Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-tf8b9 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-26T11:07:47.797Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Temporally Token-Reflexive Experiences

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2020

Uriah Kriegel*
Affiliation:
University of Arizona, Tucson, AZ85721, USA

Extract

John Searle has argued that all perceptual experiences are token-reflexive, in the sense that they are constituents of their own veridicality conditions. Many philosophers have found the kind of token-reflexivity he attributes to experiences, which I will call causal token-reflexivity, unfaithful to perceptual phenomenology. In this paper, I develop an argument for a different sort of token-reflexivity in perceptual (as well as some non-perceptual) experiences, which I will call temporal token-reflexivity, and which ought to be phenomenologically unobjectionable.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Authors 2009

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Brentano, F. 1874. Psychology from Empirical Standpoint. Kraus, O. ed. English ed. McAlister, L.L. ed. Trans. Rancurello, A.C. Terrell, D.B. and McAlister, L.L.. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul 1973.Google Scholar
Burge, T. 1991. ‘Vision and Intentional Content.’ In Gulick, R. Van and LePore, E. eds., John Searle and his Critics. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Byrne, A. 2001. ‘Intentionalism Defended.Philosophical Review 110: 199240.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Castañeda, H.-N. 1966. ‘“He”: A Study in the Logic of Self-Consciousness.Ratio 8: 130–57.Google Scholar
Chalmers, D.J. 2006. ‘Two-Dimensional Semantics.’ In LePore, E. and Smith, B. eds., Oxford Handbook of the Philosophy of Language. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Dainton, B. 2000. Stream of Consciousness. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Dretske, F.I. 1995. Naturalizing the Mind. Cambridge MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Evan, F.J. and Thorn, W.A. 1966. ‘Two Types of Posthypnotic Amnesia: Recall Amnesia and Source Amnesia.International Journal of Clinical and Experimental Hypnosis 14: 162179.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fernández, J. 2006. ‘The Intentionality of Memory.Australasian Journal of Philosophy 84: 3957.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ismael, J. 2006. The Situated Self. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Harman, G. 1990. ‘The Intrinsic Quality of Experience.Philosophical Perspectives 4: 3152.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Horgan, T. Tienson, J. and Graham, G. 2003. ‘The Phenomenology of First-Person Agency.’ In Walter, S. and Heckmann, H.D. eds., Physicalism and Mental Causation. Exeter: Imprint Academic.Google Scholar
Horgan, T. and Timmons, M. 2005. ‘Moral Phenomenology and Moral Theory.Philosophical Issues 15: 5677.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
James, W. 1890. The Principles of Psychology (2 volumes). London: McMillan (second edition, 1918).Google Scholar
Kaplan, D.Demonstratives.’ In Almog, J. Perry, J. and Wettstein, H. eds., Themes from Kaplan. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kelly, S.D. 2004. ‘Temporal Awareness.’ In Smith, D.W. and Thomasson, A. eds., Phenomenology and Philosophy of Mind. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kriegel, U. 2003. ‘Consciousness as Intransitive Self-Consciousness: Two Views and an Argument.Canadian Journal of Philosophy 33: 103–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kriegel, U. 2006. ‘The Phenomenologically Manifest.Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 5.Google Scholar
Le Poidevin, R. 2005. ‘A Puzzle Concerning Time Perception.Synthese 142: 109–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, D.K. 1976. ‘The Paradoxes of Time Travel.American Philosophical Quarterly 13: 145–52.Google Scholar
Lycan, W.G. 1996. ‘Layered Perceptual Representation.Philosophical Issues 7: 81100.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McTaggart, J.M.E. 1908. ‘The Unreality of Time.’ Reprinted in Poidevin, R. Le and McBeath, M. eds., The Philosophy of Time. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993.Google Scholar
Mellor, D.H. 1981. Real Time. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Nozick, R. 1981. Philosophical Explorations. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Perry, J. 1979. ‘The Problem of the Essential Indexical.Noûs 13: 321.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pitt, D. 2004. ‘The Phenomenology of Cognition; or What Is It Like to Think that P?Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 69: 136.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schacter, D.L. Harbluk, J.L. and McLachlan, D.R. 1984. ‘Retrieval without Recollection: An Experimental Analysis of Source Amnesia.Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior 23: 593611.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Seager, W. 1999. Theories of Consciousness. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Searle, J.R. 1983. Intentionality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Siegel, S. 2006. ‘Subject and Object in the Contents of Visual Experience.’ Philosophical Review 115.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smart, J.J.C. 1949. ‘The River of Time.Mind 58: 483–94.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sosa, E. 1999. ‘How Must Knowledge be Modally Related to What is Known?Philosophical Topics 26: 373–84.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Soteriou, M. 2000. ‘The Particularity of Visual Perception.European Journal of Philosophy 8: 173–89.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stalnaker, R. 1978. ‘Assertion.’ In Cole, P. ed., Syntax and Semantics: Pragmatics, Vol. 9. New York: Academic Press.Google Scholar
Strawson, G. 1994. Mental Reality. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Tulving, E. 1972. ‘Episodic and Semantic Memory.’ In Tulving, E. and Donaldson, W. eds., Organization of Memory. New York: Academic Press.Google Scholar
Tye, M. 2000. Consciousness, Color, and Content. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar