Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-t8hqh Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-22T14:11:00.336Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Deliberating in the presence of manipulation

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2020

Yishai Cohen*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, University of Southern Maine, Portland, ME, USA

Abstract

According to deliberation compatibilism, rational deliberation is compatible with the belief that one’s actions are causally determined by factors beyond one’s control. This paper offers a counterexample to recent accounts of rational deliberation that entail deliberation compatibilism. The counterexample involves a deliberator who believes that whichever action she performs will be the result of deterministic manipulation. It is further argued that there is no relevant difference between the purported counterexample and ordinary doxastic circumstances in which a determinist deliberates.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Journal of Philosophy 2017

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Barnes, Eric C. 2015. “Freedom, Creativity, and Manipulation.” Noûs 49(3): 560588.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bok, Hilary. 1998. Freedom and Responsibility. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. 10.1515/9781400822737CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Castañeda, Héctor-Neri. 1975. Thinking and Doing. Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing. 10.1007/978-94-010-9888-5CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clarke, Randolph. 1992. “Deliberation and Beliefs About One’s Abilities.” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 73(2): 101113.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clarke, Randolph. 2003. Libertarian Accounts of Free Will. New York: Oxford University Press. 10.1093/019515987X.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Coffman, E. J., and Warfield, Ted A.. 2005. “Deliberation and Metaphysical Freedom.” Midwest Studies in Philosophy 29(1): 2544. 10.1111/misp.2005.29.issue-1CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, Yishai. 2015. “The Manipulation Argument, At the Very Least, Undermines Classical Compatibilism.” Philosophia 43(2): 291307. 10.1007/s11406-015-9583-9CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Demetriou, Kristin. 2010. “The Soft-Line Solution to Pereboom’s Four-Case Argument.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 88(4): 595617. 10.1080/00048400903382691CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dennett, Daniel. 1984. Elbow Room. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Fischer, John Martin. 2006. My Way: Essays on Moral Responsibility. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Fischer, John Marin, and Ravizza, Mark. 1998. Responsibility and Control. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 10.1017/CBO9780511814594CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fischer, John Martin, and Tognazzini, Neal A.. 2011. “The Physiognomy of Responsibility.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 82(2): 381417. 10.1111/phpr.2011.82.issue-2CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Franklin, Christopher E. 2016. “If Anyone Should Be an Agent-Causalist, then Everyone Should Be an Agent-Causalist.” Mind 125(500): 11011131. 10.1093/mind/fzv177CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ginet, Carl. (1962) 1966. “Might We Have No Choice?” In Freedom and Determinism, edited by Lehrer, Keith, 87104. New York: Random House.Google Scholar
Haas, Daniel. 2013. “In Defense of Hard-Line Replies to the Multiple-Case Manipulation Argument.” Philosophical Studies 163(3): 797811. 10.1007/s11098-011-9847-6CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haji, Ishtiyaque. 2009. Incompatibilism’s Allure: Principal Arguments for Incompatibilism. Peterborough ON: Broadview Press.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel. (1785 )1981. Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals. Translated by Ellington, J.. Indianapolis, IN: Hacket.Google Scholar
Kapitan, Tomis. 1996. “Modal Principles in the Metaphysics of Free Will.” Philosophical Perspectives 10: 419445.Google Scholar
Lycan, William G. 1997. Consciousness. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
O’Connor, Timothy. 2000. Persons and Causes: The Metaphysics of Free Will. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Mckenna, Michael. 2008. “A Hard-Line Reply to Pereboom’s Four-Case Manipulation Argument.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 77(1): 142159. 10.1111/phpr.2008.77.issue-1CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McKenna, Michael. 2014. “Resisting the Manipulation Argument: A Hard-Liner Takes It on the Chin.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 89(2): 467484. 10.1111/phpr.2014.89.issue-2CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mele, Alfred R. 2006. Free Will and Luck. New York: Oxford University Press. 10.1093/0195305043.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nelkin, Dana K. 2004. “Deliberative Alternatives.” Philosophical Topics 32(1): 215240. 10.5840/philtopics2004321/224CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nelkin, Dana K. 2011. Making Sense of Freedom and Responsibility. New York: Oxford University Press. 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199608560.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Paul, L. A., and Hall, Ned. 2013. Causation. New York: Oxford University Press. 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199673445.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pereboom, Derk. 2014a. Free Will, Agency, and Meaning in Life. New York: Oxford University Press. 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199685516.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pereboom, Derk. 2014b. “Response to John Martin Fischer and Dana Nelkin.” Science, Religion & Culture 1(3): 218225.Google Scholar
Schlosser, Markus E. 2014. “The Luck Argument Against Event-Causal Libertarianism: It is Here to Stay.” Philosophical Studies 167(2): 375385. 10.1007/s11098-013-0102-1CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schlosser, Markus E. 2015. “Manipulation and the Zygote Argument: Another Reply.” The Journal of Ethics 19(1): 7384. 10.1007/s10892-014-9183-0CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shabo, Seth. 2010. “Uncompromising Source Incompatibilism.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 80(2): 349383. 10.1111/phpr.2010.80.issue-2CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Steward, Helen. 2012. A Metaphysics for Freedom. New York: Oxford University Press. 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199552054.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Taylor, Richard. 1964. “Deliberation and Foreknowledge.” American Philosophical Quarterly 1(1): 7380.Google Scholar
Taylor, Richard. 1966. Action and Purpose. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall Inc.Google Scholar
Todd, Patrick. 2016. “Manipulation Arguments and the Freedom to do Otherwise.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. doi: 10.1111/phpr.12298.Google Scholar
van Inwagen, Peter. 1983. An Essay on Free Will. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar