No CrossRef data available.
Article contents
Anaximander's Argument
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 01 January 2020
Extract
This topic was first put on a proper scholarly footing by the late Werner Jaeger and by Charles H. Kahn; earlier scholars tended either to refrain from speculating on the relation to Anaximander of Aristotle's Physics arguments on the infinite, or to deduce the Milesian provenance of one of them simply from its inclusion of a mention of Anaximander's name. It way my original intention in this paper to execute a tidying-up operation after the two well-planned attacks on Anaximander's argument by Jaeger and Kahn. I said some time ago in a footnote that I hoped to strengthen Professor Kahn's case for the unity of the argument concerning the infinite at Physics 203b4-15. If the following remarks achieve anything, it will be the half-fulfilment of that half-promise: instead of strengthening Kahn's reasoning for the unity of Aristotle's argument, what follows will tend to weaken it. But without the materials and the example of Jaeger and Kahn this present operation could never have been mounted, and disagreement with their strategy or tactics indicates no ingratitude and no narrowly polemical intention.
- Type
- Research Article
- Information
- Copyright
- Copyright © The Authors 1976
References
1 Jaeger, Theology of the Early Greek Philosophers pp. 24ff. with notes, and Kahn, , “Anaximander and the Arguments concerning the ΑΠΕΙΡΟΝ at Physics 203b4- 15,” Festschrift Ernst Kapp(Hamburg 1958) pp. 19–29.Google Scholar
2 See bibliography at Kahn, op.cit. p. 20 n.2.
3 One and Many in Presocratic Philosophy (Washington, D.C./Cambridge, Mass. 1971) p.29 and n.28 (on p.276). I should like to emphasize that I still find Kahn's paper illuminating. I still think also that H. B. Gottschalk's firm negative, cited in that note of mine, outruns the evidence.
4 Op.cit. p.22.
5 Op.cit. p.23.
6 Op.cit. p.22.
7 Simplicius In Physica p.463. 2ff.
8 In Physica e.g. p.463.8.
9 This is not an attack on others but a mea culpa. At One and Many p.30 (cf. p.63 first para. fin.) I was rash enough to write concerning the present passage as follows:— ‘Aristotle has evidently assimilated Anaximander's άρχή to his own kind of άρχή. and does not notice the difference between them, or at least does not think it worth while to point out the difference to his audience or readers'. Much of this I am now obliged to recant. but I am wholly unrepentant of the main conclusions reached in my chapter on the Milesians. In Physics 203b4-15 Aristotle did indeed distinguish in his own mind Anaximander's type of άρχή and his own. but his manner of writing leaves the matter unclear to his readers; whence his commentators’ criticisms, and the difficulty (visible in my translation's parentheses) in choosing between ‘beginning’ and ‘principle’ as renderings of άρχή at certain places in his argument. In this connection Aristotle's expression ὼς άρχή τις ούσα is of some interest. The addition of τις is not to be ignored as a piece of careless writing; τις here means ‘a sort of'. and the phrasing is notably cautious. Indeed it looks suspiciously like fudging. The differences between the two kinds of άρχή are more concealed than emphasized by it, despite its formal correctness. It looks as though Aristotle is not perfectly clear in his own mind, and this leaves open the possibility of his having been misled elsewhere over the word άρχή. The distinctions in Metaphysics ∆1 are by no means an insuperable bar: it is perfectly possible for even a thinker of distinction to be cloudy in one place over what is clear in another. especially if he is not philosophizing expressly on his own account, as Aristotle is not in this part of the Physics. Though it can no longer be urged that Aristotle makes a definite error over άρχή here. the possibility of error elsewhere is left open; but I have to admit its weakening. It still seems to me that if Aristotle were to bring the Milesian άρχή into his own scheme of four causes it could hardly have been as anything but the material cause in the case of Thales’ water and Anaximenes’ air, and Anaximander's ‘infinite’ was too easily assimilable to these. Clearly Aristotle rejected the notion of putting one or more of them under the head of efficient or moving cause, despite Plato's phrase in the Phaedrus άρχή τῆς ϰιυήσεως and despite Aristotle's own phrase ϰαὶ πάυτα ϰυβερυᾶυ: this perhaps because of a reluctance to allow for self-motion as a belief of thinkers before Plato. Hylozoism is conspicuously not an Aristotelian word. If not an efficient cause. the Milesian άρχή was all the more liable to representation as a material cause. The general historical reasons for supposing Aristotle mistaken about the Milesian άρχή, expounded in the relevant chapter of my book, remain, in my opinion, unshaken.
10 Op.cit. p.23.
11 In Physica p.464. 30ff.
12 Phaedrus 245d ff. (see above p. 2 (c)).
13 Aristotle, Physics, … by Ross, W. D. (Oxford 1936) p. v.Google Scholar
14 I refer to the argument that over infinite time any possibility will be actualized. especially at de Caelo 281b21ff.; for Plato any motion other than self-motion could (logically could) cease.
