Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-t8hqh Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-22T14:43:08.808Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

A relational account of intellectual autonomy

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2020

Benjamin Elzinga*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, Georgetown University, Washington, D.C., USA

Abstract

According to relational views of autonomy, some social relations or forms of dependence are necessary for autonomous agency. Recent relational theorists have primarily focused on autonomy of action or practical autonomy, and the result has been a shift away from individualistic conceptions of autonomy in the practical realm. Despite these trends, individualistic conceptions are still the default when it comes to autonomy of belief or intellectual autonomy. In this paper, I argue for a relational account of intellectual autonomy. Specifically, I claim that intellectual autonomy requires a sense of one’s standing as an equal member of the epistemic community.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Journal of Philosophy 2018

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Anderson, J., and Honneth, A.. 2005. “Autonomy, Vulnerability, Recognition, and Justice.” In Autonomy and the Challenges to Liberalism, edited by Christman, J. and Anderson, J., 127149. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Benson, P., 1994. “Free Agency and Self-Worth.” The Journal of Philosophy, 91 (12): 650668. doi:10.2307/2940760.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Benson, P., 2005. “Feminist Intuitions and the Normative Substance of Autonomy.” In Personal Autonomy: New Essays on Personal Autonomy and Its Role in Contemporary Moral Philosophy, edited by Stacey Taylor, J., 124142, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Benson, P., 2011. “Narrative Self-Understanding and Relational Autonomy”. In Symposia on Gender, Race and Philosophy, 7(1) 14. Accessed 8 February 2017. http://web.mit.edu/sgrp/2011/no1/SGRPvol7no12011.pdfGoogle Scholar
Benson, P., 2014. “Feminist Commitments and Relational Autonomy.” In Autonomy, Oppression, Gender, edited by Veltman, A. and Piper, M., 87113, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Benson, P. H., 2015. “Stereotype Threat, Social Belonging, and Relational Autonomy.” In Personal Autonomy and Social Oppression: Philosophical Perspectives, edited by Oshana, M., 124141, New York, NY: RoutledgeGoogle Scholar
Berenstain, N., 2016. “Epistemic Exploitation.” Ergo, an Open Access Journal of Philosophy, 3 (20): 569590. doi:10.3998/ergo.12405314.0003.022.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bratman, M., 2005. “Planning Agency, Autonomous Agency.” In Personal Autonomy: New Essays on Personal Autonomy and Its Role in Contemporary Moral Philosophy, edited by Stacey Taylor, J., 3357, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brownmiller, S., 1999. In Our Time: Memoir of a Revolution. New York: Dial.Google Scholar
Christman, J., 1991. “Autonomy and Personal History.” Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 21 (1): 124. 33. doi:10.1080/00455091.1991.10717234.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Christman, J., 2004. “Relational Autonomy, Liberal Individualism, and the Social Constitution of Selves.” Philosophical Studies, 117: 143164. doi:10.1023/B:PHIL.0000014532.56866.5c.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dewey, J., 1916. Democracy and Education. New York, NY: Macmillan Company.Google Scholar
Dotson, K., 2012. “A Cautionary Tale: On Limiting Epistemic Oppression.” Frontiers: A Journal of Women Studies, 33 (1): 2447. doi:10.5250/fronjwomestud.33.1.0024.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dotson, K., 2014. “Conceptualizing Epistemic Oppression.” Social Epistemology, 28 (2): 115138. doi:10.1080/02691728.2013.782585.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dworkin, G., 1988. The Theory and Practice of Autonomy. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Elzinga, B., 2018a. “Self-Regulation and Knowledge How.” Episteme, 15 (1): 119140. doi:10.1017/epi.2016.45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Elzinga, B., 2018b. “Hermeneutical Injustice and Liberatory Education.” The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 56: 5982. doi:10.1111/sjp.12268.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fichte, J. G., 2000. Foundations of Natural Right. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Frankfurt, H., 1971. “Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person.” Journal of Philosophy, 68: 520. doi:10.2307/2024717.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Freire, P., 2000. Pedagogy of the Oppressed. New York, NY: Bloomsbury Publishing.Google Scholar
Fricker, E., 2006. “Testimony and Epistemic Authority.” In The Epistemology of Testimony, edited by Lackey, J. and Sosa, E.. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Fricker, M., 2009. Epistemic Injustice: Power and the Ethics of Knowing. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Friedman, M., 2003. Autonomy, Gender, Politics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldberg, S., 2006. “Reductionism and the Distinctiveness of Testimonial Knowledge.” In The Epistemology of Testimony, edited by Lackey, J. and Sosa, E., 127144. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldman, A. I., 2001. “Experts: Which Ones Should You Trust?Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 63 (1): 85110. doi:10.1111/phpr.2001.63.issue-1.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haugeland, J., 1998. Having Thought: Essays in the Metaphysics of Mind. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Haugeland, J., 2002. “Authentic Intentionality.” In Computationalism: New Directions, edited by Scheutz, M., 159174, Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Hegel, G. W. F., 1977. Phenomenology of Spirit. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Holroyd, J., 2009. “Relational Autonomy and Paternalistic Interventions.” Res Publica (Liverpool, England), 15 (4): 321. doi:10.1007/s11158-009-9090-6.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Khader, S., 2011. Adaptive Preferences and Women’s Empowerment. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kukla, R., 2006. “Objectivity and Perspective in Empirical Knowledge.” Episteme, 3 (1): 8095. doi:10.3366/epi.2006.3.1-2.80.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Löwenstein, D., 2017. Know-How as Competence. A Rylean Responsibilist Account. Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann.Google Scholar
