Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-j824f Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-07T21:04:36.137Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Supervaluations without Truth-Value Gaps*

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2020

Hans G. Herzberger*
Affiliation:
University of Toronto

Extract

For a very long time truth-value gaps were under a cloud of suspicion because they were considered logically unmanageable. So Frege declared that:

“as regards concepts we have a requirement of sharp delimitation; if this were not satisfied it would be impossible to set forth logical laws about them”.

Three-valued logic promised to dispel the cloud but in the eyes of many it had promised more than it could deliver. So in response to Reichenbach's plea for a three-valued quantum logic Russell replied:

“This is one of a number of questions as to which I am prevented from accepting a certain view by difficulties in carrying it out, but am prepared to alter my opinion if technical skill supplies an answer to my difficulties”.

‘By now technical skill has supplied many alternative systems of three-valued logic, but few answers and numerous additional difficulties.’

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Authors 1980

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

*

I am very much indebted to Anil Gupta, Robert Martin and Bas van Fraassen for criticism of earlier drafts.

References

Bergmann, M.: “A Presuppositional Theory of Semantic Categories”, Ph. D. Dissertation, University of Toronto. “Logic and Sortal Correctness”, Review of Metaphysics, 31 (1977), 6179.Google Scholar
Fine, K.: “Vagueness, Truth and Logic”, Synthese, 36 (1975), 265300.Google Scholar
Frege, G.: “Function and Concept”, in Geach, P. and Black, M., Translations From the Philosophical Writings of Gottlob Frege (Blackwells, Oxford, 1952),Google Scholar
Herzberger, H. G.: “True, False, Etc.”, Canadian Journal of Philosophy, thus volume, pp.Google Scholar
Kripke, S.: “Outline of a Theory of Truth”, Journal of Philosophy, 72 (1975), 690716.Google Scholar
Lambert, K.: “logical Truth and Microphysics” in Lambert, K., ed. The Logical Way of Doing Things (Yale U. P., New Haven, 1969), 93118.Google Scholar
Reichenbach, H.: “Bertrand Russell's logic”, in Schilpp, P., ed., The Philosophy of Bertrand Russell (Open Court, La Salle, 1944), 2154.Google Scholar
Rescher, N.: Many-Valued Logic (McGraw-Hill, New York, 1969).Google Scholar
Russell, B.: “Reply to Criticisms”, in Schilpp, P., ed. The Philosophy of Bertrand Russell, (Open Court, La Salle, 1944), 681741.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Russell, B.: “Mr. Strawson on Referring”, Mind 1957.Google Scholar
Scott, D.: “Advice on Modal Logic”, in Lambert, K., ed., Philosophical Problems in Logic (D. Reidel, Dordrecht, 1970), 143173.Google Scholar
Skyrms, B.: “Return of the Liar: Three-Valued Logic and the Concept of Truth”, American Philosophical Quarterly 1970, 153161.Google Scholar
Thomason, R.: “Indeterminist Time and Truth-Value Gaps”, Theoria, 36 (1970), 264281.Google Scholar
Thomason, R.: “A Semantic Theory of Sortal Incorrectness”, Journal of Philosophical Logic 2, (1972), 209258.Google Scholar
van Fraassen, B. C.: “Singular Terms, Truth-Value Gaps and Free Logic”, Journal of Philosophy, 63 (1966), 481495.Google Scholar
van Fraassen, B. C.: “Presupposition, Implication and Self-Reference”, Journal of Philosophy, 65 (1968), 136152.Google Scholar
van Fraassen, B. C.: “Presuppositions, Supervaluations and Free logic”, in Lambert, K., ed., The Logical Way of Doing Things (Yale U.P., New Haven 1969), 6792.Google Scholar
van Fraassen, B. C.: “Rejoinder: On a Kantian Conception of Language”, in Martin, R. L., ed., The Paradox of the Liar (Yale U. P., New Haven, 1970), 5966.Google Scholar
van Fraassen, B. C.: Formal Semantics and Logic (Macmillan, New York 1971).Google Scholar
van Fraassen, B. C.: “Hidden Variables in Conditional Logic”, Theoria, 40 (1974), 176190.Google Scholar