibility in these cases by tracing back from the later consequence to some earlier action. My project here is twofold.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Authors 2012

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Aristotle, . 1998. Nicomachean Ethics. Ross, trans. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Copp, D. 1997. ‘Defending the Principle of Alternate Possibilities: Blameworthiness and Moral Responsibility.Noûs 31: 441–56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davidson, D. 2001. ‘Agency.’ In Essays on Actions and Events. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 4361.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Domsky, D. 2004. ‘There Is No Door: Finally Solving the Problem of Moral Luck.Journal of Philosophy 101: 445–64.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fischer, J. M. and Ravizza, M.. 1998. Responsibility and Control: A Theory of Moral Responsibility. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fischer, J. M. and Tognazzini, N.. 2009. ‘The Truth about Tracing.Noûs 43: 531–56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frankfurt, H. 1971. ‘Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person.Journal of Philosophy 68: 5–20.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Graham, P. Forthcoming. ‘A Sketch of a Theory of Moral Blameworthiness.’ Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. A. Forthcoming, Khoury. ‘Synchronic and Diachronic Responsibility.’ Philosophical Studies.Google Scholar
McKenna, M. 2008. ‘A Hard-line Reply to Pereboom's Four-Case Manipulation Argument.Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 77: 142–59.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagel, T. 1979. Mortal Questions. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Royzman, E. and R., Kumar. 2004. ‘Is Consequential Luck Morally Inconsequential? Empirical Psychology and the Reassessment of Moral Luck.Ratio 17: 329–44.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scott Card, O. 1991. Ender’s Game. New York: Tor Books.Google Scholar
Vargas, M. 2005. ‘The Trouble with Tracing.’ Midwest Studies in Philosophy 29: 269–91.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Watson, G. 1975. ‘Free Agency.’ Journal of Philosophy 72: 205–20.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, B. 1981. Moral Luck. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zimmerman, M.J. 1987. ‘Luck and Moral Responsibility.’ Ethics 97: 374–86.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zimmerman, M.J. 1997. ‘A Plea for Accuses.’ American Philosophical Quarterly 34: 229–43.Google Scholar
Zimmerman, M.J. 2002. ‘Taking Luck Seriously.’ Journal of Philosophy 99: 553–76.CrossRefGoogle Scholar