15 See the texts cited above p. 2 (d).
16 Note the words ὃϑευ ἀφαιρεῖται.
17 G.S., Kirk and J.E., RavenThe Presocratic Philosophers (Cambridge, England, repr. 1973) pp. 113–115.Google Scholar
18 One and Many (above n.3) p.73 with nn. Conceivably the notion was derived from Hesiod's Theogony; see M.L. West's commentary on Theogony 740, and Stokes, at Phronesis 7 (1962) pp.25-33CrossRefGoogle Scholar and 8 (1963) p.23. West rightly says that a bottomless chasm contradicts Theogony 814 unless chaos there and chasm at 740 are different; but it remains far from clear how much or how little contradiction one can attribute to Hesiod or how authentic are lines 807-819. West's arguments for the genuineness of 807-819 at the expense of 734-743 are unconvincing; e.g. to find the jailers at 734-5 is not analogous to finding lions and hunters in adjacent cages. but rather to finding both lions and keepers in the same zoo. On the πηγαί at 738 West speaks of this metaphor “redressing the balance” after the inadequate root-metaphor of 728, but fails (in my judgment) to consider closely enough what the metaphor actually signifies. It need not signify the same as the root-metaphor. I would add only that even if (as I do not believe) the πηγαί are other than cosmogonical, there would remain the possibility that the early philosophers thought they were cosmogonical.
19 The primacy of the spatial use was argued by Classen, C.J., Hermes 90 (1962) p.163Google Scholar on linguistic grounds. As for infinity if one admits that Anaximander believed in a true temporal infinite (as opposed to “indefinite“) then objections to a true spatial infinite surely fall to the ground?
20 Op.cit. p.24. That Argument A was Anaximander's is argued on less persuasive grounds by Babut, D., Revue des Etudes grecques 85 (1972) pp. 17–19.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
21 Op.cit. p.25.
22 See Guthrie, W.K.C.. History of Greek Philosophy I p.336.Google Scholar
23 This begs several questions about the nativi dei of Cicero. De Natura Deorum I, 10, 25, and Aëtius’ opinion (1, 7, 12) A. ἀπεφήυατο τοὺς ἀπείρους ούραυοὺς ϑεοὺς είυαι. If Cicero is right in describing Anaximander's nativos deos as orientis occidentisque, then clearly they were not immortal. For scepticism about these doxographical passages see Babut op.cit. (n.20) pp. 23-29. On the amount of Aristotle's clause beginning φησίυ which belongs to Anaximander, see Babut pp.3ff.; whether explicitly or implicitly, Anaxaminder thought of the ἄπειρου as divine if, as I believe, he described it as ἀϑάυατου ϰαὶ ἀγήρω (see Babut pp.8f. and Classen op.cit. [n.19]p.161).
24 Cf. Kirk, G.S.Classical Quarterly 5 (1955) p. 35CrossRefGoogle Scholar n.1 and Babut op.cit. (n.20) p.12.1t needs to be added that δοϰεῖ constitutes neither an acknowledgment of the figurative and purely symbolic use of ϰυβερυᾶυ (Babut p.13) nor (Classen p. 168) an expression of a personal conjecture of Aristotle's own, but must mean in context “is thought”, sc. by the thinker(s) on whom Aristotle is drawing. Otherwise διό is incorrect, since Aristotle offers reason only for the physicists holding that the infinite is an ἀρχή etc.
25 Op.cit. p.25.
26 See One and Many (above n.3) pp.253-5.
27 Parmenides B12.3: Babut (above n.20) cites parallels at p.6, n.23.
28 See Guthrie, History of Greek Philosophy II p.107 n.2.
29 Op.cit. p.22.
30 See Babut (above n.20) pp.5-10.
31 See One and Many (above n.3) pp.56-59.
32 Kahn, op.cit. p.29 is much more positive than the evidence warrants. Whether or not Thales’ geometry is in general adequately supported by the ancient evidence, it is not demonstrable that he produced consecutive and clearly set out proofs. But this is admittedly too large a question to be settled here.
33 I am much obliged to Dr. D. Bargrave-Weaver and Mr. K.W. Mills for reading and helpfully criticizing early drafts of this paper; my thanks are also due to my friendly critics at the Edmonton Workshop, and specially to Prof. Roger A. Shiner, whose written and oral criticisms compelled the modification, clarification and enlargement of the original paper. The revised version was heard and usefully questioned by the group of ancient philosophers in the Universities of Newcastle and Durham. My gratitude to all leaves me nevertheless with the whole responsibility for the paper's faults.
34 Kahn, op.cit. pp.21 and 25: see my One and Many p.29 and n.29 (on p.276).
35 See Kahn op.cit. p.27.
36 Op.cit. p.27.