Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-t8hqh Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-22T15:07:54.054Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Definiteness in Laki: Its interaction with demonstratives and number

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  14 December 2021

Sahar Taghipour*
Affiliation:
University of Toronto, Toronto, Canada
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

This article investigates definiteness and its interactions with demonstratives and number in Laki (Northwestern Iranian). By the examination of demonstratives and building upon previous proposals, I argue for two types of definite DPs in Laki, namely anaphoric and deictic. I show that the patterns of definite and number marking are sensitive to the type of the DP. In particular, I argue that double definiteness, resulting from an Agree relation between D and N, and head movement of Num to D both are obtained only in anaphoric definite DPs for feature-checking requirements. Overall, this study highlights the contributions of anaphoricity to the DP internal structure. The present proposal can account for similar phenomena in other Iranian languages (i.e., Sorani and Kermanshahi Kurdish). The divergence of Laki definiteness from similar attested patterns (i.e., Scandinavian double definiteness) contributes to our cross-linguistic understanding of definiteness and its interactions with other nominal elements.

Résumé

Résumé

Cet article étudie la définitude et ses interactions avec les démonstratifs et le nombre en laki (iranien occidental (nord)). Par l'examen des démonstratifs et en m'appuyant sur des propositions antérieures, je plaide pour deux types de SD définis, en laki, à savoir des SD anaphoriques et des SD déictiques. Je montre que les modèles de marquage de définitude et de nombre sont sensibles au type de SD. En particulier, je soutiens que la double définitude, (résultant d'une relation d'accord entre D et N) et le mouvement de la tête de Num à D, ne sont obtenus que dans des SD définis anaphoriques pour les exigences de la vérification des traits. Dans l'ensemble, cette étude met en évidence les contributions de l'anaphoricité à la structure interne du SD. La présente proposition peut rendre compte de phénomènes similaires dans d'autres langues iraniennes (le sorani et le kurde Kermanshahi). La divergence de la définitude en laki à partir de modèles attestés similaires (c'est-à-dire la double définitude scandinave) contribue à notre compréhension interlinguistique de la définitude et de ses interactions avec d'autres éléments nominaux.

Type
Article
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Linguistic Association/Association canadienne de linguistique 2021

1. Introduction

This article investigates the noun phrase of Laki (Kurdish, southern),Footnote 1 with a special focus on definiteness and number.Footnote 2 From a cross-linguistic perspective, definite marking has shown a great deal of variation with respect to different phenomena such as double definiteness (Scandinavian: Faroese, Norwegian and Swedish), polydefiniteness (modern Greek, modern Hebrew), unfixed pattern of definite marking (Amharic). Here, I examine definite marking in Laki as an instance of double definiteness. The investigation of this pattern in Laki, with its convergence and divergence from the prototypical Scandinavian pattern of double definiteness, contributes to our general cross-linguistic understanding of this phenomenon. I argue that the pattern of Laki double definiteness is limited to anaphoric definite DPs, and is obtained via an Agree relation between an anaphoric definite D and N. The goal of this study is not limited to the investigation of double definiteness. Here, I also examine demonstratives and their contribution to the definiteness of the DP. The facts of demonstratives provide supporting evidence that Laki double definiteness is obtained only in anaphoric definite DPs. The Agreement proposal for double definiteness also provides an account for the DP patterns with demonstratives. This study also examines the interaction between number and definiteness which results in Number movement to the D head. Number movement is also argued to be sensitive to the presence of the anaphoric definite D. Overall, the current study highlights the influence of anaphoricity on the DP structure. Some aspects of the proposed analyses can also be extended to sister Kurdish varieties that display similar patterns (e.g., Kermanshahi and Sorani Kurdish).

It is worth noting that Laki has remained understudied in several grammatical aspects, including its noun phrase. Considering the broad cross-linguistic diversity in definite marking under the effect of parametric variations, the current study aims to bring insights into the ongoing body of research on definiteness, and more broadly on the syntax of DP. The divergence of Laki definiteness from the previously attested patterns contributes to our understanding of definiteness and the arrays of its possible patterns in a broader empirical domain.

In Laki, nouns inflect for definiteness by the affix -a, as in (1). When a definite noun is modified, Laki allows double definite marking: one definite marker appears on the noun (henceforth DP internal definite marker) and another definite marker appears on the modifier (henceforth DP final definite marker), as illustrated in (2).

To a large extent, the definiteness pattern in Laki seems to be similar to the pattern of Scandinavian double definiteness. In Norwegian, Swedish and Faroese, in bare definite DPs (i.e., a DP without a modifier), a definite suffix appears on the noun, as in the Swedish example in (3). When the definite noun is modified, as in (4), definiteness is realized with both a definite suffix on the noun and with a definite determiner. From now on, by Scandinavian, I mean Swedish, Norwegian and Faroese. These languages show an identical definite pattern.Footnote 3

As can be observed in the examples given above, Laki and Scandinavian share one crucial similarity: in a bare definite DP, both languages have one definite marker, and in a modified definite DP, they have two definite markers. I show that the existing similarity between these two definite patterns is not sufficient to give them the same analysis. This finding calls for a novel account for Laki. In section 2, I provide a more detailed description of facts involved in Laki DPs. I show that Laki definite DPs (without demonstratives) are uniformly anaphoric in their reference (more elaboration on this definiteness feature is given in section 5). In section 3, the empirical differences between Scandinavian and Laki double definiteness are addressed. I also discuss a number of approaches to Scandinavian and argue that these approaches cannot fully capture the Laki patterns. In section 4, some cross-linguistic facts from other Kurdish varieties are provided examining the possibility of pursuing an ezafe analysis for Laki along the lines of Karimi (Reference Karimi2007), Samvelian (Reference Samvelian, Karimi, Samiian and Stilo2008) and others for different varieties of Kurdish. In Section 5, I propose an Agreement account (Chomsky Reference Chomsky1995, Reference Chomsky, Martin, Michaels and Uriagareka2000, Reference Chomsky and Kenstowicz2001) for Laki double definiteness. This Agreement is argued to be established between D and N, resulting from D probing downward. In this section, the pattern of indefinite DPs are also examined. I argue that the Agreement between D and N fails in indefinite DPs leading to a single indefinite marking. In the same section, the interaction between number and definiteness is also discussed. I provide a head movement account for the distribution of number in definite DPs. This head movement is argued to be limited to anaphoric definite DPs. In Section 6, the patterns with demonstratives are described and analyzed. Building upon Lyons (Reference Lyons1999), Alexiadou et al. (Reference Alexiadou, Haegeman and Stavrou2007), Elbourne (Reference Elbourne2008), Schwarz (Reference Schwarz2009) and Cornish (Reference Cornish2011), among others, I identify two definite features expressed by demonstratives; anaphoric and deictic. These definite features influence the DP structure in that they determine the presence of a definite agreement as well as the placement of Number. I argue that the pattern of double definiteness (resulting from the Agreement between D and N) and the head movement of Number both are obtained only in DPs with the anaphoric reference. Section 7 concludes the article.

2. Overview of definite marking in Laki

As shown above, nouns in Laki inflect for definiteness with the affix -a (5). When a definite noun is modified, Laki allows double definite marking: one definite marker appears on the noun (DP internal definite marker) and another one appears on the modifier (DP final definite marker), as in (6).

It is worth noting that this definite marking expresses anaphoric definiteness known as an expression of strong familiarity (Roberts Reference Roberts2003, Schwarz Reference Schwarz2009). Anaphoric definite DPs pick referents that are familiar to the discourse participants. This property will be illustrated in section 5.1.

As shown in (6), the DP internal definite marker appears on the noun. When there is more than one modifier, the DP final definite marker has to appear on the last modifier, leaving the intermediate modifier(s) unmarked. In (7), the DP internal definite marker appears on the noun, and the DP final definite marker appears on the last modifier. As shown in (8)–(11), all other combinations of these affixes are unacceptable.

These two definite affixes both encode (anaphoric) definiteness. In their absence, the DP has a generic reading, referring to a kind or a class of entities.Footnote 4 Even though these two suffixes seem to be definite markers, they are different in two respects: stress and syllable sensitivity. The stress pattern of these two definite markers is different. While the DP internal definite marker does not receive the primary stress of the DP, the DP final definite marker that appears on the (last) modifier receives the primary DP stress. The stress is shown in bold to highlight the contrast in (12a) and (12b). Note that it cannot be the case that the primary stress is consistently assigned to the DP final syllable. The primary stress of the DP is always assigned to the final syllable of a noun appearing in the DP, and not to the final syllable of the DP. As such, the inflectional affixes appearing on a noun and in the DP final syllable position, such as indefinite and possessor markers, do not receive the DP primary stress. Also, as we will see in section 6, another DP final definite marker, namely the deictic definite marker, co-occurring only with demonstratives, does not receive the primary stress of the DP. Overall, these facts suggest that the assignment of the DP primary stress to the DP final definite marker is not due to an independent stress pattern in Laki. If that were the case, all other inflectional markers appearing in the DP final syllable position were expected to receive the primary stress of the DP. I will return to this discussion in section 6.

The second difference between these two definite elements is in their sensitivity to the number of syllables of their host. The presence of the DP internal definite marker is sensitive to the number of syllables of its nominal host, while its DP final counterpart does not show such sensitivity. Example (13) shows that the definite markers appear on their host; that is, on the noun and the last modifier respectively. Examples (14) and (15) show that the DP internal definite marker does not appear on a polysyllabic noun. Example (16) shows that the DP final definite marker is obligatory and insensitive to the number of syllables of its host, as its absence on a polysyllabic adjective makes the DP ungrammatical. The glide in (14) and (15) is an epenthetic segment inserted for hiatus resolution.

In a bare definite DP, we see the presence of only one definite marker. Crucially, this definite marker is stressed and insensitive to the number of the syllables of the host. Taking the stress assignment and the syllable sensitivity into consideration, we can come to the conclusion that this -a is the DP final definite marker, and not the internal marker. Examples (17)–(18) show that in a bare definite DP, the DP final definite marker is stressed (shown in bold) and appears on a polysyllabic noun.

The nature of the definite marker as the DP final definite marker in (17)–(18) is further supported by some facts from closely related Kurdish languages. In other Kurdish varieties, Kermanshahi and Sorani Kurdish, the DP final and the DP internal definite markers have different forms.Footnote 5 In a bare definite DP, definiteness is marked by the the DP final marker -aga and -aka respectively (19)–(20).

In these two varieties of Kurdish, when a definite noun is modified (21)–(22), the definite suffix appears phrase-finally, and another definite marker appears on the noun.Footnote 6 This pattern is similar to what we observed in Laki. Crucially, in these languages, the form of the DP final definite marker is different from the DP internal element, showing clearly that in the bare context, we have the DP final definite marker.

These observations provide support for two claims regarding Laki; first, the -a appearing in a bare definite DP is a definite marker which is distinct from the DP internal -a, and second, the expression of the DP internal -a appearing in a modified definite DP is dependent on the modification of the DP, whereas the DP final definite marker expresses definiteness independently. The independent and consistent realization of the DP final definite marker motivates taking the DP final definite marker as the realization of D. Furthermore, wider range of data from other Iranian languages provides support to consider the Laki DP final definite marker as the realization of D. For instance, Persian, which has the same ordering in its DP as that of Laki, only shows a DP final element as its definite marker (-e). The DP internal definite marker is absent in Persian. The following examples illustrate.

Importantly, this DP final element in Persian has been uniformly treated as the realization of D (see Ghomeshi Reference Ghomeshi2003, Kahnemuyipour Reference Kahnemuyipour2014, among others). These facts provide evidence in favor of considering the Laki DP final definite marker as the realization of D, and the DP internal one as an element inserted through a different mechanism. In section 5.1, I will argue that the DP internal definite marker is a definite agreement inserted as a result of an Agreement between the anaphoric definite D and N.Footnote 7

3. Laki and Scandinavian double definiteness: Empirical and theoretical notes

With observations made so far, let us turn to the Scandinavian double definiteness again and examine its similarities and differences with the pattern of Laki more closely. For ease of reference, I repeat below the Swedish examples given in (3)–(4).

As mentioned above, the similarity is that in both languages definiteness is marked once in a bare definite DP and twice under modification. However, the two languages show one crucial difference. In Laki, we see the realization of D in two contexts: in a bare definite DP (17)–(18) and in a modified definite DP (13)–(14). As noted above, the stress pattern, syllable sensitivity and cross-linguistic observations all support the claim that the definite marker that appears in Laki bare definite DPs is the DP final definite marker. This definite marker, and not the DP internal one, was argued to be the realization of D. By contrast, in Scandinavian, we see the realization of D only in modified definite DPs (26). In bare definite DPs, we see the definite suffix (25). Importantly, what most approaches to Scandinavian have in common is the assumption that the determiner, and not the definite suffix, is the realization of D; see |Santelmann (Reference Santelmann1992, Reference Santelmann1993); Delsing (Reference Delsing1993); Embick and Noyer (Reference Embick and Noyer2001); Julien (Reference Julien2003); LaCara (Reference LaCara2011), among others.Footnote 8 In other words, in Scandinavian, it is the suffixal definite marker (i.e., a non-D element) that appears in two contexts: bare definite DPs and modified definite DPs (25)–(26). In Laki, it is the D that appears in the two contexts. This crucial difference in the realization of D in the two languages makes the approaches of Scandinavian double definiteness unsuitable to capture the Laki definite pattern.

The fact that in Scandinavian, in contrast to Laki, the realization of D is limited to modified definite DPs has motivated the main spirit in several analyses of Scandinavian double definiteness that in bare definite DPs, the (definite) noun undergoes movement to the empty D position or to the specifier of the DP. This movement is assumed to occur for the satisfaction of features or constraints (Santelmann Reference Santelmann1992, Reference Santelmann1993; Delsing Reference Delsing1993; Embick and Noyer Reference Embick and Noyer2001; Julien Reference Julien2003, Reference Julien2005, among others). In modified definite DPs, this movement is claimed to be blocked for different reasons. For example, under the proposal of Santelmann (Reference Santelmann1993), this movement is blocked due to licensing issues, as adjectives need the noun to be in a local m-commanding relation with them in order to be licensed for gender, definiteness and number. As such, in a modified DP, the noun has to remain low.Footnote 9 Julien (Reference Julien2003) proposes a probe-goal relation between the definite noun and D for the satisfaction of uninterpretable definite and phi-features posited in D which are realized by the Agreement between D and the definite noun leading to the movement of the definite noun to the specifier of the DP in bare definite DPs. As Julien argues, in modified definite DPs, this probe-goal relation is blocked due to the intervention of adjectives, as adjectives are the closest goal for Agreement with D. For Delsing (Reference Delsing1993) and Embick and Noyer (Reference Embick and Noyer2001), in modified definite DPs, the movement of the (definite) noun to D is blocked due to the intervention of adjectives. Following Abney (Reference Abney1987), they assume a head position for APs. Here, I particularly argue against the general assumption that attributive adjectives are merged in head positions. As such, the emergence of double definiteness in Laki cannot be attributed to the head status of adjectives and the blockage they cause for the movement of the noun to a higher position – to D or to Spec,DP. Furthermore, as we will see in section 5.3, the consideration of adjectives in adjunct positions is a crucial assumption in the account given for the pattern of number marking. It is shown that the presence of adjectives does not block Number head movement to a higher structural position.

The idea of adjectives occupying head positions has been criticized in several other works; see Olsen (Reference Olsen, Christa Bhatt and Schmidt1989), Valois (Reference Valois1991), Bernstein (Reference Bernstein1993), Svenonius (Reference Svenonius1994), Julien (Reference Julien2003, Reference Julien2005) and more recently Kahnemuyipour (Reference Kahnemuyipour2014), among others. A number of properties have been examined against the head position of adjectives. For example, by the use of intensifiers, APs can become larger. The iterative nature of APs provides more evidence in favor of the non-head merging position of adjectives. Considering their iterative nature, assuming adjectives merged in head positions requires them to arbitrarily select for either a nominal complement or an adjectival complement, which is an unfavourable assumption. The optionality of adjectives provides another piece of evidence against the assumption that adjectives are merged in head positions. It would be ideal if adjectives are treated uniformly across languages as phrasal projections occupying adjuncts or specifier positions. If so, the blocking analysis of head movement is systematically undermined. In what follows, I am assuming adjectives as elements that are merged in adjunct positions (i.e., NP adjoined).Footnote 10

In a number of accounts for Scandinavian double definiteness, the two definite markers have been considered as two distinct syntactic projections. For example, Santelmann (Reference Santelmann1993) and Julien (Reference Julien2003, Reference Julien2005) posit two definite heads in their analysis (also see Schoorlemmer Reference Schoorlemmer2012 for the two D copy analysis). Crucially, given the broader distribution of the Scandinavian definite suffix compared to its definite article, it is a valid assumption that the Scandinavian definite suffix could project its own phrase. By contrast, taking the Laki DP internal definite marker as the realization of a separate syntactic projection is under question, given the fact that we never see the independent realization of this element.

In light of these considerations, we can clearly observe that in spite of some surface similarities between the double definiteness pattern in Scandinavian and Laki, the two languages diverge in some empirical aspects: in Laki bare definite DPs, we see the realization of D, while in Scandinavian bare definite DPs, we see the realization of a non-D element (i.e., the definite suffix). Therefore, one cannot treat the pattern of the two languages similarly. In particular, considering the proposals examined above, the pattern of Laki bare definite DP cannot be analyzed as the result of the noun raising to D or to Spec,DP. Furthermore, regarding the pattern of modified definite DPs, given that in Scandinavian, we see the realization of D under modification, the presence of D in the absence of a modifier in Laki is unexplained.Footnote 11 In the following section, I consider the possibility of taking the DP internal definite marker as a nominal linker (a.k.a. ezafe) and examine the validity of this assumption. I argue that the DP internal definite marker cannot be taken as a nominal linker.

4. DP internal definite marker as a nominal linker?

In many Iranian languages, nominal heads are linked to their modifiers or possessors by a linking element known as ezafe; see Samiian (Reference Samiian and Marashi1994), Ghomeshi (Reference Ghomeshi1997), Karimi (Reference Karimi2007), Larson and Yamakido (Reference Larson, Yamakido, McNally and Kennedy2008), Karimi and Brame (Reference Karimi and Brame2012), Kahnemuyipour (Reference Kahnemuyipour2014), among others. The following examples are from Persian and Sorani Kurdish respectively. The Sorani data in (29)–(30) is borrowed from Karimi (Reference Karimi2007: 2).

In light of the expression of ezafe in sister languages like Sorani Kurdish, one might argue that the DP final definite marker in a Laki modified definite DP is a definite marker, and the DP internal one is an ezafe which is showing concord with the definite marker. There are proposals along the same lines for other Iranian languages in which ezafe shows concord with a morphosyntactic feature (including definiteness); see Karimi (Reference Karimi2007), Samvelian (Reference Samvelian, Karimi, Samiian and Stilo2008), Toosarvandani and van Urk (Reference Toosarvandani and van Urk2014), Atlamaz (Reference Atlamaz2016), Tahir (Reference Tahir2018), among others. In Sorani Kurdish, as shown in examples (29)–(30), ezafe is marked with -i between a noun and its modifier or possessor. Definiteness in Sorani Kurdish is realized with the affix -aka.Footnote 12 Crucially, in the context of the definite marker, the ezafe appears as -a. It has been argued that ezafe shows concord with definiteness when it is in the domain of definiteness, as in the following example.

Along these lines regarding the Laki data, one could assume that the -a between the noun and the modifier is an ezafe which shows concord with the definite marker (i.e., the DP final -a). However, a wider range of Laki data in the nominal domain reveals a difference with respect to the presence of ezafe and the function of definiteness in Laki compared to Sorani. There are two main differences between Laki and Sorani in their noun phrases, which exclude the possibility of the -a suffix between the noun and the modifier to be a linking element in Laki. Firstly, Laki lacks ezafe in its nominal domain. That is, when a noun is modified or possessed, no linking element appears between the noun and its modifier or possessor, as illustrated in (32)–(33).

Moreover, in a Sorani modified DP, as shown in (31) above, repeated below as (34), ezafe is iterative. In other words, per each modifier we see one ezafe in Sorani. But in a modified Laki DP with more than one modifier, excluding the DP final definite marker, there is only one -a which appears on the head noun. The example in (35) illustrates that the first modifier lacks -a. The iterative nature of ezafe is not a particular property of ezafe restricted to Sorani Kurdish. This property is invariably observed across Iranian languages that display the ezafe construction. This characteristics makes an ezafe analysis (combined with concord) feasible for the Sorani -a, but not for the Laki -a.

As a result of these observations, the possibility of taking the DP internal -a as a linker element is ruled out for Laki.Footnote 13

5. Analysis

In this section, building upon the proposals of Santelmann (Reference Santelmann1993) and Julien (Reference Julien2003, Reference Julien2005) for Scandinavian, I provide an Agreement account to analyze Laki double definiteness. Then, I show the pattern of indefinite DPs and argue that due to the featural properties of the indefinite D, Agreement fails in such DPs. Therefore, the double definite pattern is not obtained in indefinite DPs. Furthermore, in this section, I examine the pattern of number marking and argue for a head movement analysis of Num to D in definite DPs.

5.1 Definite nouns

As mentioned in section 2, Laki definite DPs express anaphoricity. As such, in my descriptions and analysis, I refer to these definite DPs as anaphoric definite DPs. In section 6, we will see that in the context of demonstratives, the DP can express a different definite property, namely deictic definite. Given that the deictic definite property is expressed only in the presence of a demonstrative and given that the definite DPs without demonstratives (i.e., the definite DPs we have seen so far) express anaphoricity, the discussion of this section is focused on the anaphoric definiteness. As already indicated in section 2, the anaphoric definiteness is commonly known as an expression of strong familiarity (Roberts Reference Roberts2003, Schwarz Reference Schwarz2009) which picks referents that are familiar to the discourse participants. In the following examples, the nouns ‘book’ and ‘girl’ have the same particular referent for the speaker and the hearer. These definite expressions can also be anaphoric to a linguistic antecedent (similar to the function of English definite article the).

In section 2, I also argued that the Laki DP internal and DP final definite markers are two different definite markers. In this regard, I argued that the DP final definite marker is the realization of D. By contrast, the DP internal definite marker was argued to be a non-D element which appears only in modified definite DPs. In section 3, it was argued that the pattern of Scandinavian double definiteness does not fully overlap with that of Laki and hence the accounts given for Scandinavian cannot totally capture Laki facts.

As we will see in section 5.2., similar to the DP final definite marker, the indefinite marker also appears in the phrase-final position. Following Abney (Reference Abney1987), Szabolcsi (Reference Szabolcsi, Kiefer and Kiss1994) and subsequent authors, I take the definite and indefinite markers as different realizations of a single D head (see Ghomeshi Reference Ghomeshi2003 for the QP versus DP analysis of indefinite and definite markers in Persian). Furthermore, I assume that the D head, regardless of its different realizations (e.g., definite vs. indefinite) has a valued definiteness feature. However, to capture the different patterns obtained in indefinite DPs (examined in section 5.2) or deictic definite DPs (examined in section 6), further featural specification on D is required. Given the anaphoric nature of the definite marker in definite DPs, I take the definiteness feature on D to be a valued [DEF]anaphoric feature in anaphoric definite DPs. In indefinite DPs, the valued definiteness feature on D is assumed to be [DEF]indefinite and in deictic definite DPs, the valued definiteness feature is taken to be [DEF]deictic. Crucially, this characterization of the D head can account for the different patterns we observe across different DPs. More will be discussed about these different patterns in section 5.2 and section 6, when I examine indefinite and deictic definite DPs. The discussion in this section will be focused only on the anaphoric definite DP.

The theory of Agreement proposed by Chomsky (Reference Chomsky1995, Reference Chomsky, Martin, Michaels and Uriagareka2000, Reference Chomsky and Kenstowicz2001) demonstrates a matching relation between a probe having an unvalued feature and a goal having the valued counterpart of the probe's feature, resulting in the probe's unvalued feature being checked/valued. Regarding the Laki data, given that the definiteness feature expressed in definite DPs is an anaphoric definite feature, as stated above, I assume a valued [DEF]anaphoric feature on D. The postulation of a definiteness feature on D aligns with several proposals that have provided Agreement/concord accounts in the DP domain (Thorne Reference Thorne1972; Santelmann Reference Santelmann1993; Julien Reference Julien2003, Reference Julien2005; Kramer Reference Kramer2009). Furthermore, I posit that the anaphoric definite D has an unvalued [uN] feature.Footnote 14 This unvalued [uN] feature makes the anaphoric definite D a probe. Furthermore, I assume that nouns are also merged with featural properties. The features on the noun are posited to be a valued [N] feature and an unvalued definiteness feature, namely [uDEF]. When both the noun and the definite D are merged with their features, D probes downward and establishes a matching relation with the noun having the valued [N] feature. As such, the Agreement is established between D and the noun. Given this Agreement, on one hand, the unvalued [uN] feature on D is valued; on the other hand, the unvalued [uDEF] feature on the noun is valued as a reflex of the probe by D, against the valued definiteness feature on D.

