Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-dzt6s Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-23T07:04:04.418Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Prosecuting and Propagating Emotional Harm: The Criminalisation of HIV Nondisclosure in Canada

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 March 2023

Katarina Bogosavljević
Affiliation:
PhD Candidate, Department of Criminology, University of Ottawa, Canada. [email protected]
Jennifer M. Kilty
Affiliation:
Full Professor, Department of Criminology, University of Ottawa, Canada. [email protected]
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

This article explores emotional harm in the context of the criminalization of HIV nondisclosure in Canada. With the exception of Matthew Weait in the United Kingdom, few scholars have examined what harm means in cases of HIV nondisclosure. We conceptualize the harm that follows nondisclosure as an affective response to the “HIV positive Other” and argue that law creates a legal norm about what harm is and feels like in cases of HIV nondisclosure when there is no clear consensus about how harm should be defined. Mobilizing the sociology of emotions literature, we contend that criminalizing HIV nondisclosure engages affective, moral, and criminal censure to regulate the behaviours of people living with HIV/AIDS (PLWH), thus reproducing HIV stigma and propagating emotional harm for PLWH. Canada’s response to HIV nondisclosure should instead involve a transformative justice approach that avoids the harm of criminalization and imprisonment while recognizing the emotional harm experienced by complainants.

Résumé

Résumé

Cet article a pour objet le préjudice émotionnel dans le contexte de la criminalisation de la non-divulgation du VIH au Canada. À l’exception de Matthew Weait au Royaume-Uni, peu d’universitaires ont étudié les significations attribuées aux préjudices dans les cas de non-divulgation du VIH. Dans cet article, nous conceptualisons le préjudice qui découle de la non-divulgation du VIH comme une réponse affective à « l’Autre séropositif » et nous soutenons que le droit canadien crée une norme juridique qui définit restrictivement les préjudices et les manières de ressentir les préjudices dans les cas de non-divulgation du VIH, alors qu’il n’existe pas de consensus clair sur la façon dont ces préjudices doivent être définis. En mobilisant la littérature sur la sociologie des émotions, nous soutenons que la criminalisation de la non-divulgation du VIH a un effet de blâme affectif, moral et criminel visant à réguler les comportements des personnes vivant avec le VIH/SIDA (PVV). Nous montrons d’ailleurs que ce blâme reproduit la stigmatisation du VIH et les préjudices émotionnels chez les PVV. À la lumière de ces implications, nous suggérons que la réponse du Canada à la non-divulgation du VIH devrait plutôt impliquer une approche de justice transformatrice qui évite le préjudice de la criminalisation et de l’emprisonnement tout en reconnaissant les préjudices émotionnels subis par les plaignants.

Type
Articles
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of the Canadian Law and Society Association

Introduction

In Canada, people living with HIV (PLWH) may be criminally charged for failing to disclose their HIV status prior to sex regardless of whether the virus was transmitted (Grant Reference Grant2008). While some countries, including the United Kingdom and certain Australian territories, limit criminalization to cases involving transmission, 36% of Canadian HIV nondisclosure cases involve transmission while 64% involve exposure alone (Hastings et al. Reference Hastings, Massaquoi, Elliott and Mykhalovskiy2022), evincing a national trend toward an overly broad use of criminalization and HIV exceptionalism in law. Canada does not have a specific law that criminalizes nondisclosure, meaning Crown prosecutors use general provisions in the Criminal Code (commonly aggravated sexual assault) to hold PLWH criminally responsible for failing to disclose their HIV-positive serostatus prior to sex (HIV/AIDS Legal Network 2019). Since 1989 at least 206 people in Canada have been charged for HIV nondisclosure. The Supreme Court of Canada (SCC) ruling in R v Cuerrier (1998) established that failing to disclose one’s HIV-positive status constitutes fraud, which vitiates consent since the person did not have the requisite information to give informed consent. The justices in Cuerrier determined that the “harm in question must constitute a significant risk of serious bodily harm” (Grant, Reference Grant2008, 135, emphasis added); however, they did not outline parameters for determining what constitutes a significant risk, leading to vastly different interpretations by the lower courts (MacKinnon and Crompton Reference MacKinnon and Crompton2012). The SCC revisited the issue of HIV nondisclosure in 2012. The majority ruling in Mabior interpreted nondisclosure as continuing to pose a significant risk of bodily harm as set out in Cuerrier, unless the accused had a low viral loadFootnote 1 and used a condom,Footnote 2 which together were said to lower the risk to such a point that there is no “realistic possibility of transmission” (R v Mabior, 2012, para 84).

The Mabior decision advances “a generous approach to the issue of consent and when deceit might vitiate it, an approach that respected the right of women involved to choose whether to have intercourse or not” (R v Mabior, 2012, para 31). Buchanan (Reference Buchanan2015, 1262) suggests this decision problematically concentrates on HIV “when other serious diseases, and other material sexual deceptions, are not crimes” and “transforms otherwise-wanted sex into a violation akin to rape.” In R v Kirkpatrick, the Supreme Court upheld a woman’s right to choose how intercourse is performed, specifically finding that non-consensual removal of or failure to use a condom is sexual assault. Scholars argue that HIV nondisclosure cases have been problematically subsumed under sexual assault provisions in the Criminal Code, resulting in the overcriminalization of PLWH and the “distortion of the law of sexual assault in ways that limit sexual autonomy for complainants” (Grant Reference Grant2020, 8).

In this article, we contend that the criminalization of HIV nondisclosure is an expression of emotional censure toward PLWH and an attempt to protect complainants from the emotional (rather than solely the physical) consequences of HIV nondisclosure. Criminalizing emotional harm reinforces an optimistic attachment to law as an institution that will bring justice and heal the pain associated with said harms. Such an optimistic attachment, however, fails to consider how law itself can be harmful, especially for vulnerable communities. Law struggles to grapple with the relational nature of harm, where the messiness of interpersonal relationshipsFootnote 3 and adversarial process make it even more difficult. By focusing on the emotional harms suffered by the presumed victim in these cases, law negates the emotional and other associated harms felt by PLWH, such as stigma, shame, and ostracization.

In Part I, we outline our conceptualization of the emotional harm that follows HIV nondisclosure. We examine how Canada’s criminal legal approach to HIV nondisclosure defines harm in these cases as an individual experience while failing to account for how harm, especially emotional harm, is socially constituted and felt differently by people depending on their social locations, relational contexts, and power dynamics. Following Feinberg (Reference Feinberg1987), we suggest that while nondisclosure may be classified as a harm, that alone is not a reason to criminalize it; using Feinberg’s mediating maxims, we contend that the emotional harms stemming from HIV nondisclosure are transient; they are minor harms that fall below the threshold of the harm principle for the purposes of criminalization, which in effect causes more harm than it aims to prevent. Part II of this article discusses the emotions that underpin the legal discourses surrounding HIV nondisclosure and how these are connected to perceptions of (im)morality. Part III examines how emotional attachments to criminal law produce harmful effects for PLWH. Here we explore the problematic reliance on the criminal justice system, a notoriously flawed institutional structure, to seek justice and redress for the harms experienced by complainants in HIV nondisclosure cases. In Part IV, we propose a transformative response to this social problem that would avoid the harm of criminalization and imprisonment.

I HIV Nondisclosure and the Criminalization of Emotional Harm

Few scholars have explored what the notion of harm entails—either physically or emotionally/psychically—in HIV nondisclosure cases. One notable exception is Matthew Weait, who questions whether HIV should be treated as a harm by the criminal law. Weait (Reference Weait, Stanton and Quirk2016, 33) argues that “what makes HIV a harm is not HIV per se but the moral context in which the infection occurs.” He defines new HIV infections as nothing more than a naturally occurring phenomenon. Illness and death are the effects of living with HIV and while they can be harmful, they are not in and of themselves justifications for “treating [HIV infection] as necessarily a harm for the purposes of criminal law” (Weait Reference Weait, Stanton and Quirk2016, 34, emphasis in original). We support Weait’s argument that HIV exposure and transmission via nondisclosure are harms that should be addressed, albeit not by the criminal law. Instead, the effects of exposure via nondisclosure are better conceptualized as emotional harm, reflecting Feinberg’s (Reference Feinberg1987) description of mental pains and forms of offendedness that do not meet the criteria for criminal wrongdoing using the harm principle. As Feinberg (Reference Feinberg1987, 46) argues, hurts that include physical pains like aches and stabs, mental pains such as “‘wounded’ feelings, bitterness, keen disappointment, remorse, depression, grief, ‘heartache,’ despair,” other “nonpainful forms of physical unpleasantness [such as] nausea, itches, dizziness, tension,” and nonpainful mental states he classifies as “forms of offendedness,” including, “unpleasant sensations, disgust, shocked sensibilities, irritation, frustration, anxiety, embarrassment, shame, guilt, boredom, and certain kinds of responsive anger and fear” do not constitute harms to be addressed through criminal law. Feinberg’s (Reference Feinberg1987) limited offence principle positions profound offenses such as revulsion and disgust, hurts such as harmless throbs and pangs, and other feelings such as shame and embarrassment, as potential wrongful setbacks to interests that could justify criminal prohibition if they are sufficiently severe or prolonged.

