Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-8ctnn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-23T03:05:30.823Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Ethical Intuitionism and Naturalism: A Reconciliation

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2020

M. B. E. Smith*
Affiliation:
Smith College

Extract

Intuitionism is most commonly defined in terms of various strong epistemological and metaphysical presuppositions, e.g., that true moral principles are synthetic a priori propositions, known by some special faculty of moral reflection, and the like. I shall not here be concerned with such views. Rather my focus will be upon the program for normative investigation which I have elsewhere argued is implicit in the intuitionists’ writings and which I take to be intuitionism's salient characteristic.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Authors 1979

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 In my “Rawls and lntuitioinism,” in New Essays in Contract Theory, Canadian Journal of Philosophy, supp. val. 3(1977).

2 I borrow the notion of a considered judgment from John Rawls, who characterizes it as applying to judgments made in such circumstances that “the more common excuses and explanations for making a mistake do not obtain,” i.e., when we are confident in our opinion, when we are not emotionally upset, when our interests are not directly affected, and when we have a desire to reach a correct determination. See: Rawls's, John A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, Mass: 1971). pp. 47f.Google Scholar

3 For the suggestion that both Rawls's theory and intuitionism are subjectivist, see Hare, R. M., “Rawls’ Theory of Justice, 1,” Philosophical Quarterly 23 (1973), pp. 145f.Google Scholar S. Lukes suggests that Rawls's appeal to our considered judgments is invidiously parochial-and I suppose he would be willing to generalize the pointin his “Relativism: Cognitive and Moral,” Aristotelian Society supp. vol. 8 1974), esp. p. 184.Google Scholar See also: Nielsen, K., “Our Considered Judgements,” Ratio 19 (1977).Google Scholar

4 Many of Rawls's commentators have argued that his method fails to yield determinate principles of justice. I find particularly persuasive Gardner's, M. R. “Rawls on the Maximin Rule and Distributive Justice,” Philosophical Studies 27 (1975).CrossRefGoogle Scholar I argue that it similarly fails to yield determinate principles of individual duty and obligation in my “Rawls and Intuitionism.” For discussion of Hare's method, see Locke, D., “The Trivializability of Universalizability,” Philosophical Review 77 1968).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

5 I here assume that we have a pretheoretical ability to distinguish moral judgments from nonmoral ones and, hence, a pretheoretical ability to distinguish moral sentences from nonmoral ones. (Of course, a sentence may do double duty: on some occasions of its use it may express a moral judgment and on others a nonmoral one, as is shown by the hoary example of “In Sparta it was good to steal,” which may be used either to express one's own judgment about Spartan practices or simply to remark on the Spartan moral code.) Some may find this assumption problematical, but it seems to be an essential presupposition of any metaethical inquiry: were we to lack this pretheoretical ability we should have no way at all to distinguish the moral from the nonmoral, and so could never assess competing metaethical claims.

6 Kripke, S., “Naming and Necessity,” in Davidson, D. and Harman, G., eds., Semantics of Natural Languages (Dordrecht: 1972);Google Scholar and Putnam, H., Mind, Language, and Reality (New York: 1975)CrossRefGoogle Scholar, esp. “Is Semantics Possible” and “The Meaning of ‘Meaning'.“

7 For argument contra Putnam to this effect, see Schwartz, S. P., “Putnam on Artifacts,” Philosophical Review 87 (1978);CrossRefGoogle Scholar and Goosens, W. K., “Underlying Trait Terms,” in Schwartz, S. P., ed., Natural Kinds (Ithaca: 1977).Google Scholar For a more sweeping critique, see J. J. Katz, “A Proper Theory of Names,” Philosophical Studies 31 (1977).

8 Chomsky, N., Aspects of the Theory of Syntax (Cambridge, Mass: 1965)Google Scholar, chapter 1. See also: Katz, J.J., The Philosophy of Language (New York: 1966), pp. 115-18Google Scholar, and “A Proper Theory of Names,” op. cit., pp. 36f. I am aware that Chomsky's program is controversial, that some linguists and philosophers object to its appeal to linguistic intuitions. See esp.: Waldo, J., “Remarks on the Notion of Grammaticality,” in Stillings, J., ed., University of Massachusetts Occasional Papers in Linguistics, val. 2 (Amherst: 1976)Google Scholar; and Labov, W., “Methodology” in Dingwall, W., A Survey of Linguistic Science (College Park: 1971).Google Scholar I can here but say that I find Chomsky's views more persuasive.