Under the current proposal, the DP final definite marker is taken as the spell-out of D and the DP internal definite marker appearing on the noun is taken as a definite agreement marker, resulting from the valuation of the [uDEF] feature on N. The Agreement involved in a modified definite DP is shown in a two-step derivation below.

  1. (38) a. Definite Agreement: Step one  b. Definite Agreement: Step two

With respect to the syllable sensitivity of the definite agreement, one can postulate that the syllable structure of the root is visible to the insertion of the definite agreement. Hence, when the nominal root has more than one syllable, due to a PF constraint, the definite agreement is realized with a null allomorph.

Furthermore, considering the Agreement relation between D and the noun, we should expect to see the double expression of definiteness on the noun in a bare definite DP. The first marker is supposed to be the definite agreement, and the second one is supposed to be the realization of D. Therefore, what we would expect to see is the following DP.

  1. (39) *det-a-a

    girl-def-def

    ‘the girl’

However, this prediction is not borne out as the DP det-a-a is ill-formed. In the bare definite DP, we see one definite marker on the noun. As shown in section 2, this definite marker has the properties of the DP final definite marker: it is stressed, and it is not syllable sensitive (40)–(41).

As argued in section 2, in addition to the difference in the stress assignment and syllable sensitivity, the cross-linguistic facts from other Iranian languages confirm the accuracy of the claim that the definite marker in bare definite DPs is the DP final definite marker and not the definite agreement on the noun (see examples (17)–(24) in section 2). Therefore, the overt realization of the definite agreement at PF seems to be sensitive to the adjacency of two definite markers in a bare DP. I take the lack of the definite agreement in bare definite DPs as an OCP effect captured by the conditions on insertion rules banning the adjacency of two overt definite markers on a noun. In general, regarding the null realization of the definite agreement marker, I posit that a null allomorph of the definite agreement is chosen in two contexts: when there is already a definite marker on the noun arising in the context of bare definite DPs, and when the noun is not monosyllabic. Overall, the sensitivity of the definite agreement to such PF constraints provides support for taking the two definite markers (i.e., DP final definite marker and definite agreement) as distinct elements, as has been argued in the current proposal.

5.2 Indefinite nouns

The proposal put forth above provided an Agreement account for the pattern of double definiteness emerging in (anaphoric) definite contexts. In this section, we will be looking at indefinite nouns. Indefinite nouns in Laki are marked with the affix -i (42). In contrast to definite nouns, when an indefinite noun is modified, no double marking is obtained, even if the noun is monosyllabic, as shown in (43)–(44). In (43), there is only one indefinite marker, which appears on the modifier. A modified noun cannot take an indefinite marker (44).

As indicated in the previous section, I am taking definite and indefinite markers as different realizations of a single D head occupying a high functional position in the DP structure. It is worth noting that the pattern of stress assignment in definite and indefinite DPs seems to cast doubt on the assumption of a single head approach. As already mentioned, the DP final definite marker receives the primary DP stress. By contrast, the indefinite marker does not receive the primary stress. Considering this difference at first glance, one can postulate that the definite and indefinite markers are inserted in two different syntactic positions. However, one can argue on the contrary that the different pattern of stress assignment is not necessarily an indication of distinct projections for these two elements. As we will see in section 6, the difference in the stress pattern exists even in sub-types of definite DPs. While the anaphoric definite D receives the primary stress, the deictic definite D does not. I will argue in section 6 that the stress pattern could possibly be explained via independent PF principles such as the specific prosody of the vocabulary items.

With respect to the pattern of indefinite DPs, the main question is why don't we obtain double indefinite marking in indefinite DPs? As indicated in the previous section, in indefinite DPs, the valued definiteness feature on D is assumed to be [DEF]indefinite, reflecting its indefinite property as opposed to the definite D. I posit that the unvalued [uN] feature is limited to an anaphoric definite D. Therefore, the only feature available on the indefinite D is the valued [DEF]indefinite feature. Given the strong referential property of anaphoric definite elements, the postulation of the [uN] feature limited to the anaphoric D seems motivated. As a result of the featural property on the indefinite D (i.e., lacking the [uN] feature), D does not probe and hence the Agreement fails.Footnote 15 Following Preminger (Reference Preminger2009, Reference Preminger2011), I posit that the failure of Agree in an indefinite DP and hence the presence of the uninterpretable [uDEF] feature on the noun does not lead to a crashed derivation. In such a derivation, the unvalued [uDEF] feature on the noun is deleted, to avoid the ill-formedness of the indefinite DP, illustrated in (45).Footnote 16

  1. (45) a.   Failure of Agree         b.   Feature deletion

5.3 The interaction of number and definiteness

In this section, I examine the pattern of number marking and argue for an interaction between definiteness and number. Laki has two numbers: singular and plural. Singular is unmarked and plural is marked. In a modified indefinite DP (46)–(47), the plural marker appears on the noun (see (50)). By contrast, in a modified definite DP (48)–(49), the plural marker appears on the (last) modifier (51).

With respect to number marking, there is a similar pattern in other Kurdish varieties (i.e., Sorani and Kermanshahi Kurdish), where we see the mobility of the plural marker. Let us consider this cross-dialectal evidence before attempting to provide an analysis for the Laki pattern.

The plural marker in Sorani Kurdish is -ān, and the definite marker is -aka. In (52), we have an indefinite DP and the plural marker remains on the noun. By contrast, in (53) which is a definite DP, the plural marker appears on the modifier next to the definite marker.Footnote 17 Examples are adapted from Salehi (Reference Salehi2018: 62, 30).

In Kermanshahi Kurdish, we see a similar pattern. In this variety, -aga, and -eyl encode definiteness and plurality respectively, as in (54)–(55).

In a modified non-definite (generic or indefinite) noun phrase, as in the generic DP (56), the plural marker appears on the noun. By contrast, when the noun is definite, the plural marker appears in the phrase-final position and is realized with the definite marker, forming a single affix (i.e., -agān), as in (57). Importantly, here the plural markers used in generic and definite DPs are clearly distinct.

The above facts raise a question about the interaction of definiteness and number marking. These observations motivate an analysis requiring a different realization of number in plural definite DPs compared to its realization in non-definite DPs (i.e., generic and indefinite). In section 6.2, we will see that this pattern is sensitive only to anaphoricity.Footnote 18 Leaving these details aside, in what follows, I provide an account for the interaction of number and definiteness.

With respect to the Laki, Sorani and Kermanshahi facts, firstly following Delfitto and Schroten (Reference Delfitto and Schroten1991), Rouveret (Reference Rouveret1991), Ritter (Reference Ritter1992), among others, I assume that Num is a functional projection. In the context of the definite DP, I argue that Num undergoes head movement to the anaphoric definite D. In addition to the [uN] feature that triggers Agreement with N, the (anaphoric) definite D is assumed to have a strong [uNUM] feature. This strong feature triggers the movement of Num to D. Furthermore, I propose that two heads (Num and D) after the head movement of Num, are fused and realized as one single head at PF.Footnote 19 Some previous accounts have presented proposals along the same lines. For example, regarding Swedish definite DPs, Julien (Reference Julien2003, Reference Julien2005) proposes uninterpretable phi-features on D that are checked against the interpretable phi-features of Number. This Agreement has been argued to involve the head movement of Number to a definite projection and ultimately to the specifier of the DP (for discussion, see Julien Reference Julien2003). Furthermore, similar facts from another Iranian language, Persian, provide further supporting evidence for the special interaction of number and definite marking which is absent in indefinite DPs. Based on several pieces of evidence, Ghomeshi (Reference Ghomeshi2003) argues that plural nouns in Persian have a definite interpretation, unless the noun is marked with an indefinite suffix. Leaving the details of this discussion aside, Persian brings an important piece of evidence for the claim that number and definite marking have a particular interaction. As briefly discussed in section 2, nouns in Persian are marked for definiteness by the phrase-final suffix -e, as illustrated in the following examples.

Number is marked with the suffix - (and -ā in colloquial speech). In indefinite modified DPs, the plural marker appears on the noun, as shown in (60). By contrast, in a modified definite DP (61), the plural marker appears in the phrase-final position and the definite suffix -e disappears. In such DPs, the definiteness and number both are expressed by the plural marker. Ghomeshi considers this plural marker as an allomorph of the definite marker (i.e., the plural counterpart to the singular definite marker -e). These facts from Persian lend cross-linguistic support for the interaction of number and definite marking leading to their single realization in definite DPs.

I propose the following structure for the head movement analysis of Number in Laki which could also be extended to Kermanshahi and Sorani Kurdish varieties, examined above.Footnote 20 After head movement of Num to D, D and Num form a complex D head, which is realized as a plural definite suffix at PF.

  1. (62) Number head movement in definite DPs

Note that the strong unvalued [uNUM] feature is limited to the plural anaphoric definite DP (i.e., when D is [DEF]anaphoric). As the empirical observations of other Iranian languages suggested, head movement of Num to D does not seem to occur in indefinite or generic DPs. I posit that in plural indefinite DPs (i.e., D having the valued [DEF]indefinite feature), D lacks the [uNUM] feature. Therefore, in such DPs, Num remains low and does not undergo head movement to D, illustrated in the Laki examples (46)–(47) above and in the diagram given below.

  1. (63) Number in indefinite DPs

In the next section, I consider a wider range of data involving demonstratives. I extend the proposed analyses to account for definite marking and the position of number in DPs with demonstratives.

6. Demonstratives

In this section, I introduce a different type of definite feature – namely deictic definite. The facts regarding the demonstratives, presented in this section, support the claim that demonstratives can express two types of definiteness: deictic and anaphoric. Furthermore, the demonstrative facts crucially show that double definiteness and Num head movement both are limited to the anaphoric definite DP, as argued in sections 5.1 and 5.3.

There are two DP initial demonstratives in Laki, i ‘this’ and a ‘that’. As shown in (64)–(67), in DPs with demonstratives, a DP final suffix (i.e., -a) obligatorily appears. Similar to the DP final definite marker, this affix is not syllable sensitive. However, in contrast to the DP final definite marker, this affix does not receive the primary stress of the DP. Furthermore, in (64)–(67), we do not see the definite agreement marker on the noun (i.e., the DP internal definite marker). I intentionally put a question mark in the glossing, until the nature of this phrase-final -a is identified.

In spite of the difference in the stress assignment, I argue that the DP final suffix in DPs with demonstratives is an allomorph of the DP final definite marker expressing a different type of definite property – namely deictic definite. The deictic property signals an immediately accessible reference to the hearer/reader (i.e., direct reference). From a cross-linguistic perspective, taking this phrase-final suffix as a definite marker looks well-motivated. In a number of languages (e.g., Hungarian, Javanese, Greek and Romanian), demonstratives obligatorily appear with a definite element, as illustrated in (68–71). Furthermore, see Roberts (Reference Roberts, van Deemter and Kibble2002), Wolter (Reference Wolter2006), Elbourne (Reference Elbourne2008), Schwarz (Reference Schwarz2009), among others, for the analyses that have considered noun phrases with demonstratives to be definite across languages.

Crucially, demonstratives show another pattern. This pattern is similar to the pattern observed with the (anaphoric) definite DPs (i.e., definite DPs without demonstratives, analyzed in section 5.1). As shown below in (72)–(73), the similarity is that a definite agreement appears on the monosyllabic noun, and the DP final definite marker is stressed (in bold). It should be highlighted that this pattern is restricted to DPs with the demonstrative a ‘that’ and not i ‘this’. Examples (74)–(75) show that we cannot have the equivalent pattern in modified DPs with the demonstrative i ‘this’. Instead, the pattern that we consistently see with the demonstrative i ‘this’ is the pattern we observed above in (64)–(67).

I argue that demonstratives in Laki are definite expressions and have both deictic and anaphoric references. However, the anaphoricity is argued to be restricted to the demonstrative that, leading to the pattern in (72)–(73). To illustrate the semantic difference between anaphoric and deictic properties in Laki more clearly, consider the following contexts. In (76), we have the demonstrative that. When the demonstrative is used in its anaphoric sense, it has to refer to a tree that is not physically present but known to the speaker and hearer due to some prior knowledge or due to a previous indication of that particular tree in the conversation. With this interpretation, as indicated above, the DP final definite marker receives the primary stress of the DP, and the pattern of double definiteness is obtained. If the demonstrative is used in its deictic sense, the tree has to be physically present (e.g., the speaker and the hearer can both see a tree that is in their view.). With this interpretation, as mentioned before, the DP final definite marker does not receive the primary stress and there is no definite agreement on the noun. The demonstrative this, as in (77), can only express the deictic sense and hence illustrates the deictic pattern.Footnote 21

Based on the observations given above, I refer to the demonstrative that in its anaphoric sense as the anaphoric demonstrative. For the rest of the discussion in this section, I will focus on the anaphoricity of DPs with the demonstrative that and their semantic and syntactic similarities to the anaphoric definite DPs without demonstratives, examined in section 5.1. For more clarity in the discussion here, I consistently refer to the definite DPs without demonstratives as “anaphoric definite DPs without demonstratives”. One piece of evidence supporting the semantic similarity between anaphoric definite DPs without demonstratives and DPs with the anaphoric demonstrative that is the fact that in terms of their meaning, the DPs with the anaphoric demonstrative are totally interchangeable with anaphoric definite DPs without demonstratives. That is, in DPs with the anaphoric demonstrative, the use of the demonstrative that is optional. By contrast, such optionality is not possible with DPs having the deictic demonstratives. Furthermore, as indicated above, there are some syntactic and prosodic similarities between anaphoric definite DPs without demonstratives and DPs with the anaphoric demonstrative that. As already shown, the pattern of double definiteness is obtained in both DPs. Also, as indicated earlier, with the anaphoric demonstrative that, the DP final definite marker similarly receives the primary stress. Importantly, prosodic properties such as contrastive accent or pitch have been previously argued to be mechanisms used to express a greater degree of referentiality (Cornish Reference Cornish, Nilsen, Appiah Amfo and Borthen2007). Anaphoric expressions are known for their strong level of familiarity or referentiality regrading an entity known to the speaker and the hearer (Roberts Reference Roberts, van Deemter and Kibble2002, Schwarz Reference Schwarz2009). As such, one can posit that the fact that the DP final definite marker receives the primary stress in the anaphoric context, as opposed to the deictic context (or indefinite contexts), is an indication of the strong level of referentiality that is involved in anaphoric definite DPs. In this regard, DPs with the anaphoric demonstrative that are identical to definite anaphoric DPs without demonstratives. This is in contrast with DPs having the deictic demonstratives whose DP final definite marker does not receive the primary stress. The pattern of number marking also lends support for another syntactic similarity between anaphoric definite DPs without demonstratives and DPs with the anaphoric demonstrative. As we will see in section 6.2, in their number marking, both DPs show an identical pattern.

These observations generally support the claim that Laki demonstratives can have either deictic or anaphoric references. In the anaphoric sense, the DPs, with or without the anaphoric demonstrative, show similar patterns. These similarities require the postulation of a D head with the same featural properties in the two anaphoric DPs.

It is worth noting that the anaphoricity of demonstratives has been argued in previous works. As argued by Lyons (Reference Lyons1999), Alexiadou et al. (Reference Alexiadou, Haegeman and Stavrou2007), Schwarz (Reference Schwarz2009), Cornish (Reference Cornish2011), among many others for several languages, beside the deictic property, demonstratives can express anaphoricity. In some languages, the importance of the use of demonstratives as anaphoric expressions is even more substantial. For example, in Mandarin, the anaphoric definiteness is expressed only by the use of a demonstrative (see Jenks Reference Jenks2018 for discussion).

6.1 Accounting for demonstratives: Selection and Agreement

In light of these observations, I consider demonstratives as definite elements, and distinguish them in terms of the definite features they express. In Laki, the demonstrative i ‘this’ can express only the deictic definite property (i.e., [DEF]deictic). The demonstrative a ‘that’ can be the expression of both deictic and anaphoric definite properties (i.e., [DEF]deictic and [DEF]anaphoric).Footnote 22

Furthermore, I propose a distinction between the DP final definite markers as anaphoric versus deictic. As argued in section 5.1, the valued definiteness feature on the anaphoric definite D is assumed to be [DEF]anaphoric, and the valued definiteness feature on the deictic definite D is assumed to be [DEF]deictic. I also propose a selectional requirement for Laki demonstratives. Thus, the demonstratives are claimed to select for a definite DP complement. The deictic demonstratives (i.e. i ‘this’ and the deictic a ‘that’) select for a deictic definite DP, and the anaphoric demonstrative selects for an anaphoric definite DP. The anaphoric versus deictic type of the DP is determined by the valued definiteness feature on its D head (having either [DEF]anaphoric or [DEF]deictic). Furthermore, I take the demonstratives to be merged high (following Julien Reference Julien2005 for Scandinavian). In this configuration, the demonstrative holds a selectional relation with its DP complement. It should be noted that under several approaches, demonstratives are taken to be specifiers. Some authors in particular have argued for a low merge position for demonstratives. For example, for Modern Greek, Bernstein (Reference Bernstein1997), Brugè (Reference Brugè and Cinque2002), Giusti (Reference Giusti and Cinque2002) and Alexiadou et al. (Reference Alexiadou, Haegeman and Stavrou2007) propose that demonstratives are merged in the specifier of a low functional category. Here, however, given the obligatory definiteness of the DP, as well as the identical nature of the definite feature on D and Dem, a selectional account that takes demonstratives as high elements seems to be more motivated. The following diagrams illustrate the selectional requirement in DPs with both types of demonstratives.

  1. (78) Demonstratives selecting for definite DPs

As indicated in sections 5.1 and 5.2, given the strong referentiality of anaphoric definite DPs, the unvalued [uN] feature is only assumed for the anaphoric definite D. As such, D is considered as the probe establishing a downward Agreement with the noun. Moreover, nouns are always assumed to merge with a [uDEF] feature which is valued as a reflex of the probe by D, against the valued definiteness feature on D. These assumptions along with the selectional requirement of the demonstratives (78) predict 1) the establishment of Agreement in a DP selected by the anaphoric demonstrative, and 2) the failure of Agreement in a DP selected by the deictic demonstrative. The failure of Agreement in the context of the deictic demonstrative is due to the absence of the uninterpretable [uN] feature on the deictic D and hence the lack of probing by the deictic D (hence no reflex). As already shown in examples given in this section, these predictions are borne out. While the pattern of double definiteness is obtained with the anaphoric demonstrative, it is not obtained with the deictic demonstrative. The analysis proposed for the anaphoric definite DPs in section 5.1 is extended to the DPs with the anaphoric demonstrative (79a). Regarding the deictic definite DPs, similar to the account proposed for the indefinite DPs in section 5.2, I posit that in the absence of Agreement probed by D, there is no reflex. As such, the [uDEF] feature on the noun remains unvalued. To avoid the ill-formedness of the DP, the [uDEF] feature on the noun is deleted, as shown in (79b) (along the lines of Preminger Reference Preminger2009, Reference Preminger2011).

  1. (79) a. Deriving double definiteness  b. The failure of Agreement

In the following section, I examine the pattern of number marking in the context of demonstratives. The facts show that number marking in DPs with the anaphoric demonstrative that is completely identical to the pattern of number marking in the anaphoric definite DP without demonstrative. The data provides support for the claim that the strong [uNUM] feature on the anaphoric definite D consistently leads to the Num head movement to D in anaphoric definite DPs.

6.2 Number marking in the context of demonstratives

In section 5.3, I argued for the head movement analysis of Num in the definite context triggered by the strong [uNUM] feature on D. Let us reconsider the distribution of number in the context of demonstratives.

The distribution of number in the context of demonstratives depends on the anaphoric-deictic distinction of the demonstratives. In (80)–(81), the demonstratives have the deictic reference. In this context, the plural marker -al appears on the noun. By contrast, in (82), the demonstrative a ‘that’ has the anaphoric reference, and the plural marker is realized phrase-finally, identical to the pattern observed in the definite plural DP in section 5.3.

Considering the head movement analysis for number marking, the patterns in (80)–(82), raise the question of what prevents the movement of number to D in the deictic environment. With respect to this data set, I postulate that the strong [uNUM] feature is limited to the anaphoric D (i.e., the definite DP without demonstrative and the DP with the anaphoric demonstrative). The following examples show the distribution of number in definite and indefinite DPs (83)–(84), as already shown in section 5.3.

These examples suggest that the number distribution in DPs with the deictic demonstratives (80)–(81) patterns with the expression of number in indefinite DPs (84) and the number marking in DPs with the anaphoric demonstrative (82) patterns with the number expression in definite DPs without demonstrative (83). Crucially, the latter follows from the fact that these two DPs are both anaphoric definite and hence their D head is assumed to be identical and have a strong [uNUM] feature triggering the movement of Num to D.

In this study, the head movement of Num and double definiteness both were shown to be obtained only in anaphoric definite DPs. This finding raises an interesting question of why such patterns arise only in DPs with the anaphoric definite reference. This calls for an examination of wider cross-linguistic data, to explore if beyond a parametric account, the effects of anaphoricity could be observed and explained in a larger empirical scope.

7. Conclusion

In this article, I examined definiteness along with other nominal projections influencing definite marking. I argued that despite the surface similarities of the double definiteness in Scandinavian and Laki, their definite marking diverges in some empirical aspects. I approached Laki double definiteness through an Agreement account. The Agreement was claimed to be established only in anaphoric definite DPs and was argued to fail in deictic definite and indefinite DPs due to the lack of probing by D. The failure of Agreement in such DPs was argued to be the result of the absence of the unvalued [uN] feature on the indefinite and the deictic definite D.

Furthermore, I argued for two types of definite feature associated with the Laki demonstratives: [DEF]deictic and [DEF]anaphoric. The demonstrative i ‘this’ was argued to express only the deictic definite feature. By contrast, the demonstrative a ‘that’ was argued to express both definite features. Regarding the co-occurrence of demonstratives and the DP final definite marker, I proposed a selectional requirement accounting for the obligatory co-occurrence of the demonstratives and the DP final definite marker -a. Furthermore, in the context of demonstratives, the D head was also argued to express two definite features (i.e., deictic and anaphoric). The insertion of either of these DP final definite markers was argued to align with the definite feature expressed by the demonstrative. I also argued that the pattern of double definiteness is obtained only in DPs with the anaphoric demonstrative. This pattern provided support for the generalization that double definiteness is restricted to the anaphoricity of the DP. In addition, I proposed a strong [uNUM] feature on the anaphoric D, leading to Num head movement to D only in the anaphoric definite DP.

The patterns investigated in this article generally showcase the contribution of the anaphoricity to the structure of the DP. Furthermore, the divergence of Laki definiteness from the previously attested patterns contributes to our cross-linguistic understanding of definiteness and the arrays of its possible patterns in a broader empirical domain.

Footnotes

First and foremost, I thank my advisor, Arsalan Kahnemuyipour, for his support and insightful advice at several stages of this work. Thanks also to Susana Bejar and Nicholas LaCara for their constructive feedback on earlier versions of this article. Heartfelt thanks to the native speakers of Laki and Kermanshahi Kurdish: Morteza Ghobadi, Mahdieh Ghobadifard and Koorosh Ariyaee for their help and support. I sincerely thank the three anonymous CJL reviewers for their critical reading and valuable suggestions which greatly improved my manuscript.

1 Under some classifications, Laki is separated from southern Kurdish. However, here, following much of the dialectal studies (e.g., McCarus Reference McCarus and Windfuhr2009, Dabir-Moghaddam Reference Dabir-Moghaddam2013), I am considering Laki as a southern Kurdish variety. The data in this article is based on the variety of Laki which is spoken in the city of Kuhdasht in the western part of the Lorestan province of Iran (Taghipour Reference Taghipour2017).

2 Abbreviations: def: definite; dur: durative; ez: ezafe; indef: indefinite; pl: plural; prs: present; sbj: subject agreement; sg: singular; we: weak; neu: neuter.

3 The following examples illustrate the pattern in Norwegian (i and ii) (Anderssen Reference Anderssen2007: 252) and Faroese (iii and iv) (Schoorlemmer Reference Schoorlemmer2012: 109).

4 The absence of these definite suffixes does not lead to an indefinite reading, as indefinite DPs are marked with the phrase-final suffix -i. I will address indefinite DPs fully under section 5.2.

5 Kermanshahi and Sorani Kurdish belong to the southern and central branches of Kurdish language family, respectively. Recall that Laki is southern Kurdish.

6 With respect to Sorani Kurdish (22), some previous proposals (e.g., Karimi Reference Karimi2007) have considered the DP internal definite marker as a linking element (a.k.a. ezafe) appearing between the noun and its modifier, which inflects for definiteness in definite DPs. I will return to this discussion in section 4 and argue that this assumption is not viable for Laki.

7 In section 3, compared to the pattern of Scandinavian, I reject the basic idea of taking the Laki DP internal definite marker as the realization of a distinct syntactic projection.

8 There is debate over the nature of the definite suffix in Scandinavian. Some authors have taken it as a functional head; that is, Art (Santelmann Reference Santelmann1993), or n (Julien Reference Julien2003), a bound morpheme base-generated on the noun or in D (Delsing Reference Delsing1993), a dissociated morpheme inserted at PF (Embick and Noyer Reference Embick and Noyer2001).