Mackenzie, C., and Stoljar, N.. 2000. “Autonomy Refigured.” In Relational Autonomy: Feminist Perspectives on Autonomy, Agency and the Social Self, edited by Mackenzie, C. and Stoljar, N., 331, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Mackenzie, C., 2014. “Three Dimensions of Autonomy: A Relational Analysis.” In Autonomy, Oppression, Gender, edited by Veltman, A. and Piper, M., 1541, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mackenzie, C., 2015. “Responding to the Agency Dilemma: Autonomy, Adaptive Preferences and Internalized Oppression.” In Personal Autonomy and Social Oppression: Philosophical Perspectives, edited by Oshana, M., 4867.New York, NY: Routledge.Google Scholar
McDowell, J., 2010. “Brandom on Observation.” In Reading Brandom: On Making It Explicit, edited by Weiss, B. and Wanderer, J., 129144, New York, NY: Routledge.Google Scholar
Medina, J., 2013. The Epistemology of Resistance: Gender and Racial Oppression, Epistemic Injustice, and Resistant Imaginations. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Meyers, D., 1987. “Personal Autonomy and the Paradox of Feminine Socialization.” Journal of Philosophy, 84: 619628. doi:10.5840/jphil198784117.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Meyers, D., 2000. “Intersectional Identity and the Authentic Self. Opposites Attract!.” In Relational Autonomy: Feminist Perspectives on Autonomy, Agency and the Social Self, edited by Mackenzie, C. and Stoljar, N., 151180, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Meyers, D., 2002. Gender in the Mirror: Cultural Imagery and Women’s Agency. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Meyers, D., 2004. Being Yourself: Essays on Identity, Action, and Social Life. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
Meyers, D., 2005. “Decentralizing Autonomy: Five Faces of Selfhood.” In Autonomy and the Challenges to Liberalism, edited by Christman, J. and Anderson, J., 2755. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Meyers, D. T., 2014. “The Feminist Debate over Values in Autonomy Theory.” In Autonomy, Oppression, Gender, edited by Veltman, A. and Piper, M., 114140, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nedelsky, J., 1989. “Reconceiving Autonomy: Sources, Thoughts and Possibilities.” Yale Journal of Law and Feminism, 1: 736.Google Scholar
Oshana, M., 2006. Personal Autonomy in Society. Aldershot: Ashgate Publishing.Google Scholar
Oshana, M., 2015. “Is Social-Relational Autonomy a Plausible Ideal.” In Personal Autonomy and Social Oppression: Philosophical Perspectives, edited by Oshana, M., 324, New York, NY: Routledge.Google Scholar
Pohlhaus, G., 2012. “Relational Knowing and Epistemic Injustice: Toward a Theory of Willful Hermeneutical Ignorance.” Hypatia, 27 (4): 715735. doi:10.1111/hypa.2012.27.issue-4.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pritchard, D., 2016. “Seeing It for Oneself: Perceptual Knowledge, Understanding, and Intellectual Autonomy.” Episteme, 13 (01): 2942. doi:10.1017/epi.2015.59.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Roessler, B., 2015. “Autonomy, Self-Knowledge, and Oppression.” In Personal Autonomy and Social Oppression: Philosophical Perspectives, edited by Oshana, M., 6884, New York, NY: Routledge.Google Scholar
Sellars, W., 1953. “Inference and Meaning.” Mind; a Quarterly Review of Psychology and Philosophy, 62 (247): 313338. doi:10.1093/mind/LXII.247.313.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sellars, W., 1974. “Meaning as Functional Classification.” Synthese, 27 (3–4): 417437. doi:10.1007/BF00484606.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Snowden, P. T., Davies, I. R., and Roling, P.. 2000. “Perceptual Learning of the Detection of Features in X-Ray Images: A Functional Role for Improvements in Adults’ Visual Sensitivity?Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 26 (1): 379.Google Scholar
Stoljar, N., 2000. “Autonomy and the Feminist Intuition.” In Relational Autonomy: Feminist Perspectives on Autonomy, Agency and the Social Self, edited by Mackenzie, C. and Stoljar, N., 94111, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Warriner, J., 2015. “Gender Oppression and Weak Substantive Theories of Autonomy.” In Personal Autonomy and Social Oppression: Philosophical Perspectives, edited by Oshana, M., 2547, New York, NY: Routledge.Google Scholar
Westlund, A., 2009. “Rethinking Relational Autonomy.” Hypatia, 24 (4): 2649. doi:10.1111/j.1527-2001.2009.01056.x.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Westlund, A., 2014. “Autonomy and Self-Care.” In Autonomy, Oppression, Gender, edited by Veltman, A. and Piper, M., 181198, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zagzebski, L., 2007. “Ethical and Epistemic Egoism and the Ideal of Autonomy.” Episteme, 4 (03): 252263. doi:10.3366/E174236000700007X.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zagzebski, L., 2013. “Intellectual Autonomy.” Philosophical Issues, 23 (1): 244261. doi:10.1111/phis.2013.23.issue-1.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zagzebski, L., 2015. Epistemic Authority: A Theory of Trust, Authority, and Autonomy in Belief. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar