Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-t7czq Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-22T15:38:36.886Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Backing as Truthmaking

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  26 November 2021

Alexios Stamatiadis-Bréhier*
Affiliation:
School of Philosophy, Religion, and History of Science, University of Leeds, Leeds, UK
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Separatists about grounding take explanations to be separate from their corresponding grounding-facts. Grounding-facts are supposed to underlie, or back, such explanations. However, the backing relation hasn’t received much attention in the literature. The aim of this paper is to provide an informative definition of backing. First, I examine two prominent proposals: backing as explaining (Kovacs 2017; 2019a) and backing as grounding (see Sjölin Wirling 2020). Finally, I put forward my own proposal. I argue that under plausible assumptions about the role of backing and the nature of explanation, backing should be understood as a form of truthmaking, minimally construed.

Type
Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2021. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of Canadian Journal of Philosophy

1. Introduction

Grounding is a worldly noncausal determination relation that is widely thought to be linked with a particular kind of noncausal explanation.Footnote 1 Typical examples of grounding-facts include mental states being grounded in their physical features, chairs by their constituents, and sets by their instances. Unionists about grounding take grounding-facts to be identical to their corresponding explanations. Separatists, on the other hand, argue that explanations are distinct from grounding-facts: grounding-facts underlie, or back, explanations (Raven Reference Raven2015).Footnote 2 Explanations of the form ‘A explains B’ are backed by facts of the form [A grounds B].Footnote 3 Still, the backing relation has not received much attention in the literature. The aim of this paper is to provide an informative definition of backing.

Why is this important? First, the backing-locution appears in many contexts other than the grounding literature. For example, causal or constitutive explanations are said to be backed in an analogous manner but, again, backing-talk is left unspecified.Footnote 4 Providing a unified account of backing would allow us to make sense of backing-talk across many different contexts. Secondly, separatists are at a disadvantage in comparison to unionists when they cannot specify what backing-talk is supposed to designate. If we expect to do any sort of progress vis-à-vis the unionism/separatism debate, we should know more about what backing is supposed to be.Footnote 5 Finally, a definition of backing might be important for functionalist theories of grounding. Such theories do not define grounding in terms of their first-order formal features but in terms of their functional role. The most obvious role that grounding relations can play is their ability to back noncausal explanations (Rettler Reference Rettler2017). A primitive or unspecified notion of backing would count significantly against such views.

In section 2, I propose and motivate some constraints about the nature of backing. In section 3 and 4, I examine two prominent proposals: backing as explaining (B=E) and backing as grounding (B=G). In short, I argue that both (B=E) and (B=G) generate more questions than they answer. In section 5, I put forward my own proposal. Briefly, I argue that under plausible assumptions about the role of backing and the nature of explanation, backing should be understood as truthmaking, minimally construed. Finally, I tackle some objections.

2. Platitudes about backing

Separatism is the view that explanations are separate from the facts that make them obtain. In this sense, separatism is a minimal thesis (although some of its versions might be more plausible than others).Footnote 6 Still, since the focus of this paper is the backing relation that obtains between these two separated entities, I will bring up plausible features of separatism that are relevant to my discussion when appropriate.

In this section, I will propose a functional definition of backing based on minimal assumptions about its nature. Then, I will clarify and motivate these features, thus showing that they can act as prior constraints for any proposed theory of backing. The functional characterization I want to propose is the following:

(Functional) [A grounds B] (G) backs ‘A explains B’ (E), iff, there is a relation R with the following features:

  1. (1) R holds nontrivially between G and E,

  2. (2) R is cross-categorical, and,

  3. (3) R’s obtaining (at least partially) makes it the case that E’s success conditions are met.

A couple of specifications are in order. First, the nontriviality clause makes sure that relations such as ‘being in the same world as’ do not come out as backing relations. Secondly, the success conditions of an explanation are those conditions that, once they are met, necessitate that the explanation is successful. When a grounding-fact backs an explanation, then that fact contributes to the satisfaction of the success conditions of that explanation.Footnote 7 Thirdly, this characterization involves grounding-facts but there is no reason to think that it cannot be extended to other kinds of facts as well.Footnote 8 I begin my discussion by focusing on grounding since backing has received attention primarily in the context of grounding (Raven Reference Raven2015; Schaffer Reference Schaffer2016). Even though, as mentioned, the backing-locution can also be found in other domains, it is fair to expect that the main source of my audience are people interested in grounding.Footnote 9 Finally, I take backing to be cross-categorical in the sense that backers (in this case, grounding-facts) are different in kind from the explanations they back. This is perhaps the most contentious proposed feature of backing and for this reason it requires further discussion.

Why think that backing is cross-categorical? First, I take cross-categoricity to be a default feature of backing. Taking at face value the way the term backing is used in the literature entails that backing is cross-categorical. Grounding-facts are taken to be worldly and broadly stance independent, whereas explanations are about such facts (thus, representational in character). This is particularly salient if one considers the relation between causal events and the explanations which they back. As Schaffer (Reference Schaffer2016, 36) puts it:

[O]ne wants to distinguish between causation—a concrete relation in the world—and causal explanation—an abstract pattern over facts or sentences. And one wants to connect these notions by allowing causal relations in the world to back causal explanations among facts or sentences. Or so orthodoxy has it, and so I take for granted here.

Secondly, it is independently plausible that explanations are ontologically different from their backers. Consider causation again. Causal explanations are apt to pragmatic/epistemic constraints whereas the causal relation itself typically is not.Footnote 10 To compare, separatists about grounding make analogous remarks (Sjölin Wirling Reference Sjölin Wirling2020, 2–3). In this sense, it is no accident that separatists about grounding model their view according to the relation between causation and causal explanation.

There are ways to resist the cross-categoricity of backing. Sjölin Wirling (Reference Sjölin Wirling2020, 4, 5, 6), in an interesting move, argues that explanations are not the proper kind of relatum for the backing relation. Rather, she argues, a grounding-fact like [A grounds B] backs the fact that ‘A explains B’ is an explanation. In other words, backers back the explanatoriness of that which represents them. In this sense, backing is not cross-categorical since both of its relata are facts.

It could be argued that one can translate explanation-talk into fact-talk: saying ‘a grounding-fact G backs an explanation E’ can be translated into ‘G backs the fact that E is an explanation.’ But it is unclear if one should do so. First, translating talk of one ontological category to another does not come for free. To compare, consider operator-based views of grounding being translated into relational-talk. This is certainly possible, but one would need to make some substantive ontological assumptions along the way (i.e., countenancing a relation of grounding). In this sense, it is unclear if the results of such translation procedures can be trusted. More importantly, it seems to me that the explanation ‘A explains B’ and the fact that ‘A explains B’ is an explanation are importantly different entities. The former is an explanation, whereas the latter is a fact about that explanation. To my mind, backing concerns the former.

Identifying the facts that determine the fact that ‘A explains B’ is an explanation is an interesting (albeit different) question. There are two versions of this question. The first reading concerns the fact that ‘A explains B’ is a successful explanation (Sjölin Wirling [Reference Sjölin Wirling2020, 4] seems to adopt this reading). But this fact is not “backed” in the original sense. Rather, it holds in virtue of the fact that ‘A explains B’ is fully backed (in the sense that its success conditions are fully met). The second reading concerns the fact that ‘A explains B’ is an explanation (successful or not). I cannot settle this question here, but I am inclined to think that facts about the explanatoriness of a putative explanation are grounded in certain of its structural features. For example, on Kim’s proposal (Reference Kim1994), explanations are propositions that have three “slots”: one for the explanans (or explanantia), one for the explanandum, and one for the determination-relation that connects the underlying phenomena (more on this later). At any rate, I take the question concerning the nature of the relations that are involved in these two readings to be an open question (and distinct from the issue concerning the nature of backing).

Finally, it could be argued that even if Sjölin Wirling is wrong about the exact details of the explanation-relatum, backing is still monocategorical in the following sense (bracketing translatability worries): backing could be the relation between the fact that A grounds B and the fact that A explains B. Footnote 11

I have the following response. The cross-categoricity of backing should be understood in a general, nonfetishistic, way. A relation is cross-categorical when it relates entities that are importantly different from one another, even if those entities belong (strictly speaking) to the same ontological category. As noted, grounding relations are worldly items whereas explanations are representational entities about those items. In this sense, even if explanations are facts, the kinds of facts that they are differ significantly from the kinds of facts that grounding-facts are.Footnote 12

2.a On the nature of explanations

(Functional) in its current state is nontrivial but not very informative. Its content will become more determined once we answer the following question: What sort of entity is an explanation? There are two plausible types of answers to this question. The first view takes explanations to be vessels that report or represent determination-facts. For example, some take explanations to be arguments (Kitcher Reference Kitcher, Kitcher and Salmon1989) or sets of propositions (Kim Reference Kim1994). Alternatively, according to the so-called ontic conception, explanations are determination-facts themselves. In this sense, explanations are (quite literally) discovered in the same way causal events are discovered.Footnote 13

The ontic conception cannot accommodate the cross-categoricity of backing and is incompatible with separatism. According to the ontic view, the explanation of B in terms of A is identical to a fact like A grounds B. If explanations just are determination-facts, then there is nothing separating them from those very determination-facts. So, it seems that the ontic view is a unionist-friendly account. Instead, the thesis that we should plug in to (Functional) to get a more substantive account is the one that identifies explanations with vessels that have some sort of representational or reporting capacity.Footnote 14

Simply saying that explanations are vessels that report determination-facts does not get us very far since this idea can be cashed out in many different ways. For example, explanations could be arguments, sets of propositions, models, or something along those lines. Still, I think there is a way forward by taking explanations to be sets of propositions. This is not a costly assumption. For one, it is not clear that the competitors of such a view have anything more to offer in terms of features. The only contestable feature I can think of concerns the datum that many explanations are complex. The view that takes explanations to be arguments can accommodate this datum rather naturally. An argument can have many different premises each capturing a different kind of explanans: singular causes, background conditions, laws of nature, etc. But I see no reason why the explanations-as-propositions view cannot deliver the same result. Propositions can be complex or structured too.

3. Backing as explaining

So, what would the relation between an explanation and its backer be? The first proposal I will examine has been advanced by Kovacs (Reference Kovacs2017, 2934; Reference Kovacs2019a, 6) who identifies “backing” with “explaining”:

(B=E) [A grounds B] backs ‘A explains B,’ iff, [A grounds B] explains ‘A explains B.”Footnote 15

For example, according to (B=E), an explanation of a specific mental state in virtue of a brain state is explained by the fact that the latter grounds the former.

I have two worries against this proposal. The first worry concerns the cross-categoricity of backing. As mentioned, the grounding separatist view does not simply claim that explanations are distinct from their corresponding grounding-facts. Specifically, the claim is that explanations are separate from grounding-facts and different in kind. But (B=E) cannot accommodate this datum. I take it that the explanation-relation obtains between the explanandum and the relevant explanans (or explanantia). In this sense, every theory of explanation takes explanations to relate the same kind of entities. As mentioned, some views take explanations to be arguments: explanantia and explananda are both propositions or sets of sentences (Kitcher Reference Kitcher, Kitcher and Salmon1989). Others take the explanation-relation to be a connective: explanantia and explananda are nonreified, linguistic, entities (Schnieder Reference Schnieder2010).Footnote 16 Or, perhaps, explanations are relations between worldly items as per the so-called ontic conception of explanation.Footnote 17 No theory of explanation, which I know of, takes (or can take) the explanation-relation to be cross-categorical.Footnote 18

My second worry against (B=E) appeals to a particular version of the separatist view. If the separatist view is that every successful explanation is backed, and if to be backed is to be explained, then we get the following thesis:

(Explanation Maximalism) Every successful explanation is explained.

But (Explanation Maximalism) leads to a regress since it requires the existence of an infinite series of explanations.

The proponent of (B=E) might respond by saying that the resulting regress is benign. But this move does not come cheap. First, it is not that clear what counts as a vicious regress. Some believe that vicious regresses are regresses that have some specific structural feature. Others disagree and take viciousness to be context relative. So, it seems that in order for the proponent of (B=E) to claim that the relevant regress is benign, additional (and controversial) assumptions about the nature of regresses must be made.Footnote 19 Secondly, even if we accept that (Explanation Maximalism) leads to a benign regress, it is still the case that (B=E) has to countenance a regress. And even benign regresses have implications for one’s ontology. Specifically, (Explanation Maximalism) leads to the existence of infinite explanations. This is still a cost for (B=E).Footnote 20

The obvious move for the proponent of (B=E) would be to reject (Explanation Maximalism) and claim that only some successful explanations are explained. Such a view is entailed by the weaker separatist view that only some successful explanations are backed. This move avoids the regress worry. It does so, however, at a significant cost. Again, more questions are raised. Which explanations are not backed? And (once we identify them), why is it the case that these explanations are as such that they do not require a backer? Again, I take these questions to not have obvious or easy answers.Footnote 21

Finally, and perhaps more importantly, accepting that only some explanations are explained requires the existence of successful but unbacked (or bare) explanations (bare explanations, henceforth). Bareness should be distinguished from fundamentality. An explanation can be fundamental but still backed in the sense that it holds in virtue of a fundamental fact. Bare explanations, on the other hand, are “naked”: they do not hold in virtue of anything else. Some successful explanations would have to be unbacked for the regress worry to be avoided.

Bare explanations are controversial in themselves but, more importantly, they seem to be in tension with separatism. This is a significant cost for (B=E). Separatism wants to capture the intuition that successful explanations are higher-order, macro, phenomena that do not “float-free.” Bare explanations go against this intuition. To be clear, I am not claiming that the existence of bare explanations is incompatible with separatism. If separatism is construed minimally as the thesis that explanations are separate from their backers, then bare explanations do not pose a threat (bracketing their controversial nature). My point is that positing successful unbacked explanations is in tension with a philosophically attractive version of separatism. Such a view would say that every successful explanation is backed, in the same way physicalists say that every state is nothing over and above a physical state. In this sense, proponents of (B=E) who wish to argue that only some successful explanations are explained need to adopt an unattractive version of separatism.Footnote 22

4. Backing as grounding

The natural alternative to (B=E) is the view that backing is a form of grounding. As previously noted, explanations hold in virtue of the facts that back them. Since in-virtue-of talk and priority-talk are often taken to be indicators for the existence of grounding relations, backing-as-grounding is a view that deserves consideration:

(B=G) [A grounds B] backs ‘A explains B,’ iff, [A grounds B] grounds ‘A explains B.’

Saying that the explanation of a mental state in terms of its corresponding brain state is backed by the relevant grounding-fact means that the former is grounded by the latter. Still, the proponent of (B=G) needs to do a lot of additional work in order to make (B=G) an illuminating definition of backing.

Before critically evaluating (B=G), I should make the following clarification. The most developed version of (B=G) has been recently proposed by Sjölin Wirling (Reference Sjölin Wirling2020).Footnote 23 However, her account is different from my understanding of (B=G) in two ways. First, as already noted, she takes backing to relate facts of the form [A grounds B] with facts concerning the explanatoriness of the proposition ‘A explains B.’ Secondly, she defines backing as partial grounding.

I have addressed the first point in section 2. Concerning the second point, I agree with Sjölin Wirling that if backing is a form of grounding, then grounding-facts partially ground their corresponding explanations.Footnote 24 It is plausible that for an explanation’s success conditions to be fulfilled certain epistemic/pragmatic conditions should also be in place (in addition to the relevant grounding-facts). But I see no reason to insist that the first relatum of backing should always be a grounding-fact. In this sense, these epistemic/pragmatic conditions would also be partial grounds. And such conditions together with the relevant grounding-fact would fully ground the relevant explanation. In this sense, backing can’t be defined as partial grounding since there are clear instances of backing being underwritten by full grounding relations (i.e., the ones involving the conjunction of a grounding-fact with its appropriate epistemic/pragmatic conditions).Footnote 25

That being said, I take these two differences to not be particularly important. The core of Sjölin Wirling’s theory (i.e., that backing is a form of grounding) is independent from these auxiliary assumptions and deserves serious consideration. Also, as it will become apparent, the challenges I will raise against (B=G) also apply to Sjölin Wirling’s specific view. For this reason, my focus on (B=G) is dialectically acceptable.

Appeals to grounding can be understood in many ways. I will divide them into two groups: reductive and nonreductive accounts. The nonreductive view takes grounding to be primitive (Audi Reference Audi2012). Proponents of this view argue that grounding resists analysis but is still a valuable metaphysical tool. Perhaps the most important merit of this view is that it can accommodate the thesis that every successful explanation is backed without generating a regress. The resulting picture would simply be the view that every successful explanation is grounded.

Still, nonreductive versions of (B=G) have an important shortcoming: they are uninformative. First, if grounding is primitive and backing is a form of grounding, then (B=G) simply collapses to the view that backing is ultimately unanalyzable.Footnote 26 In this sense, it simply is not illuminating enough to say that backing is a form of grounding. Instead, we should prefer views which reduce backing to more familiar phenomena. Secondly, the grounding literature is still relatively young in comparison to other literatures. This unsurprisingly leads to a lack of consensus concerning many of the features of grounding (cf. Rodriguez-Pereyra Reference Rodriguez-Pereyra2015). In this sense, it would be better to appeal to a less controversial entity when we wish to define backing.

At this point it could be objected that, for separatists, the existence of grounding is already assumed. In this sense, separatists would not take grounding to be unfamiliar. This is certainly true for some separatists. But, as noted in section 1, backing is a phenomenon that appears in other domains as well (e.g., causal explanation). One needn’t believe in the existence of grounding in order to be a separatist. In this sense, a separatist about causal explanation who is also a grounding-skeptic would find (B=G) unconvincing.

Finally, another way to illustrate the fact that (B=G) is uninformative is by considering that a characterization of grounding in terms of backing would be explanatorily underwhelming.Footnote 27 Even if one does not aim to define grounding in terms of its backing role toward explanation, it would be nice to be able to characterize grounding in terms of its function. Grounding is the relation that, among other things, backs explanations. If backing is a form of grounding, then that way of illuminating grounding would not be available anymore.

I should note that I agree with Sjölin Wirling (Reference Sjölin Wirling2020, 7) that a circular characterization of grounding is permissible. She presents the following case: the property of being a blood relative is realized by the property of parenthood. But it is plausible that in characterizing blood relatedness, one would refer to the property of parenthood. Indeed, it would not “obstruct understanding” (Sjölin Wirling [Reference Sjölin Wirling2020, 7]; my emphasis) to say that grounding is that which grounds certain kinds of explanations. My weaker point is that it would be desirable to be able to illuminate grounding in this additional way (i.e., by appealing to its function to back explanations). In this sense, a characterization of grounding in terms of backing qua grounding would be uninformative (albeit, possible).

What about reductive versions of grounding? A promising way of reducing grounding is by appealing to the set of, what Wilson calls, “small-g” relations (Reference Wilson2014). A small-g relation is, roughly, a determination relation that has a very similar profile to grounding. For example, the relation of constitution is also said to capture priority-talk and is also taken to be explanatory.

A reductive account of grounding in terms of small-g relations can be articulated in two ways. The first one would be to say that backing is a form of grounding and grounding is multiply realizable by different small-g relations (J. Wilson Reference Wilson2014, 567-8; Rettler Reference Rettler2017). In this sense, backing would be identical to the realized entity which would entail that backing itself is multiply realizable by small-g relations.Footnote 28 This option is very implausible. Many paradigmatic small-g relations are not plausible realizers of backing (e.g., set-formation).

A more promising way of understanding backing as a kind of reduced grounding is by taking backing to be identical to one of the (potentially many) realizers of grounding. In this sense, (B=G) would be the view that backing is identical to some small-g relation. Still, it is impossible to assess this proposal without specifying which small-g relation backing is supposed to be. For this reason, (B=G) is unilluminating and, at best, only the first step toward an informative definition of backing.

5. Backing as truthmaking

In this section, I propose a new definition of backing. According to (Functional), the backing relation connects grounding-facts with explanations. Also, explanations, as mentioned in section 2, are certain kinds of propositions. But what kind of relation connects propositions with grounding-facts? A very plausible candidate for this role is the truthmaking relation.

(B=T) [A grounds B] backs ‘A explains B,’ iff, ‘A explains B’ is made true by [A grounds B].

(B=T) satisfies all three clauses of (Functional). It is a nontrivial and substantive issue whether a given worldly fact serves as a truthmaker for a proposition. Also, truthmaking is a cross-categorical relation par excellence (Tahko Reference Tahko and Calemi2016). Finally, it is plausible that in order for an explanation to be successful it is (at least) necessary for that explanation to be true.

What is the nature of the truthmaking relation? According to Armstrong’s (Reference Armstrong2004) classic picture, truthmaking is the internal relation of necessitation. As a quick example, take the following psychophysical explanation:

(M) The fact that Mary has mental state M1 is noncausally explained by the fact that Mary has brain state B1 and that a psychophysical law connecting M-type mental states with B-type brain states obtains.

What backs (M)? Plausibly, worldly facts such as the relevant psychophysical law partially grounding the fact that Mary has mental state M1. Adopting Armstrong’s account, this means that Mary’s brain state B1 together with the relevant psychophysical law necessitate the truth of (M). On the face of it this seems plausible. Of course, there are well known objections to the view that truthmaking is the relation of necessitation, which I am not going to rehearse here (MacBride Reference MacBride2020, sec. 1.2.). Thankfully, (B=T), on its own, takes no particular stance toward the specifics of the truthmaking relation. In this sense, I intend for my proposal to be minimal. Truthmaking, in this context, is supposed to designate whichever relation is posited by one’s background truthmaker theory.

Deferring to one’s background truthmaker theory is dialectically acceptable. Figuring out which truthmaker theory is the correct one is a substantive philosophical problem that requires our attention anyway, independently of the discussion around backing, grounding, and the separatism/unionism debate. In this sense, the fact that the final details of my proposal are “hostage” to one’s background truthmaker theory is not a significant cost.Footnote 29

The minimality of (B=T) is worth emphasizing in at least three additional ways. For one, nothing in (B=T) entails a robust notion of truthmakers. Opponents of truthmaker theory usually argue that one can make sense of truth being dependent on reality without having to posit separate entities called “truthmakers.” (B=T) is neutral toward this objection. One is free to adopt a thin understanding of truthmakers according to which such entities are not separate and distinct facts but are simply those bits of reality that account for the truth of the relevant proposition.Footnote 30

Secondly, there is an ongoing discussion about the level of grain of the truthmaking relation. For example, some opponents of the correspondence theory of truth argue that a robust understanding of correspondence (perhaps, as causal regulation) is explanatorily superfluous. Again, (B=T) is neutral toward this discussion. Following Armstrong, proponents of (B=T) can take the truthmaking relation to be an internal relation without reifying it by appealing to some external determination relation.

Thirdly, so far, I have been focusing on backing as a relation that holds between explanations and grounding-facts. But, as mentioned in section 2, there is no reason why backing should be constrained in this way. Truthmaking, as such, can be used to define diverse metaphysical theses (from antirealism to realism about a given domain). Analogously, an explanation could be backed by determination-facts (broadly construed), nomic facts, or facts about essences. But they could also be backed by facts which are not worldly, at least in the traditional sense. For example, it could turn out that explanations are true in virtue of the fact that they are appropriately related to other explanations. In a case like this, such explanations would be backed by the fact that they figure in an appropriately defined set of explanations.Footnote 31

Finally, (B=T) is more informative than both construals of (B=G) while staying minimal toward the details of the truthmaking relation itself and pluralistic concerning the different kinds of entities that can serve as truthmakers. In this sense, (B=T) could be compatible with (B=G) if one takes grounding to be reducible and truthmaking to be one of its realizers. Still, such assumptions are controversial, and I take it that (B=T) has merit independently of its connection to grounding. This is particularly evident if one considers that skepticism about truthmaking is, in general, more controversial (and less widespread) than skepticism about grounding. As mentioned, grounding is a relatively new metaphysical tool whereas my notion of truthmaking is minimal. Under these considerations, I take it that (B=T) should be the default view concerning the nature of the backing relation. In the following two sections, I consider two objections against my view.

6. The inheritance worry

Grounding theorists often appeal to the nature of explanation to justify the fact that grounding has certain formal features. Grounding is supposed to be irreflexive because explanation is irreflexive (grounding inherits its formal features from explanation) (Maurin Reference Maurin2019). However, it could be objected that (B=T) is implausible because the truthmaking relation (in any of its forms) cannot plausibly fulfill the inheritance function. Specifically, it is implausible that truthbearers have the same formal features as their truthmakers.

To illustrate, compare truthmaking to relations that plausibly do license inheritance claims. The identity relation is the most obvious example. If explanations are identical to grounding-facts, then it follows that they have the same formal features. A less trivial case can be found in the literature on mental causation. Some philosophers argue that mental states hold in virtue of brain states and, because of that, the causal profile of the latter is transmitted to the former.Footnote 32 But backing is neither the identity relation nor the relation that holds between minds and brains.

There are two ways in which (B=T) can be defended against this. The first strategy involves directly meeting the challenge by arguing that truthmaking can license inheritance claims. To that effect, it could be claimed that truthmaking should be understood as an isomorphic relation. More specifically, truthmaking could be isomorphic in the sense that truthbearers are structurally identical to their corresponding truthmakers. The proposition that the cat is on the mat involves a certain relation between its constituents that “mirrors” the structure of the fact that the cat is on the mat. If this is true, then those explanations that are backed plausibly share the same formal features with the grounding-facts that back them.

Against this move, it should be noted that knowing about the features of explanation cannot tell us anything about grounding-facts that do not serve as truthmakers. Looking into the features of explanation (asymmetry, irreflexivity, etc.) can only serve to illuminate the features of those (and only those) grounding-facts which back explanations. In this sense, even if one assumes that truthmaking is isomorphic, this at best provides only limited access to the inner workings of grounding. Also, the very claim that truthmaking is isomorphic is far from obviously true (Schipper Reference Schipper2020).

So far, I have been mostly focusing on how explanations relate to their corresponding grounding or determination-facts. But, as previously mentioned, there is no good reason to restrict backing in this way. Backing is supposed to be the relation that connects explanations with whichever entity makes them true. Assuming isomorphism would beg the question against views that allow for successful explanations to be true but cash out their success holistically (to mention one example). Such views would say that an explanation of the form ‘A explains B’ is not made true by a grounding-fact of the form [A grounds B] but by a plurality of different facts that bear no isomorphic relation to the original explanation.

My preferred strategy involves denying that we should expect to find out about the nature of grounding by looking at the explanations which grounding-facts back. Grounding should be examined in the same way every other phenomenon is examined: by hypothesizing and testing such hypotheses against a background of a well-established body of beliefs. The analogy with causation is helpful at this point.Footnote 33 It is uncontroversial that there are causal events which are not explanatory. Still, there are other ways in which philosophers have proceeded to learn about the nature of causation. Being able to back causal explanations is one of the roles that causal relations have. Other roles include, for example, figuring in our best scientific and folk theories. Philosophers, based on certain folk and scientific platitudes about causation, propose certain hypotheses about what the causal relation really is (e.g., counterfactual dependence, energy transfer, etc.). At best, looking into the nature of causal explanations can be one of the many ways in which we can uncover the true nature of causation.

7. The regress worry

Recall that one of my worries against (B=E) was that given (Explanation Maximalism), a regress is generated. (B=T) is supposed to avoid this worry. But it could be plausibly argued that (B=T) also leads to a regress if one takes truthmaking to be an explanatory relation. If truthmaking is explanatory, then (B=T) seems to collapse into (B=E). A way to raise this worry is to take truthmaking to be a form of grounding and then take grounding to be explanatory. But the objector does not even need to make this move.Footnote 34 The link between truthmaking and explanation is usually highlighted in the relevant literature, so I take the claim that truthmaking is explanatory to be well-motivated independently of whether it is a grounding relation.

What does it mean to say that truthmaking is explanatory? Asay (Reference Asay2017, 10) identifies two possible answers: either truthmaking is itself an instance of the explanation-relation or explanation is simply a constraint on truthmaking (i.e., P makes <P> true only if P explains <P>). The first option is a form of unionism about truthmaking whereas the second is a form of separatism about truthmaking.

Ruling out the first option seems fairly easy. It is simply bizarre to be a separatist about grounding and a unionist about truthmaking. Even if one does not take truthmaking to be a form of grounding, it could still be argued that the two notions are similar enough. So, separatism can be motivated for both relations on similar grounds.

Is grounding similar to truthmaking? It is not obvious that it is. As previously mentioned, it is controversial that truthmaking is a form of grounding. Perhaps, as Audi (Reference Audi2019) notes, truthmaking is not a grounding relation because it should not be understood as a determination relation. But if that’s the case, then the putative similarity between the two relations becomes thin. Against this, I propose that separatism about both grounding and truthmaking should be motivated differently. Rather, separatism is primarily a view about explanation. Successful explanations are certain kinds of propositions which do not float free. So, insofar as one is a separatist about explanations involving grounding one should also be a separatist about explanations involving truthmaking. In other words, separatism about grounding and truthmaking are simply instances of separatism simpliciter.

The second option is trickier. According to this form of separatism, truthmaking and explanation are distinct, but every truthmaking-fact ([P makes <P> true]) has a corresponding explanation (<P explains <P>>). This version of separatism is different from the kind of separatism I have been considering so far (call my version, standard separatism). An important and desirable feature of standard separatism is that grounding-facts can exist in the absence of explanation. In an analogous sense, separatism about truthmaking should allow for certain truthmaking-facts to exist in the absence of a corresponding explanation. Does this compromise the well-established link between truthmaking and explanation? It does not. It can still be said that truthmaking is explanatory even if it is not the case that every truthmaking-fact figures into an explanation. Causation is also explanatory by anyone’s lights even though there are clear cases of causal events which are not involved in causal explanation.

Still, one could wonder whether standard versions of separatism coupled with (B=T) can successfully deal with the regress worry. Can truthmaking-facts exist in the absence of explanation? In essence, the answer to this question depends on one’s view about the ontological status of explanations (i.e., the ontological status of propositions). According to one influential view, propositions are reified abstracta that are expressed by particular sentences. Such views take explanations to be stance independent in the sense that explanations exist independently of whether they are expressed or conceived by agents. But if that’s the case, then the regress worry looms large again. Every truthmaking-fact would have a real, stance independent, corresponding explanation. Such truthmaking-facts (e.g., the fact that [P makes <P> true] makes <P explains <P>> true) would, in turn, have their own corresponding explanations, and so on ad infinitum. So, it seems that (B=T) faces the same worry as (B=E) in terms of generating regresses.

One thing to immediately notice is that even if we accept that (B=T) generates a regress, the kind of regress it generates is significantly different from the one (B=E) generates. (B=E) coupled with the thesis that every explanation is backed entails that every explanation is explained. This means that if an explanation exists, then an infinite series of explanations is generated. Under closer inspection, this is a regress that runs “downward.” A second-order explanation is more “fundamental” than the explanation it explains (in the sense that first-order explanations depend on second-order explanation, second-order explanations depend on third-order explanations, and so on ad infinitum). This means that the infinite regress (B=E) generates runs toward the fundamental level. (B=T), on the other hand, leads to an “upward” regress. In this case, the first element of the series is a truthmaking-fact which, in turn, gives rise to another truthmaking-fact, and so on ad infinitum. This means that the order of dependence goes from a truthmaking-fact (of the form [P makes <P> true]) toward its corresponding “meta” truthmaking-fact (of the form [[P makes <P> true] makes <P makes <P> true> true]). This is a significant difference because upward regresses are generally regarded as less problematic than downward regresses (Cameron Reference Cameron2008).

Still, it should be noted that there is a way for the separatist to deny that (B=T) generates a regress altogether. Specifically, the separatist should deny that propositions exist stance independently.Footnote 35 Notice that if the existence of explanations directly depends on the deliberation of conscious agents, then there will not be an infinite series of explanations unless an agent can generate one. If a truthmaking-fact makes its corresponding explanation true, this presupposes that that explanation exists. The demand for a truthmaker arises only once the relevant proposition is formed. But according to the view I am considering, whether an explanation is formed depends on the relevant agents and their explanatory demands. To compare, (B=E) faces a regress worry that cannot be avoided using similar means. It is independently plausible that every successful explanation requires a backer. (B=T) can meet that demand: explanations, insofar as they are formed, require truthmakers. Rather, the proponent of (B=T) should deny the converse thesis, namely, that every truthmaker has a corresponding explanation.Footnote 36

I do not have the space to fully defend a stance-dependent view about the existence of propositions. Still, it suffices to say that such a view is both powerful and already assumed by many philosophers working on explanation. Kim (Reference Kim1988), for example, adopts a view of propositions akin to contemporary conceptualist theories (i.e., propositions as abstractions of mental tokenings) (King Reference King2007).Footnote 37 The alternative would be to understand propositions as entities whose existence-conditions are completely independent of human agency. But such views are notorious for their inability to explain how they get their truth-conditions and their representational capacities. In comparison, the agent-dependent view has a clear-cut explanation: propositions get their truth-conditions and their ability to represent in virtue of the capacities of conscious agents.

There are ways to resist these points, but it should be noted that whichever way the relevant dialectic plays out, at least as far as regresses are concerned, (B=T) is superior to (B=E). If (B=T) generates a regress, then it is a regress that is more palatable than the one (B=E) generates. Finally, I have highlighted a plausible, albeit not completely nonparochial, way for the proponent of standard separatism to completely bypass the regress worry.

A final point about (B=T) and regresses. I have argued that (B=E) leads to a downward regress, whereas (B=T) leads to an upward one. But it could be argued that (B=T) leads to a downward regress as well. After all, we can still ask: What explains why [A grounds B] makes ‘A explains B’ true? And, then, we can ask what explains that further truthmaking-fact ad infinitum. In this sense, (B=T) might not be superior to (B=E) in that regard after all.

Note that in order for (B=T) to generate a regress in the above sense, (B=T) needs to be coupled with the two following triggering statements:Footnote 38

  1. (1) Every truthmaking-fact has a ground.

  2. (2) Every grounding-fact involving a truthmaking-fact (of the form “P grounds the fact that Q makes <Q> true”) has a corresponding explanation (of the form “P explains the fact that Q makes <Q> true”).

Both statements can be contested. (2) presumably follows from the principle that determination-facts always have explanations which they back. But I have already indicated that an attractive version of separatism would want to accept the possibility of determination-facts occurring in the absence of explanation. I also proposed a plausible way to deliver this result by taking propositions to be stance-independent entities.

(1) can also be resisted. Even if some truthmaking-facts have grounds, it is not obvious that this should apply to every truthmaking-fact. For all we know, some truthmaking-facts might be brute or fundamental. Perhaps (1) can be motivated by appealing to a principle of sufficient reason according to which everything has a ground. Compare with (B=E). The triggering statement that (B=E) needs to be coupled with is, as noted, simply a plausible version of separatism: “Every successful explanation is backed.” But, surely, that principle is much less controversial than the principle that everything has a ground.

Separatism coupled with (B=T) entails that every successful explanation has a truthmaker, whereas separatism coupled with (B=E) entails that every successful explanation needs to be explained (which results in a regress). For this reason, the downward regress problem is avoided by (B=T) and is particularly pressing for the proponent of (B=E).Footnote 39

8. Conclusion

The aim of this paper is to argue that instances of backing are instances of truthmaking. I examined and rejected two prominent proposals: backing as explaining and backing as grounding. Then I proposed that backing should be understood as an instance of truthmaking. I also understood truthmaking minimally. Finally, I responded to two objections against my proposal: the inheritance worry and the regress worry.

Acknowledgments

Earlier versions of this paper have been presented at the Metaphysical Explanation III workshop (Lund University), at the Centre for Metaphysics and Mind (University of Leeds), and at the Explaining Philosophy conference (Wuhan University). I am very grateful to the participants of these events. For extremely substantive and detailed written comments, I would like to thank: Pekka Väyrynen, Jack Woods, Anna-Sofia Maurin (my commentator at Lund), Arthur Carlyle, Pei-Lung Cheng, Zak Gudmunsen, Olof Leffler (special thanks to Adina Covaci for her comments and for organizing the relevant work-in-progress session where I presented my paper). I have also greatly benefited from discussions on the topic of explanation with David Heering, Yorgos Karagiannopoulos, and Sotiris Paraskevopoulos. Finally, I would like to thank two anonymous referees for this journal. Both reviewers read my paper carefully, understood it, and provided comments that significantly improved it. I appreciate their work and their help with this project.

Funding statement

Research on this paper was funded by the Onassis Foundation (grant no. F ZN 056-1/2017-2018), whose support is gratefully acknowledged.

Alexios Stamatiadis-Bréhier is a LAHRI postdoctoral researcher at the University of Leeds, UK. His main area of specialization is moral metaphysics. He also has interests in the philosophy of science and moral metasemantics.

Footnotes

1 These explanations are usually called metaphysical explanations (Fine Reference Fine, Correia and Schnieder2012). Spelling out the nature of metaphysical explanations is hard and a matter of ongoing discussion (see, e.g., A. Wilson Reference Wilson, Glick, Darby and Marmodoro2020). In the context of this paper, I will treat metaphysical explanations as species of noncausal explanations (perhaps they are noncausal explanations that are of some particular interest to metaphysicians). I will also take ‘explanation’ to refer to noncausal explanation unless stated otherwise.

2 Proponents of separatism include Schaffer (Reference Schaffer2016) and J. Wilson (Reference Wilson2016). On the unionist camp we could include Rosen (Reference Rosen, Hale and Hoffmann2010), Fine (Reference Fine, Correia and Schnieder2012), and Litland (Reference Litland2018a) (still, see fn. 5).

3 For readability, I assume that grounding and explanation-claims involve one-to-one relations. This is unusual. Most grounding theorists take the grounding relation to be many-to-one (Bliss and Trogdon Reference Bliss and Trogdon2016) (cf. Litland Reference Litland2016).

4 See e.g., Kim (Reference Kim1988, 226; 1994, 58, 60, 67), Ruben (Reference Ruben1990, 232), Glennan (Reference Glennan2002, 342).

5 Two clarifications. First, I do not wish to imply that an informative definition of backing would settle the debate. It could be that there are independent reasons for why someone should be a separatist (Maurin Reference Maurin2019, 20). Still, the question about the nature of backing plays a significant dialectical role in the relevant debate (see, e.g., Wallner [Reference Wallner2021, 3]). Secondly, I am also assuming that the separatism/unionism debate is a substantial one. For the view that the debate is largely verbal see Dasgupta (Reference Dasgupta2017, 94 fn. 8), Skiles and Trogdon (Reference Skiles, Trogdon, Stenwall and Wahlberg2019, 160), and Kovacs (Reference Kovacs2019a, 4). Note that if it turns out that unionists also need to countenance a backing relation, then they would also need to provide an account of backing.

6 Sjölin Wirling (Reference Sjölin Wirling2020, 2–3) takes separatism to be primarily driven by the idea that explanation necessarily involves some epistemic or pragmatic dimension. But unionists also recognize that feature and actively try to accommodate it, either by adopting some nonmonotonicity clause or by countenancing multiple (often primitive) grounding relations (e.g., Litland Reference Litland2018b).

7 Of course, I do not need to commit to the view that a given grounding-fact is sufficient for the relevant success conditions to be fully met. Perhaps, there are facts other than grounding-facts (e.g., pragmatic/epistemic facts as per Sjölin Wirling [Reference Sjölin Wirling2020, 2–3, 5]), which are also necessary. Or, it could be that grounding-facts are sufficient on their own given that the relevant pragmatic/epistemic conditions are built into the relevant grounding-fact (e.g., by taking grounding to be a quaternary relation ranging over contrast classes).

8 The standard view is that explanations are backed by determination-facts (broadly construed) (see Taylor [Reference Taylor2018]). But there might be other ways to back an explanation. For example, Lange (Reference Lange2016) claims that some explanations are distinctively modal (in cases were the explanandum holds with a weaker modality than the explanans). Glazier (Reference Glazier and Raven2020) also mentions explanations backed by nomic facts. Kovacs (Reference Kovacs2019a, sec. 4.3; Reference Kovacs2019b) argues that noncausal explanations are backed holistically. deRosset (Reference deRosset2013, 12) takes explanations to be backed by arguments. Taylor (Reference Taylor2020) has also argued that there is room for an antirealist version of backing.

9 I will transition to a more generalized conception of separatism when dialectically appropriate (e.g., secs. 4, 5, 7; see also fn. 8).

10 The point that causal explanation and causation are significantly different kinds of entities goes all the way back to Davidson (Reference Davidson1967). Still, there are unorthodox exceptions (cf. Kim Reference Kim1981).

11 It could be suggested that given that grounding and explanation typically relate facts, we can infer that backing relates facts. I have two responses. First, this inference can be doubted: backing doesn’t relate the relata of a given explanation but that explanation as a whole. To compare, explanations might relate propositions, but it doesn’t follow that explanations are propositions themselves. They could, for example, be arguments as per Hempel (Reference Hempel1965). Secondly, we should resist the claim that explanation relates facts. Bracketing controversial views, standard accounts in the literature take the relevant relata of explanation to be sets of interpreted sentences (Kitcher Reference Kitcher, Kitcher and Salmon1989) or constituents of propositions (Kim Reference Kim1994). The so-called ontic view of explanation might be a plausible candidate for the view that the relata of the explanation-relation are facts (in saying this, I assume that such facts would be worldly in the same way the typical relata of the grounding relation are). Still, as it will become apparent, the ontic view is incompatible with separatism (see sec. 2.a).

12 To compare, the monocategoricity of explanation goes beyond the sameness in the ontological category of its relata. Take the classic Hempel view (Reference Hempel1965) according to which an explanation is a relation between a set of sentences involving reference to a law of nature, and a sentence having a nomologically expected state as its content. Both relata occupy the same ontological category, while also being importantly similar: they both have a representational function vis-à-vis the phenomenon under examination.

13 Conceptions of explanations should be distinguished from theories of explanation (Bokulich Reference Bokulich2016, 263; Wright and van Eck Reference Wright and van Eck2018, 998). Theories propose a model of how explanations are supposed to work (e.g., law-based theories, à la Hempel, take reference to laws to be a constitutive feature of explanations). Conceptions, on the other hand, concern the metaphysics of explanations (i.e., what explanations are in the most literal sense). For interpretative issues see Craver (Reference Craver2019).

14 For this reason, we can reject Glazier’s (Reference Glazier and Raven2020, 125) recent proposal that backing is a version of the part-whole relation. If explanations were themselves worldly facts, then it could (perhaps) be said that an instance of a determination relation literally composes an explanation. But this view does not seem to deliver the right results once one understands explanations as vessels that report. It is a category mistake to claim that instances of determination-relations are literally proper parts of the entities that represent them.

15 Kovacs cites Rodriguez-Pereyra (Reference Rodriguez-Pereyra, Beebee and Dodd2005, 28) and Schnieder (Reference Schnieder2010, 326–28) as others who share this view. But it is not so clear from these passages that they do. Rodriguez-Pereyra (Reference Rodriguez-Pereyra, Beebee and Dodd2005, 18) takes explanations to be truth-apt and backing to be a form of primitive grounding. But primitive grounding is arguably distinct from the explanation-relation unless one is a unionist about grounding in this latter instance (which is bizarre and unmotivated). Similarly, Schnieder’s view is that backing is grounding, but grounding is construed as a connective and not as a reified relation (Reference Schnieder2010, 327; see also MacBride [Reference MacBride2020, sec. 3.5]). I consider backing-as-grounding in the next section.

16 One might worry that some representational accounts of explanation are cross-categorical. For example, a model of some phenomenon (a representation) would, presumably, explain that very phenomenon (a worldly entity). This is false. A model involves an explanandum and some explanantia in the same way an explanatory proposition or an explanatory argument does. In this sense, the explanation relation obtains between those entities (which, in turn, are literally components of that model); not between the explanation and the phenomenon itself.

17 I addressed the ontic conception in the previous section.

18 Sjölin Wirling (Reference Sjölin Wirling2020, 7) prefers an interpretation of (B=E) according to which the relevant ‘is’ is not the ‘is’ of identity. Rather, the slogan “backing is explanation” should be read elliptically as the claim that the backing relation is explanatory. But this, in turn, is compatible with the claim that such explanations are underwritten by some other relation (with which backing would be identical). I agree that the explanatoriness of backing can be cashed out in this way (I return to this point in section 7). But Kovacs’s view is that backing is literally the explanation-relation. After all, this is what allows him to respond to one version of the meta-grounding problem (i.e., the problem of what explains facts of the form: [A explains B]) in a new and interesting way (Reference Kovacs2019a, sec. 4.3.).

19 The most straightforward way of doing this would involve claiming that a regress is benign in virtue of its objective features and showing that (Explanation Maximalism) leads to a regress with such features. Alternatively, one could adopt a context-relative account of benign regresses and claim that (Explanation Maximalism) leads to a benign regress in the relevant contexts. For example, Maurin (Reference Maurin, Svennerlind, Almäng and Ingthorsson2013) argues that a series is vicious insofar as the task that that series was supposed to fulfil isn’t met. So, now the question arises: what kind of task is a second-order explanation supposed to fulfill? Again, this indicates that, either way, the proponent of (B=E) needs to do a lot of additional work in order to claim that (Explanation Maximalism) leads to a benign regress.

20 Of course, evaluating the severity of such a cost requires further assumptions about the relevant metric of parsimony. Also, it is worth mentioning that Kovacs, in other work, accepts that countenancing regresses (regardless of their form) counts against a theory (Reference Kovacs2019b, 7–8).

21 Note that the issue here concerns successful explanations in particular, as per (Explanation Maximalism). Separatism should allow for unbacked unsuccessful explanations.

22 The proponent of (B=E) would need to show in what way, if any, the principle that every explanation is backed should be rejected. So far, I have argued that the rejection of that principle generates more questions than it answers. Also, a philosophically attractive version of separatism takes every successful explanation to be backed. In this sense, it is not just that backing has some pretheoretical content that puts pressure on (B=E). There are also philosophical reasons to prefer a notion of backing with the features I have highlighted.

23 J. Wilson (Reference Wilson2016), Thompson (Reference Thompson, Bliss and Priest2018), and Kovacs (Reference Kovacs2019a) also consider (B=G).

24 Naturally, Sjölin Wirling would frame things using her preferred backing relatum (i.e., facts about the explanatoriness of propositions instead of explanations themselves). Still, my formulations are dialectically acceptable since I take the claim that backing is partial grounding to be largely orthogonal to whether backing relates explanations or facts about such explanations.

25 The point that such epistemic/pragmatic conditions are partial grounds is in line Sjölin Wirling’s own remarks (Reference Sjölin Wirling2020, 5). Still, it could be argued that even if such conditions are partial grounds, they should not be understood as backers of the relevant explanation (the same worry might also apply to the conjunction of these conditions and the relevant grounding-fact). Presumably this is because the first relatum of backing is supposed to be restricted to grounding-facts or determination-facts broadly construed. But, again, I do not see the motivation for this restriction.

26 Of course, taking backing itself to be primitive is different from taking backing to reduce to grounding and then taking grounding to be primitive. In the latter instance, backing reduces to something ‘more familiar’ which, among other things, has a primitive nature. In this sense, (B=G) is superior to the view that backing is primitive simpliciter in terms of ontological parsimony.

27 Versions of this objection can be found in J. Wilson (Reference Wilson2016) and Thompson (Reference Thompson, Bliss and Priest2018).

28 I think this is the most promising reductive theory of grounding currently in the literature (hence my focus). Another option would involve reducing grounding to essences (e.g., Correia and Skiles Reference Correia and Skiles2019). I do not have the space to properly discuss this interesting alternative.

29 The relevant literature has made a number of proposals concerning the nature of truthmaking. Perhaps, truthmaking is a version of the supervenience relation (Heil Reference Heil2016) or, as mentioned, some kind of necessitation (Armstrong Reference Armstrong2004). Truthmaking could also be a version of grounding (cf. Footnote footnotes 30 and Footnote 34).

30 See Rodriguez-Pereya (Reference Rodriguez-Pereyra, Beebee and Dodd2005, 24) and MacBride (Reference MacBride2014, 378) for the distinction I am appealing to. Truthmaking relations which do not seem to require a robust ontological category of truthmakers include most traditional correspondence-relations (e.g., Barnard and Horgan Reference Barnard and Horgan2006, 29) and deflationary truthmaking (Hornsby Reference Hornsby, Beebee and Dodd2005). For discussion see Asay and Baron (Reference Asay and Baron2019, 10).

31 As Daly (Reference Daly, Beebee and Dodd2005, 97) correctly notes, coherentists about truth can argue that a true proposition is “backed” by the fact that this proposition is a member of a maximally coherent set of propositions. For the analogous view on explanation, see Kovacs (Reference Kovacs2019b).

32 Such inheritance theses are usually articulated by appealing to functional realization or immanent causation (Robb and Heil Reference Robb and Heil2021, sec. 6.4).

33 For the tight connection between causation and grounding, see Fine (Reference Fine, Correia and Schnieder2012), Schaffer (Reference Schaffer2016), and A. Wilson (Reference Wilson2018).

34 Especially since cashing out the relation between grounding and truthmaking is controversial (see Liggins Reference Liggins, Correia and Schnieder2012; Tahko Reference Tahko and Calemi2016; Asay Reference Asay2017). For recent and direct rejections of the thesis that truthmaking is a case of grounding see Griffith (Reference Griffith2014), Saenz (Reference Saenz2018), and Audi (Reference Audi2019).

35 It could be objected that my solution is plausible insofar as explanations are propositions. But what if they are physical structures representing some phenomenon (say, two rocks representing the sun and the moon)? Surely, the rocks would continue to exist even in the absence of an explanation involving them. It is certainly possible to construe explanations in this way. But, sticking to the framework that explanations are propositions (entailing that the existence of that explanation is nothing over and above the existence of that proposition), it could be said that such physical systems illustrate or express the content of the relevant explanation (without being, themselves, explanations).

36 This also means that A grounding B is compatible with there being an explanatory gap between A and B (see J. Wilson Reference Wilson2016, 11). The fact that A grounds B does not entail, on its own, that A explains B.

37 Philosophers adopting similar views include Armstrong (Reference Armstrong1997), Wright (Reference Wright2012, 375–76, 376), Koslicki (Reference Koslicki, Correia and Schnieder2012, 212–13), Wright and van Eck (Reference Wright and van Eck2018, 1005). One can also trace this line of thinking in the literature on scientific representation (Giere Reference Giere2010).

38 A triggering statement is a statement that ensures that the relevant series of elements will not have a last member (Maurin Reference Maurin, Svennerlind, Almäng and Ingthorsson2013).

39 It is also not so clear whether (B=T) coupled with (1) and (2) generates a downward instead of an upward regress (the latter of which, as noted, is generally understood as less controversial). The proposed regress runs as follows. First, a truthmaking-fact (TM) is grounded by some ground (G). Then, a grounding-fact of the form [G grounds TM] is formed. Then, that grounding-fact makes its corresponding explanation true. Then, that truthmaking-fact has a further ground, and so on ad infinitum. But the dependencies involved in this regress run in multiple directions. The first element of the series (TM) depends on the second element (G). But, then, the emerging grounding-fact gives rises to its corresponding explanation (which, in turn, depends on a further ground, and so on). To compare, on a paradigmatic downward regress the first element depends on the second element, which depends on the third element ad infinitum. So, even if one brackets the worries that I raised against (1) and (2), the resulting regress is not paradigmatically downward.

References

Armstrong, D. M. 1997. A World of States of Affairs. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Armstrong, D. M. 2004Truth and Truthmakers. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Asay, Jamin, and Baron, Sam. 2019. “Deflating Deflationary Truthmaking.” Philosophical Quarterly 70 (278): 121. https://doi.org/10.1093/pq/pqz036.Google Scholar
Asay, Jamin. 2017. “Run Aground: Kit Fine’s Critique of Truthmaker Theory.” Philosophical Quarterly 67 (268): 443–63. https://doi.org/10.1093/pq/pqw072.Google Scholar
Audi, Paul. 2012. “Grounding: Toward a Theory of the In-Virtue-Of Relation.” Journal of Philosophy 109 (12): 685711. https://doi.org/10.5840/jphil20121091232.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Audi, Paul. 2019. “Why Truthmaking Is Not a Case of Grounding.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 101 (3): 567–90. https://doi.org/10.1111/phpr.12605.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barnard, Robert, and Horgan, Terence. 2006. “Truth as Mediated Correspondence.” The Monist 89 (1): 2849. https://doi.org/10.5840/monist200689132.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bliss, Ricki, and Trogdon, Kelly. 2016. "Metaphysical Grounding." In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2016), edited by Edward N. Zalta. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/grounding/.Google Scholar
Bokulich, Alisa. 2016. “Fiction as a Vehicle for Truth: Moving beyond the Ontic Conception.” The Monist 99 (3): 260–79. https://doi.org/10.1093/monist/onw004.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cameron, Ross P. 2008. “Turtles All the Way Down: Regress, Priority and Fundamentality.” Philosophical Quarterly 58 (230): 114. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9213.2007.509.x.Google Scholar
Correia, Fabrice, and Skiles, Alexander. 2019. “Grounding, Essence, and Identity.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 98 (3): 642–70.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Craver, Carl F. 2019. “Idealization and the Ontic Conception: A Reply to Bokulich.” The Monist 102 (4): 525–30.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Daly, Chris. 2005. “So Where’s the Explanation?” In Truthmakers: The Contemporary Debate, edited by Beebee, Helen and Dodd, Julian, 85105New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dasgupta, Shamik. 2017. “Constitutive Explanation.” Philosophical Issues 27 (1): 7497. https://doi.org/10.1111/phis.12102.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davidson, Donald. 1967. “Causal Relations.” Journal of Philosophy 64 (21): 691703.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
deRosset, Louis. 2013. “Grounding Explanations.” Philosophers’ Imprint 13. http://hdl.handle.net/2027/spo.3521354.0013.007.Google Scholar
Fine, Kit. 2012. “Guide to Ground.” In Metaphysical Grounding: Understanding the Structure of Reality, edited by Correia, Fabrice and Schnieder, Benjamin, 3780. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Giere, Ronald N. 2010. “An Agent-Based Conception of Models and Scientific Representation.” Synthese 172 (2): 269–81. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-009-9506-z.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Glazier, Martin. 2020. “Explanation.” In Routledge Handbook of Metaphysical Grounding, edited by Raven, Michael J., 121–32. London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Glennan, Stuart. 2002. “Rethinking Mechanistic Explanation.” Philosophy of Science 69 (S3): S34253. https://doi.org/10.1086/341857.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Griffith, Aaron M. 2014. “Truthmaking and Grounding.” Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 57 (2): 196215. https://doi.org/10.1080/0020174X.2013.855655.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heil, John. 2016. “Truthmaking and Fundamentality.” Synthese 198: 849–60. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-016-1292-9.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hempel, Carl. 1965. Aspects of Scientific Explanation and Other Essays in the Philosophy of Science. New York: Free Press.Google Scholar
Hornsby, Jennifer. 2005. “Truth without Truthmaking Entities.” In Truthmakers: The Contemporary Debate, edited by Beebee, Helen and Dodd, Julian, 3349. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kim, Jaegwon. 1981. “Causes as Explanations: A Critique.” Theory and Decision 13: 293309. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00126965.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kim, Jaegwon. 1988. “Explanatory Realism, Causal Realism, and Explanatory Exclusion.” Midwest Studies in Philosophy 12 (1): 225–39. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1475-4975.1988.tb00167.x.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kim, Jaegwon. 1994. “Explanatory Knowledge and Metaphysical Dependence.” Philosophical Issues 5: 5169. https://doi.org/10.2307/1522873.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
King, Jeffrey C. 2007. The Nature and Structure of Content. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kitcher, Philip. 1989. “Explanatory Unification and the Causal Structure of the Wworld.” In Scientific Explanation, edited by Kitcher, Philip and Salmon, Wesley, 410505. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Koslicki, Kathrin. 2012. “Varieties of Ontological Dependence.” In Metaphysical Grounding: Understanding the Structure of Reality, edited by Correia, Fabrice and Schnieder, Benjamin, 186213. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kovacs, David Mark. 2017. “Grounding and the Argument from Explanatoriness.” Philosophical Studies 174 (12): 2927–52. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-016-0818-9.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kovacs, David Mark. 2019a. “Four Questions of Iterated Grounding.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 101 (2): 341–64. https://doi.org/10.1111/phpr.12591.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kovacs, David Mark. 2019b. “Metaphysically Explanatory Unification.” Philosophical Studies 177 (6): 1659–83. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-019-01279-z.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lange, Marc. 2016Because without Cause: Noncausal Explanations in Science and Mathematics. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Liggins, David. 2012. “Truthmakers and Dependence.” In Metaphysical Grounding: Understanding the Structure of Reality, edited by Correia, Fabrice and Schnieder, Benjamin, 254–71. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Litland, Jon. 2016. “Pure Logic of Many-Many Ground.” Journal of Philosophical Logic 45 (5): 531–77. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-015-9386-2.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Litland, Jon Erling. 2018a. “Could the Grounds’s Grounding the Grounded Ground the Grounded?” Analysis 78 (1): 5665.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Litland, Jon Erling. 2018b. “In Defense of the Disunity of Grounding.” Thought: A Journal of Philosophy 7 (2): 97108.Google Scholar
MacBride, Fraser. 2014. “How Truth Depends upon Being.” Analysis 74 (3): 370–78. https://doi.org/10.1093/analys/anu057.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
MacBride, Fraser. 2020. "Truthmakers." In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2020), edited by Edward N. Zalta. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2020/entries/truthmakers/.Google Scholar
Maurin, Anna-Sofia. 2013. “Infinite Regress Arguments.” In Johanssonian Investigations: Essays in Honour of Ingvar Johansson on His Seventieth Birthday, edited by Svennerlind, Christer, Almäng, Jan, and Ingthorsson, Rögnvaldur, 421–38. Frankfurt: Ontos Verlag.Google Scholar
Maurin, Anna-Sofia. 2019. “Grounding and Metaphysical Explanation: It’s Complicated.” Philosophical Studies 176 (6): 1573–94. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-018-1080-0.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Raven, Michael J. 2015. “Ground.” Philosophy Compass 10 (5): 322–33. https://doi.org/10.1111/phc3.12220.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rettler, Bradley. 2017. “Grounds and ‘Grounds.’” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 47 (5): 631–55. https://doi.org/10.1080/00455091.2017.1282306.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Robb, David, and Heil, John. 2021. "Mental Causation.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2019), edited by Edward N. Zalta. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2019/entries/mental-causation/.Google Scholar
Rodriguez-Pereyra, Gonzalo. 2005. “Why Truthmakers?” In Truthmakers: The Contemporary Debate, edited by Beebee, Helen and Dodd, Julian, 1731New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rodriguez-Pereyra, Gonzalo. 2015. “Grounding is Not a Strict Order.” Journal of the American Philosophical Association 1 (3): 517–34. https://doi.org/10.1017/apa.2014.22.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosen, Gideon. 2010. “Metaphysical Dependence: Grounding and Reduction.” In Modality: Metaphysics, Logic, and Epistemology, edited by Hale, Bob and Hoffmann, Aviv, 109–36. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ruben, David-Hillel. 1990. Explaining Explanation. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Saenz, Noël Blas. 2018. “An Account of Truthmaking.” Synthese 197 (8): 3413–35. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-1894-5.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schaffer, Jonathan. 2016. “Grounding in the Image of Causation.” Philosophical Studies 173 (1): 49100. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-014-0438-1.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schipper, Arthur. 2020. “Aboutness and Ontology: A Modest Approach to Truthmakers.” Philosophical Studies 177 (2): 505–33. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-018-1192-6.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schnieder, Benjamin. 2010. “A Puzzle about ‘Because.’Logique et Analyse 53 (211): 317– 43.Google Scholar
Sjölin Wirling, Ylwa. 2020. “Is Backing Grounding?” Ratio 33 (3): 129–37.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Skiles, Alex, and Trogdon, Kelly. 2019. “Maurin on Grounding and Explanation.” In Maurinian Truths: Essays in Honour of Anna-Sofia Maurin on her 50th Birthday, edited by Stenwall, Robin and Wahlberg, Tobias Hansson, 159–72. Lund, Sweden: Lund University.Google Scholar
Tahko, Tuomas E. 2016. “Armstrong on Truthmaking and Realism.” In Metaphysics and Scientific Realism: Essays in Honour of David Malet Armstrong, edited by Calemi, Francesco F., 207–18. Boston: De Gruyter.Google Scholar
Taylor, Elanor. 2018. “Against Explanatory Realism.” Philosophical Studies 175 (1): 197219. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-017-0862-0.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Taylor, Elanor. 2020. “Backing without Realism.” Erkenntnis. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-020-00249-w.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thompson, Naomi. 2018. “Metaphysical Interdependence, Epistemic Coherentism, and Holistic Explanation.” In Reality and Its Structure, edited by Bliss, Ricki and Priest, Graham, 107–25. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Wallner, Michael. 2021. “The Ground of Ground, Essence, and Explanation.” Synthese. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-1856-y.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilson, Alastair. 2018. “Metaphysical Causation.” Noûs 52 (4): 723–51. https://doi.org/10.1111/nous.12190.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilson, Alastair. 2020. "Classifying Dependencies." In The Foundation of Reality: Fundamentality, Space and Time, edited by Glick, David, Darby, George, and Marmodoro, Anna. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Wilson, Jessica M. 2014. “No Work for a Theory of Grounding.” Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 57 (5–6): 535–79. https://doi.org/10.1080/0020174X.2014.907542.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilson, Jessica M. 2016. “Grounding-Based Formulations of Physicalism.” Topoi 37 (3): 495512. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-019-09644-7.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wright, Cory, and van Eck, Dingmar. 2018. “Ontic Explanation Is Either Ontic or Explanatory, but Not Both.” Ergo: An Open Access Journal of Philosophy 5: 9971029. http://dx.doi.org/10.3998/ergo.12405314.0005.038.Google Scholar
Wright, Cory D. (2012). Mechanistic Explanation without the Ontic ConceptionEuropean Journal of Philosophy of Science 2 (3): 375–94. https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-012-0048-8.CrossRefGoogle Scholar