9 Adjectives in Scandinavian inflect for definiteness, gender and number. The definite inflection (a.k.a. weak inflection) can be seen on adjectives in examples (4) and (26) and (ii) and (iv) in footnote 3. Definiteness in (4) and (26) is marked with the vowel -a on the adjective gaml. Adjectives in (ii) and (iv) are modified and hence hyphenated and glossed for the definite inflection. Gender and number are marked on adjectives in indefinite DPs (i.e., strong inflection).

10 Since Kayne (Reference Kayne1994), the distinction between specifiers and adjuncts has been lost for some scholars, leading to the placement of APs in the specifiers of functional projections above NP; for example, Cinque (Reference Cinque2005, Reference Cinque2010). The detailed theoretical distinctions between these two possible positions for APs are not the concern of the present study.

11 For more discussion on Scandinavian double definiteness see Delsing (Reference Delsing1988); Svenonius (Reference Svenonius and Holmberg1993); Börjars (Reference Börjars1994, Reference Börjars1998); Börjars and Donohue (Reference Börjars and Donohue2000); Hankamer and Mikkelsen (Reference Hankamer and Mikkelsen2002, Reference Hankamer and Mikkelsen2005); Anderssen (Reference Anderssen2007); Faarlund (Reference Faarlund2009); LaCara (Reference LaCara2011); Schoorlemmer (Reference Schoorlemmer2012).

12 In some varieties of Sorani and depending on the orthography, the variant -eke is used.

13 The observations in this section raise the possibility that in a diachronic scale, Laki might have developed differently and have undergone reanalysis in its ezafe construction. What we synchronically see as a definite construction might have originated from an ezafe construction. If it is the case, the question that arises is how ezafe has developed differently in two sister Kurdish languages. This is a question that I leave aside in this study.

14 The postulation of an uninterpretable/unvalued [uN] feature on non-nominal elements (e.g., verbs or adpositions) has also been considered in a number of places (see Adger Reference Adger2003, Kinsella Reference Kinsella2009, among others).

15 In my analyses, I consistently assume a downward Agree (i.e., the probe c-commands the goal), as opposed to upward Agree (i.e., the goal c-commands the probe); see Wurmbrand (Reference Wurmbrand2012), Zeijlstra (Reference Zeijlstra2012) and Bjorkman and Zeijlstra (Reference Bjorkman and Zeijlstra2014) for a discussion of upward Agree.

16 Looking at cross-linguistic data, we observe that the expression of definiteness via agreement, concord or spreading is a well-known phenomenon; see Simpson (Reference Simpson2001); Aboh (Reference Aboh2004); Kramer (Reference Kramer2009); Norris (Reference Norris and Choi2012, Reference Norris2014), a.o. This raises the question of why such patterns are widely observed with definite DPs, compared to their indefinite counterparts; this asymmetry across languages I leave for a future research.

17 I will argue later that in definite DPs, the definite marker and the plural marker undergo fusion. Therefore, in example (53), the plural and the definite affixes are not hyphenated. Instead, they are considered as one affix.

18 The definite DPs of Sorani and Kermanshahi Kurdish varieties cited here are anaphoric definite.

19 One can provide an alternative explanation through which a portmanteau suffix realizes the [plural definite] feature as an allomorph of the definite D. Under this assumption, we do not need to assume a fusion operation. Regardless of the realization of D, we still need to explain why number is not realized in situ; that is, under Num. The head movement analysis seems to be one appropriate explanation for this problem.

20 This analysis could also be extended to Persian number marking. The application of this analysis to Persian facts requires the assumption that number in Persian is introduced under a NumP (contra Ghomeshi Reference Ghomeshi2003) that moves to D. Moreover, in contrast to Laki, in Persian plural definite DPs, the definite marker disappears and the number marker expresses both definiteness and number.

21 The anaphoric use of demonstratives in other varieties of Kurdish has been described in previous works; see MacKenzie (Reference MacKenzie1961) and Haig (Reference Haig, Yap, Grunow-Hårsta and Wrona2011).

22 There seems to be a constrained use of the demonstrative this which appears to be anaphoric and seems to have a limited use. Consider a speaker talking about a smart boy physically absent and unknown to the hearer. The hearer asks ‘where does this smart boy study?’, as shown in the following example in (i).

In this context, although kor ‘boy’ is not physically present, the demonstrative i ‘this’ is used. However, there is no definite agreement and the DP final definite marker is unstressed, like what we have seen in the deictic use of the demonstratives. This raises the question of whether there is a semantic difference between these seemingly anaphoric uses which can justify the absence of the definite agreement and the deictic pattern of stress assignment. I leave a closer examination of this question to future research.