To determine whether the mental distress is severe or prolonged enough to justify criminalization, we turn to Feinberg’s (Reference Feinberg1987) discussion of the linked maxims of the gravity and probability of harm, wherein the greater the gravity of the harm, the less probable the harm needs to be to justify prohibition of the harmful activity. Likewise, the more probable the harm is, the less grave it needs to be to justify criminalization. Our understanding of HIV nondisclosure as emotional harm does not fall under the harm principle, nor does it subscribe to the individualized understanding of harm that law propagates and that Feinberg details in his four-volume work on the harm principle. Instead, we propose that emotional harm be considered as something that is socially constituted and relationally produced and felt.

While we classify HIV exposure via nondisclosure as an emotional harm that falls outside of the harm principle, we cannot deny the disruption to one’s life and sense of self that learning and having to manage an illness that lives “in wait” in one’s body can represent (Ciambrone Reference Ciambrone2001). Accepting Feinberg’s (Reference Feinberg1987) maxims, the continued criminalization of HIV exposure via nondisclosure evinces HIV exceptionalism in Canadian law, given that transmission is rendered less probable through condom use and/or a low viral load (UNAIDS 2018). HIV exposure from nondisclosure is a harm in the emotional sense insofar as it causes feelings of anxiety, fear, and shock until the undisclosed-to-person receives a negative HIV test result, at which point those feelings may subside and feelings of betrayal and anger (may) surface. This kind of emotional harm and the feelings attached to it “reflect the victim’s recognition of the harm that he has suffered [and] if he did not realize that he had [not] been [disclosed to], this would not mean that he did not suffer a harm of this distinctive kind; it would mean that he did not realize that he had been thus harmed.” This raises the question “of whether one who does not care […] about the wrong done has still been harmed by it” (Duff Reference Duff2001, 23) and could explain why it is that heterosexual women are the predominant group that reports instances of HIV nondisclosure to police (Hastings et al. Reference Hastings, Massaquoi, Elliott and Mykhalovskiy2022).

Weait (Reference Weait2007, 112) acknowledges that “incorporeal feelings—of time stolen, of a future damaged, of intimacy soured—which may more adequately reflect the harm experienced, are irrelevant in establishing whether an offence has been committed under the law as it stands.” This sentiment was articulated by Justice Beveridge of the Nova Scotia Court of Appeal in R v CAT, who held that “worry, stress, anger are natural emotions on learning of unwittingly being exposed to HIV. But absent a significant risk of serious bodily harm, satisfied by actual transmission or a realistic possibility of transmission, consent is not vitiated” (R v CAT, 2018 NSCA 13 at para 48). This is a significant departure from the lower court decision in R v CAT (2016 NSSC at para 136–144),Footnote 4 where Justice Hood found C.A.T. not guilty of aggravated sexual assault, but guilty of sexual assault causing bodily harm because of the psychological harm the complainants endured.

Both H.R.H. and M.A.M. testified about their reaction to the news that [C.A.T.] was HIV-positive. H.R.H. said she was scared and shocked, and underwent testing to determine if HIV had been transmitted to her. Between the time she knew that [C.A.T.] was HIV-positive until the time she had the testing done and received the results, H.R.H. suffered psychological harm in that she did not know if she had contracted HIV. I conclude this is not harm of a trifling nature because of the seriousness of HIV as a disease. Nor was the harm of a transient nature. The psychological worry of whether she had contracted HIV continued until she had the results of the testing. This satisfies the requirement of deprivation. […] M.A.M. testified she had one year of testing for HIV. She said it was stressful and she had a fear of the unknown, that is whether she had contracted HIV. She too suffered psychological harm within the meaning of bodily harm. The psychological harm lasted for one year and I conclude therefore it was not trifling or transient.

Justice Hood uses the term psychological harm, which he situates within law’s understanding of bodily harm, to describe the harmful effects of nondisclosure.Footnote 5 Emotional harm is at the heart of Canada’s nondisclosure laws precisely because risk (the realistic possibility of transmission) and emotions are intimately tied and configure one another, something Lupton (Reference Lupton2013, 641) describes as an “emotion-risk assemblage.”

While we support Justice Beveridge’s conclusion that emotional distress does not meet the threshold for vitiating consent, it also shows the court’s attempt to maintain traditional notions of legal objectivity, which denies that emotions are always-already present in legal judgements about risk. In other words, “judgements about what phenomena should be called ‘risks’ are influenced by the social and cultural context and by personal experience, including the embodied sensations that are defined as ‘emotions’” (Lupton Reference Lupton2013, 638). When individuals make decisions about what they deem risky, they do so by cross-referencing these judgements with their own values and morals about what they perceive to be acceptable and harmless and what they perceive to be dangerous or threatening. These appraisals are tied to emotions because “all thought and reason is inevitably emotional” (Lupton Reference Lupton2013, 641). By reducing judgements about right and wrong to experiences of hurt, pain, or suffering, we sustain forms of violence that go unnoticed, unfelt, and unacknowledged (Ahmed Reference Ahmed2004), such as the violence experienced by PLWH who are criminalized for nondisclosure (McClelland Reference McClelland2019). That criminal law is ill-equipped to deal with the nuance and messiness of emotions and feelings, particularly in the context of interpersonal relationships (Eisenberg Reference Eisenberg2015), suggests it is problematic to define a crime based on how it is imagined to make a person feel.

By criminalizing HIV nondisclosure to address emotional harm and protect the HIV-negative body politic, the courts have created a “truth” or norm about what harm is even though there is no consensus on this (Hillyard and Tombs Reference Hillyard and Tombs2007; Pemberton Reference Pemberton2015). Social theorists contend that harm is difficult to define as it is subjectively experienced, meaning what one person experiences as harm may not be harmful to another person (Hillyard and Tombs Reference Hillyard and Tombs2007). Similarly, what law defines as a harm does not reflect a universal experience, but rather the paternalist and moralist norms that buttress legal interpretations of harm. For example, in R v Cuerrier (1998, para 142) Justice Cory stated that criminal law:

Provides a needed measure of protection in the form of deterrence and reflects society’s abhorrence of the self-centered recklessness and the callous insensitivity of the actions of the respondent and those who have acted in a similar manner. The risk of infection and death of partners of HIV-positive individuals is a cruel and ever present reality. Indeed the potentially fatal consequences are far more invidious and graver than many other actions prohibited by the Criminal Code. The risks of infection are so devastating that there is a real and urgent need to provide a measure of protection for those in the position of the complainants. If ever there was a place for the deterrence provided by criminal sanctions it is present in these circumstances. It may well have the desired effect of ensuring that there is disclosure of the risk and that appropriate precautions are taken.

Although written twenty-five years ago, when PLWH experienced more overt and persistent discrimination and HIV treatment was much less effective, Justice Cory’s precedent-setting reasoning in Cuerrier situates PLWH who do not disclose as reckless and callous without acknowledging that people routinely consent to activities that involve varying degrees of risk or that decisions to consent to sex are not always completely informed. Pronouncements that the “risks of infection are so devastating” and “the potentially fatal consequences are far more invidious and graver than many other actions prohibited by the Criminal Code” amplify perceptions of the exceptional nature of HIV harms.

We might consider HIV transmission following nondisclosure to fall under the harm principle. Feinberg (Reference Feinberg1987, 215) contends that harm is produced by “morally indefensible conduct that not only sets back the victim’s interest, but also violates his right.” Certainly, acquiring HIV is a harm in the sense that it sets back a person’s interests; however, returning to Feinberg’s (Reference Feinberg1987) mediating maxim on the gravity of harm, we suggest that, with the scientific advancements that have transformed HIV into a chronic but manageable condition (Loutfy et al. Reference Loutfy, Tyndall, Baril, Julio, Kaul and Hankins2014), criminalization is unjustified. As Stewart (Reference Stewart2010, 32) writes, “conduct should be criminalized only if, on balance, criminalization would do more good than harm, and should not be criminalized if, on balance, criminalization would do more harm than good.” HIV nondisclosure that results in transmission where intent to transmit can be proven may be considered a harm for the purposes of the application of the criminal law. Canadian law currently requires no proof of an intent to harm by way of HIV transmission, the highest mens rea threshold compared with negligence and recklessness. We recognize that the absence of proof of intent is not exceptional as there are other crimes that do not require intent to harm. In nondisclosure cases, the law is only concerned with whether disclosure happened prior to sex so as to justify the fraud requirement in the legal test set out in Cuerrier and confirmed in Mabior (Buchanan Reference Buchanan2015). By focusing on disclosure only in relation to HIV, the law perpetuates HIV/AIDS exceptionalism and reveals the pervasive stickiness of emotions (Ahmed Reference Ahmed2004) like fear and disgust to HIV (Bogosavljević and Kilty Reference Bogosavljević and Kilty2021). These emotional attachments situate nondisclosure as a moral failure that angers, scares, and disgusts, emotions that underpin state efforts to manage, trace, and criminalize individuals perceived to be threats to the body politic.

The concept of “intent” is complex in HIV nondisclosure cases. Consider the notion of constructive intent in which the defendant does not necessarily set about to harm the complainant, but harm nonetheless occurs and is objectively foreseeable. In the context of constructive intent, can the accused objectively foresee harm to the complainant (i.e., a realistic possibility of transmission) if they have unprotected sex but are adhering to their antiretroviral medications regimen and have an undetectable viral load? Alternatively, can the accused objectively foresee harm to the complainant if they wear a condom but do not have a low viral load? Both of these instances show an ethic of care and an intent to protect rather than harm a sexual partner. This reasoning illustrates how the threshold for nondisclosure set out in Mabior uses a problematic notion of harm that is defined in individualistic terms rather than as something that is socially constituted and relationally produced and felt. While there is not always a clear distinction between emotional and physical harm, particularly if the emotional harm of exposure is so severe that there are lasting effects, it is important not to depend on the criminal justice system to address this harm. Instead, “we need to respond to injustice in a way that shows rather than erases the complexity of the relation between violence, power and emotion” (Ahmed Reference Ahmed2004, 196). This might involve turning to the helping professions and those working at AIDS service organizations, who are better equipped to deal with the emotional harm that arises from exposure (a point we develop in Part IV).

Importantly, we do not diminish the emotional harm that is felt by those who have been exposed to HIV. We recognize that this experience could be linked to feelings of trauma—including those borne from other experiences, such as sexual assault. While nondisclosure may be traumatic for some, the emotional harm felt should not be the basis for using criminal law to apportion blame and assign punishment. We contend that emotional harm (e.g., anger, fear, shock, and/or betrayal) should not be inherently understood as a medical issue requiring treatment (by linking trauma to PTSD for example) or as a criminal problem requiring punishment, but rather “as felt experiences that can be mobilized in a range of directions” (Cvetkovich Reference Cvetkovich2003, 47), including alternative legal or non-legal approaches such as restorative justice, transformative justice, or other methods of reconciliation. This allows us to think past law as a mechanism for dealing with the emotional harm that follows HIV nondisclosure to explore how “trauma can be understood as a sign or symptom of a broader systemic problem, a moment in which abstract social systems can actually be felt or sensed” (Cvetkovich Reference Cvetkovich2003, 43). It also forces us to think of harm in a broader sense than what the law or Feinberg’s (Reference Feinberg1987) definition of harm allows, particularly given critiques that the harm principle has been co-opted by conservative liberalism (Harcourt Reference Harcourt1999). Emotional harm is therefore best conceptualized as an aspect of “social harm” that “acts as shorthand to reflect the relations, processes, flows, practices, discourses, actions and inactions that constitute the fabric of our societies which serve to compromise the fulfilment of human needs and in doing so result in identifiable harms” (Pemberton Reference Pemberton2015, 24). Indigenous teachings and forms of justice help us to see how emotional harm is social and relational; for example, Tynan (Reference Tynan2021, 600) suggests that “relationships between ideas or entities [are] an affective force that compels us to not just understand the world as relational, but feel the world as kin… [and] to enact a relational ethos and the responsibilities and accountabilities that accompany it.” This framework reveals that nondisclosure may cause emotional harm and that the criminalization of HIV nondisclosure fosters state-inflicted emotional and physical harm, making it a demonstrably poor deterrence policy and public health strategy.

II The Emotional and Moral Roots of HIV Nondisclosure Criminalization

Criminalization punishes HIV nondisclosure and tries to protect HIV-negative people from the emotional harm that HIV exposure can manifest as well as the guilt and shame that they may experience in cases where they failed to ask about a partner’s status and/or use a condom. The state’s effort to protect in this regard essentializes complainants as inherent victims, while obscuring the fact that criminalization propagates emotional harm, stigma, and ostracism for PLWH. We maintain that this use of criminal law is rooted in cultural and emotional reactions to the ongoing HIV epidemic, which has long-been described as a moralized crisis (Watney Reference Watney1996).

Emotions play an important role in moral thought and behaviour. Cova, Deonna, and Sander (Reference Cova, Deonna and Sander2015) identify five aspects of the relationship between morality and emotions. First, emotions are considered moral when they present their object as having some moral value or disvalue. For example, this occurs when fear constructs its object as dangerous or when guilt presents the person who feels this emotion as responsible for wrongdoing. Second, emotions are integral to moral evaluation, meaning we determine moral actions with our emotions rather than without. Third, emotions are moral to the extent that they have motivational power—they move us to action. For instance, we are motivated to help someone in need because we feel compassion for them. Fourth, emotions are moral “insofar as their cultivation within a certain individual or society contribute [sic] to fostering morality,” the evaluation of which “requires distancing ourselves from the framework of everyday interactions and ‘reactive attitudes’ to reflect on the value judgements that our affective reactions embody” (Cova, Deonna, and Sander Reference Cova, Deonna and Sander2015, 398). Lastly, because emotions can be evaluated as moral or immoral, individuals can be praised or blamed for having them.

It is worth noting that this debate is only relevant with respect to HIV nondisclosure prior to sex; Canada does not criminalize HIV nondisclosure in relation to injection drug use, for example. The presumption is that drug users choose to use drugs with the understanding that drug use is inherently risky and therefore that they consent to the risk posed by sharing injection equipment. In contrast, complainants in HIV nondisclosure cases are situated as unwitting, innocent victims whom the law must protect. Embedded within SCC jurisprudence is the assumption that moral individuals will disclose their HIV seropositivity, which problematically implies that it is safe to engage in unprotected sex when there is no such disclosure. Following Cova, Deonna, and Sander (Reference Cova, Deonna and Sander2015), we can see that law positions disclosure as the only moral course of action, which, when coupled with emotions like anger (at nondisclosure), disgust and fear (of HIV), results in legal characterizations of PLWH who fail to disclose as dangerous, immoral people who must be censured by law (Kilty and Bogosavljević Reference Kilty and Bogosavljević2019; Adam et al. Reference Adam, Corriveau, Elliott, Globerman, English and Rourke2015; Bennett, Draper, and Frith Reference Bennett, Draper and Frith2000; Chalmers Reference Chalmers2002; Kirkup Reference Kirkup2015). That this application of law undermines decades of public health messaging that encourages us to approach every sexual encounter as a potential risk for infection (of HIV or any other sexually transmitted infection) usefully illustrates the disequilibrium in how we apply moral censure to HIV risk (Kilty Reference Kilty, Hundmarch, Orsini and Gagnon2018)Footnote 6 and raises questions as to whose claims are considered credible (Bogosavljević and Kilty Reference Bogosavljević and Kilty2021). Harcourt (Reference Harcourt1999, 131) contends that the harm principle has undergone an ideological shift since the 1960s, where proponents of regulation and prohibition abandoned the rhetoric of legal moralism in favour of the harm principle such that “harm became the critical principle used to police the line between law and morality.”