9 McCawley, J. D., “The Role of Semantics in a Grammar,” in Bach, E. and Harms, R. T., eds., Universals in Linguistic Theory (New York: 1968). p. 129.Google Scholar

10 With some small changes I have taken this example from Bever, T., “The Psychology of Language,” in Harman, G., ed., On Noam Chomsky: Critical Essays (Garden City: 1974), p. 150.Google Scholar

11 J. Rawls, A Theory of justice, pp. 49f.

12 Such an understanding and criticism of Rawls may be found in Nagel, T., “Rawls on Justice,” Philosophical Review 82 (1973), p. 221,CrossRefGoogle Scholar and in R. M. Hare, “Rawls’ Theory of Justice, 1,” op. cit., p. 148. But, although Rawls thinks moral theory is subject to methodological constraints identical to those which govern other theoretical enterprises, he nowhere recommends that moral theorists follow linguists’ methodology specifically; and he is certainly not to be read as espousing any sort of moral foundationalism. Rather his point in making the comparison was mainly to prepare his reader for the subtlety and complexity of his own theory. Anticipating that the ease and familiarity with which we arrive at moral judgment may lead some to suppose that the principles which underlie and explain them can be of no great complexity, he points out that we speak grammatically with analogous ease and familiarity, but that describing our sense of grammaticality is an exceedingly complicated business.

13 Hare, R. M., The Language of Morals (Oxford: 1951), esp. pp. 163-79.Google Scholar I here understand prescriptivism to encapsulate the view about moral acceptance or belief which is often called internalism, viz., that a person who accepts a moral judgment must have some favorable attitude towards the thing that the judgment is about-or, which is the same thing, that he must have some inclination to act in accordance with the judgment. Moreover, it holds that moral sentences have the pragmatic property of necessarily expressing the attitudes or commitments of those persons who sincerely assert or assent to them.

14 Nor need we suppose the speaker to have any feelings, which marks off our theory from a family of theories superficially resembling it, those which appeal to the reactions of an ideal observer.

15 For a critical discussion of prescriptivism, see my “Indifference and Moral Acceptance,” American Philosophical Quarterly 9 (1972), pp. 8693.Google Scholar

16 I was put in mind of the cluster hypothesis by a passage on p. 201 of Lewis, D. K., Convention (Cambridge, Mass: 1969).Google Scholar

17 For such argument, with which I largely agree, see Lean, M. L., “Aren't Moral Judgements Factual?” in Hospers, J. and Sellars, W., eds., Readings in Ethical Theory, 2nd ed. (New York: 1975), pp. 382-84.Google Scholar See also Warnock, G. J., Contemporary Moral Philosophy (New York: 1967), pp. 4852.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

18 Frankena, W. K., “The Naturalistic Fallacy,” Mind 48 (1939);Google Scholar Sumner, L. W., “Hare's Arguments Against Ethical Naturalism,” Journal of Philosophy 64 (1967).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

19 For such an argument against naturalism, see Hare, R. M., “The Practical Relevance of Philosophy,” in his Essays on Philosophical Method (London 1971), pp. 112-14;Google Scholar for one against intuitionism, see Noweii-Smith, P. H., Ethics (Harmondsworth: 1954). pp. 4042.Google Scholar

20 For suggesting this point I am indebted to Elizabeth C. Scott, who was generally helpful throughout.

21 R. M. Hare, he Language of Morals, pp. 18-27.

22 See my “Foot and Hare on Naturalism,” Metaphilosophy (1974), esp. pp. 193-97.Google Scholar

23 So far as I am aware, the independence of the question as to what entailment relations moral sentences stand in from that as to what their pragmatic properties might be has been appreciated only by P. Foot in her “Moral Arguments,” Mind, 68 (1958). She there conceded arguendo the truth of prescriptivism, and then suggested that no good argument has been produced to bar the deduction of evaluative conclusions from nonevaluative premises. For critical discussion of Foot's own naturalistic argument, see my “Foot and Hare on Naturalism.“

24 I believe, although I am not wholly certain, that Moore offers something like this argument in Principia Ethica (Oxford: 1903), p. 12. See also: R. M. Hare, “The Practical Relevance of Philosophy.”