References

Abney, Steven. 1987. The English noun phrase in its sentential aspect. Doctoral dissertation, Massachusetts Institute of Technology.Google Scholar
Aboh, Enoch O. 2004. Topic and focus within D. Linguistics in the Netherlands 21(1): 112.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Adger, David. 2003. Core syntax: A minimalist approach. Oxford Core Linguistics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Alexiadou, Artemis, Haegeman, Liliane, and Stavrou, Melita. 2007. Noun phrases in the generative perspective. Berlin: Mouton De Gruyter.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anderssen, Merete. 2007. The acquisition of compositional definiteness in Norwegian. Nordlyd 34(3): 252275.Google Scholar
Atlamaz, Ümit. 2016. Merging modifiers of an NP before its arguments. In Proceedings of the 33rd West Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics, 47–56. Somerville: Cascadilla Proceedings project.Google Scholar
Bernstein, Judy B. 1993. Topics in the syntax of nominal structure across Romance. Doctoral dissertation, The City University of New York.Google Scholar
Bernstein, Judy B. 1997. Demonstratives and reinforcers in Romance and Germanic languages. Lingua 102: 87113.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bjorkman, Bronwyn, and Zeijlstra, Hedde. 2014. Upward agree is superior. Manuscript.Google Scholar
Börjars, Kersti. 1994. Swedish double determination in a European perspective. Nordic Journal of Linguistics 17(2): 219252.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Börjars, Kersti. 1998. Feature distribution in Swedish noun phrases. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Börjars, Kersti, and Donohue, Mark. 2000. Much ado about nothing: Features and zeroes in Germanic noun phrases. Studia Linguistica 54(3): 309353.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brugè, Laura. 2002. The position of demonstartives in the extended nominal projection. In Functional structure in DP and IP, ed. Cinque, Guglielmo, 1553. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Chomsky, Noam. 1995. The minimalist program. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Chomsky, Noam. 2000. Minimalist inquiries. In Step by step: Essays on minimalist syntax in honor of Howard Lasnik, ed. Martin, Roger, Michaels, David, and Uriagareka, Juan, 89156. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Chomsky, Noam. 2001. Derivation by phase. In Ken Hale: A life in language, ed. Kenstowicz, Michael, 152. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Cinque, Guglielmo. 2005. Deriving Greenberg's universal 20 and its exceptions. Linguistic Inquiry 36(3): 315332.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cinque, Guglielmo. 2010. The syntax of adjectives: A comparative study. No 57 in LI Monographs. Cambridge: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cornish, Francis. 2007. English demonstratives: Discourse deixis and anaphora. A discourse-pragmatic account. In Interpreting utterances: Pragmatics and its interfaces––Essays in honour of Thorstein Fretheim, ed. Nilsen, Randi Alice, Appiah Amfo, Nana Aba, and Borthen, Kaja, 147166. Oslo: Novus Press.Google Scholar
Cornish, Francis. 2011. Indexical reference within a discourse context: Anaphora, deixis, “anadeixis” and ellipsis. Journée d'Etude Ellipse et anaphore≫, 131 Institut Charles V/Université Paris.Google Scholar
Dabir-Moghaddam, Mohammad. 2013. Typology of Iranian languages. Tehran: SAMT.Google Scholar
Delfitto, Denis, and Schroten, Jan. 1991. Bare plurals and the number affix in DP. Probus 3(2): 155185.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Delsing, Lars-Olof. 1988. The Scandinavian noun phrase. Working Papers in Scandinavian Syntax 42: 5779.Google Scholar
Delsing, Lars-Olof. 1993. The internal structure of noun phrases in the Scandinavian languages. Doctoral dissertation, University of Lund.Google Scholar
Elbourne, Paul. 2008. Demonstratives as individual concepts. Linguistics and Philosophy 31(4): 409466.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Embick, David, and Noyer, Rolf. 2001. Movement operations after syntax. Linguistic Inquiry 32(4): 555595.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Faarlund, Jan Terje. 2009. On the history of definiteness marking in Scandinavian. Journal of Linguistics 45(3): 617639.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ghomeshi, Jila. 1997. Non-projecting nouns and the ezafe construction in Persian. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 15: 729788.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ghomeshi, Jila. 2003. Plural marking, indefiniteness, and the noun phrase. Studia Linguistica 57(2): 4774.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Giusti, Giuliana. 2002. The functional structure of noun phrases: A bare phrase structure approach. In Functional structure in DP and IP: the cartography of syntactic structures, ed. Cinque, Guglielmo, vol. 1, 5490. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Haig, Geoffrey. 2011. Linker, relativizer, nominalizer, tense-particle. In Nominalization in Asian languages: Diachronic and typological perspectives, ed. Yap, Foong Ha, Grunow-Hårsta, Karen, and Wrona, Janick, Typological Studies in Language, vol. 96, 363390. Amsterdam: John Benjamins Publishing.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hankamer, Jorge, and Mikkelsen, Line. 2002. A morphological analysis of definite nouns in Danish. Journal of Germanic Linguistics 14(2): 137175.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hankamer, Jorge, and Mikkelsen, Line. 2005. When movement must be blocked: A reply to Embick and Noyer. Linguistic Inquiry 36(1): 85125.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jenks, Peter. 2018. Articulated definiteness without articles. Linguistic Inquiry 49(3): 501536.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Julien, Marit. 2003. Double definiteness in Scandinavian. Proceedings of the 19th Scandinavian Conference of Linguistics 31(1): 230244.Google Scholar
Julien, Marit. 2005. Nominal phrases from a Scandinavian perspective. Philadelphia: John Benjamins.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kahnemuyipour, Arsalan. 2014. Revisiting the Persian ezafe construction: A roll-up movement analysis. Lingua 150: 124.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Karimi, Simin, and Brame, Michael. 2012. A generalization concerning the EZAFE construction in Persian. Linguistic Analysis 38(1): 111144.Google Scholar
Karimi, Yadgar. 2007. Kurdish ezafe construction: Implications for DP structure. Lingua 117: 21592177.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kayne, Richard S. 1994. The antisymmetry of syntax, Linguistic Inquiry Monographs, vol. 25. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Kinsella, Anna R. 2009. Language evolution and syntactic theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kramer, Ruth. 2009. Definite markers, Phi-features and agreement: A morphosyntactic investigation of the Amharic DP. Doctoral dissertation, University of California, Santa Cruz.Google Scholar
LaCara, Nicholas. 2011. A definite problem: The morphosyntax of double definiteness in Swedish. In Morphology at Santa Cruz: Papers in honor of Jorge Hankamer, 55–83.Google Scholar
Larson, Richard, and Yamakido, Hiroko. 2008. Ezafe and the deep position of nominal modifiers. In Adjectives and adverbs: Syntax, semantics and discourse, ed. McNally, Louise and Kennedy, Christopher, 4370. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lyons, Christopher. 1999. Definiteness. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
MacKenzie, David Neil. 1961. The origins of Kurdish. Transactions of the Philological Society 60(1): 6886.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCarus, Ernest N. 2009. Kurdish. In The Iranian languages, ed. Windfuhr, Gernot. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Norris, Mark. 2012. Towards an analysis of concord (in Icelandic). In Proceedings of the 29th West Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics, ed. Choi, Jaehoon et al. , 205213. Somerville, MA: Cascadilla Proceedings Project.Google Scholar
Norris, Mark. 2014. A theory of nominal concord. Doctoral dissertation, University of California, Santa Cruz.Google Scholar
Olsen, Susan. 1989. AGR(eement) in the German noun phrase. In Syntactic phrase structure phenomena in noun phrases and sentences, ed. Christa Bhatt, Elisabeth Löbel and Schmidt, Claudia. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.Google Scholar
Preminger, Omer. 2009. Breaking agreements: Distinguishing agreement and clitic-doubling by their failures. Linguistic Inquiry 40(2): 619666.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Preminger, Omer. 2011. Agreement as a fallible operation. Doctoral dissertation, Massachusetts Institute of Technology, Cambridge, MA.Google Scholar
Ritter, Elizabeth. 1992. Cross-linguistic evidence for number phrase. Canadian Journal of Linguistics/Revue canadienne de linguistique 37(2): 197218.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Roberts, Craige. 2002. Demonstratives as definites. In Information sharing: Reference and presupposition in language generation and interpretation, ed. van Deemter, K. and Kibble, R., 89106. Stanford: CSLI Press.Google Scholar
Roberts, Craige. 2003. Uniqueness in definite noun phrases. Linguistics and philosophy 26(3): 287350.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rouveret, Alain. 1991. Functional categories and agreement. The Linguistic Review 8: 353388.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Salehi, Ali. 2018. Constraints on izafa in Sorani Kurdish. Master's thesis, University of Kentucky.Google Scholar
Samiian, Vida. 1994. The ezafe construction: Some implications for the theory of X-bar morphosyntax. In Persian studies in North America, ed. Marashi, Mehdi. Bethesda, MD: Iranbooks.Google Scholar
Samvelian, Pollet. 2008. The ezafe as a head-marking inflectional affix: evidence from Persian and Kurmanji Kurdish. In Aspects of iranian linguistics, ed. Karimi, Simin, Samiian, Vida, and Stilo, Donald. Newcastle: Cambridge Scholars Publishing.Google Scholar
Santelmann, Lynn. 1992. Den-support: An analysis of double determiners in Swedish. In Papers from the workshop on the Scandinavian noun phrase, ed. Anders Holmberg, 100–118.Google Scholar
Santelmann, Lynn. 1993. The distribution of double determiners in Swedish. Studia Linguistica 47: 154176.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schoorlemmer, Erik. 2012. Definiteness marking in Germanic: morphological variations on the same syntactic theme. The Journal of Comparative Germanic Linguistics 15(2): 107156.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schwarz, Florian. 2009. Two types of definites in natural language. Doctoral dissertation, University of Massachusetts Amherst.Google Scholar
Simpson, Andrew. 2001. Definiteness agreement and the Chinese DP. Language and Linguistics 2(1): 125156.Google Scholar
Svenonius, Peter. 1993. The distribution of definite marking. In Papers from the workshop on the Scandinavian noun phrase, ed. Holmberg, Anders, 2044. Umea: DGL-UUM.Google Scholar
Svenonius, Peter. 1994. The structural location of the attributive adjective. In Proceedings of the 12th West Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics, ed. Erin Duncan, Donka Farkas, and Philip Spaelti, 439–454.Google Scholar
Szabolcsi, Anna. 1994. The noun phrase. In The syntactic structure of Hungarian, ed. Kiefer, Ferenc and Kiss, Katalin E., 179275. Cambridge: Academic Press.Google Scholar
Taghipour, Sahar. 2017. Laki verbal inflection. Master's thesis, University of Kentucky.Google Scholar
Tahir, Rebwar. 2018. The structure of the DP in Central Kurdish. Doctoral dissertation, Newcastle University.Google Scholar
Thorne, James Peter. 1972. On the notion definite. Foundations of language 8: 562568.Google Scholar
Toosarvandani, Maziar, and van Urk, Coppe. 2014. The syntax of nominal concord: What ezafe in Zazaki shows us. In Proceedings of the 43th North East Linguistic Society, ed. Hsin-Lun Huang, Ethan Poole, and Amanda Rysling, 221–234.Google Scholar
Valois, Daniel. 1991. The internal syntax of DP. Doctoral dissertation, University of California, Los Angeles.Google Scholar
Wolter, Lynsey K. 2006. That's that: The semantics and pragmatics of demonstrative noun phrases. Doctoral dissertation, University of California, Santa Cruz.Google Scholar
Wurmbrand, Susi. 2012. Parasitic participles in Germanic: Evidence for the theory of verb clusters. Taal en Tongval 64: 129156.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zeijlstra, Hedde. 2012. There is only one way to agree. The Linguistic Review 29(3): 491539.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Figure 0

(1)

Figure 1

(3)

Figure 2

(5)

Figure 3

(7)

Figure 4

(12)

Figure 5

(13)

Figure 6

(17)

Figure 7

(19)

Figure 8

(21)

Figure 9

(23)

Figure 10

(25)

Figure 11

(27)

Figure 12

(31)

Figure 13

(32)

Figure 14

(34)

Figure 15

(36)

Figure 16

(40)

Figure 17

(42)

Figure 18

(46)

Figure 19

(52)

Figure 20

(54)

Figure 21

(56)

Figure 22

(58)

Figure 23

(60)

Figure 24

(64)

Figure 25

(68)

Figure 26

(72)

Figure 27

(76)

Figure 28

(80)

Figure 29

(83)