We suggest that, while it may be morally wrong to lie to a sexual partner, through either active deceit or omission, about one’s HIV serostatus, it is a leap of logic to presume that this moral wrong is a criminal act. This logic reveals that emotions structure our evaluations of the morality of certain behaviours and thus of whether they should be criminalized (Cova, Deonna, and Sander Reference Cova, Deonna and Sander2015). For example, T.S. was convicted of aggravated sexual assault for failing to disclose his serostatus to two women, both of whom tested negative for HIV. Despite the fact that T.S. often, although not always, practised safer sex by using condoms and consistently adhered to his anti-retroviral medication regimen to ensure he maintained an undetectable viral load, the Crown prosecutor argued that T.S. should be handed the severest possible sentence because he “chose” to put two women at risk, one of whom is a single mother while the other was to be an organ donor for her father. In his submission, Mr. Burge stated:

His treatment of these women, it was more of a casual relationship with B.G. but he knew who she was, he knew she was a single mother and chose to put her at risk and deliberately put her at risk through his lies. […] that should result in a denunciatory sentence [in terms of] how he treated B.G. [and] how he treated O.A. […] the factor of O.A.’s father involves an aspect of moral blameworthiness that is […] so serious and […] so egregious that it puts Mr. T.S. among the worst of the worse in the category of moral blameworthiness […]. Mr. T.S. has chosen to put people at risk. […] There are other sexual partners that he has admitted that he doesn’t tell his sexual partners [sic] of his status and it’s my submission that Mr. T.S. will continue to put females at risk as long as he has the opportunity. (R v TS, 2007, decision, 27–28 )

This quote demonstrates the anger and frustration expressed towards T.S. for failing to exercise proper moral judgement with regard to disclosure, even though “for some, silence functions as a technology of self-care” (Kilty, Orsini, and Balogh Reference Kilty, Orsini and Balogh2017). Disclosure is never just about telling someone your HIV status, it “can expose and depersonalize someone, taking things away from them. It gives them the name of the virus and substitutes that for their own name, their own person, even for themselves: ‘I am HIV’” (Squire Reference Squire, Davis and Manderson2014, 152). Given T.S.’s former status as a professional football player in Canada and American immigrant, it is perhaps unsurprising that his was one of the most sensational HIV nondisclosure cases in Canada, complete with extensive hyperbolic and racist media coverage that constructed him as a remorseless sexual predator with an insatiable libido (Kilty and Bogosavljević Reference Kilty and Bogosavljević2019).

The decision to transform the morally wrong act of lying to a sexual partner about one’s serostatus into a criminal wrong reconstructs lying (by act or omission) into reckless indifference by PLWH towards the sexual health of their partners. This discursive move fails to consider the harmful consequences PLWH may face when disclosing their status, including violence, cultural ostracization, and loss of income (Adam et al. Reference Adam, Corriveau, Elliott, Globerman, English and Rourke2015). The perception that all PLWH who do not disclose are indifferent to the health and safety of their sexual partners positions them as immoral, callous, manipulative liars whose liberty should be restricted following the exhibition of society’s collective moral censure via a criminal trial. In contrast, the complainant’s feelings of fear and betrayal (what we classify as emotional harm) reflect moral judgements that motivate some complainants to go to the police. As both Chalmers (Reference Chalmers2002, 162) and Bennett, Draper, and Frith (Reference Bennett, Draper and Frith2000) contend, failing to recognize the distinction between moral and legal obligations around disclosure, exemplified by Canada’s criminalization of both protected and unprotected sex, has the harmful unintended consequence of reducing one’s “incentive to refrain from high-risk activities and to use condoms.” Perhaps more to the point, “the existence of a moral duty is a necessary but not a sufficient condition for invoking the criminal sanction” (Chalmers Reference Chalmers2002, 162).

III Emotional Attachments to and the Harmful Effects of Law

Although the SCC determined that HIV nondisclosure constitutes fraud, we heed Young’s (Reference Young2015) position that this legal reasoning fails to account for the fact that people often engage in sex without disclosing personal, sensitive information about themselves. For example, a criminal record, history of addiction or past sexual behaviour in which they were unfaithful or failed to engage in safer sex practices might dissuade a sexual partner from consenting to sex. Constituting HIV nondisclosure as an act of fraud that vitiates consent while not criminalizing other forms of deceit before sex again exemplifies HIV exceptionalism and the affective attachments that construct PLWH as dangerous threats to the body politic. Criminalization also fails to consider the different materializations of power relations involved in sex and in negotiations of safer sex practices. For this reason, we contend that nondisclosure laws in Canada propagate emotional harm to PLWH, who already experience marginalization in our communities. Young (Reference Young2015, 122) uses the example of a street-based sex worker living with HIV who does not disclose to their client and who may be charged with sexual assault, and asks, “but who should really bear the responsibility for ensuring the avoidance of HIV transmission in the context of this particular relationship”? Disclosure might bring about harm to the sex worker who may not be able to negotiate safer sex practices with her client. Indeed, research documents that PLWH who have been criminalized for HIV nondisclosure experience violence, verbal abuse, and other forms of emotional violence, ostracization from their families and communities, loss of employment and/or the inability to gain employment because of a criminal record, emotional distress in the form of fear and anxiety about their future and of being “outed” as HIV-positive by police press releases and media coverage of their case (McClelland Reference McClelland2019).

Underscoring Carol Smart’s (Reference Smart1989) argument that there is a juridogenic effect to law, meaning that while law purports to remedy harm it also perpetuates it, it is wiser to promote alternative responses to the emotional harm wrought from nondisclosure that do not rely upon the optimism that a criminal trial will provide justice and help one heal. Importantly, optimism in the criminal justice system is predominantly felt by those who are most privileged (i.e., those who are white, cisgendered, and who have a high socioeconomic status). Dilts (Reference Dilts, Struthers-Montford and Taylor2022, 215) contends that our optimism about the criminal justice system is reinforced precisely because “prison may seem to soothe now […] because of the carceral enjoyments of the social death of the criminalized other, the suffering of the marginalized other, and the bad faith of parasitic social life.”

To recognize emotional harms as justification for criminalization “is to hold all our activities hostage to those who are most sensitive to them, reasonably or not” (Stewart Reference Stewart2010, 30). In other words, “the feelings we have are unreliable measures of justice and fairness” (Berlant Reference Berlant, Ahmed, Kilby, Lury, McNeil and Skeggs2000, 45), given that the emotional meanings we assign to events typically reflect what each party believes they are reasonably owed in terms of how one should act and react after or at the time of the event (Hochschild Reference Hochschild1979). This is particularly evident in the context of HIV nondisclosure, wherein the law is overly sensitive to the emotional harm experienced by complainants, while remaining indifferent to the emotional harm experienced by defendants. Ironically, some heterosexual women (the largest group of complainants in nondisclosure cases) view the state with optimism, as an “agent of justice” (Ahmed Reference Ahmed2004, 197) that can deliver a sense of closure (Bandes Reference Bandes1996), despite the long and persistent history of rape culture in which women are routinely disbelieved by agents of the criminal justice system (Ehrlich Reference Ehrlich and Elizabeth2012). Thus a relation of “cruel optimism” exists precisely because the desired justice after a painful experience “is actually an obstacle to [one’s] flourishing” (Berlant Reference Berlant2011, 1). For example, sexual assault victims report that criminal justice processes feel unfair and the personnel insensitive, which can amplify the experience of PTSD symptoms for complainants (Wemmers Reference Wemmers2013).

Indeed, the legal arena limits victims’ emotional expression in relation to the harms they have experienced (Bandes Reference Bandes, Abell and Smith2016; Miller Reference Miller2013), and victim impact statements have been shown to “offend human dignity—the victim’s as well as the defendant’s” (Bandes Reference Bandes1996, 366). The harm claims of victims that are allowed in court are often manipulated by legal actors for strategic purposes (Miller Reference Miller2013), and a victim’s emotions and beliefs about forgiveness and justice often change throughout the legal process, especially if they are pressured to support punitive sentences or the death penalty (Bandes Reference Bandes1996; Reference Bandes, Abell and Smith2016). Victims experience what McGlynn and Westmarland (Reference McGlynn and Westmarland2019, 186) term kaleidoscopic justice: “justice is complex, nuanced and a difficult to (pre)determine feeling. Justice is a lived, ongoing and ever evolving experience and process, rather than an ending or result.” The criminal legal system’s ability to repair harm is hindered by the emotion culture of the courtroom, where legal actors work adversarially and where empathetic judicial displays of emotions are discouraged in the name of “objectivity” (Bandes Reference Bandes, Abell and Smith2016).

Lastly, we must consider the harm that comes from criminalizing HIV nondisclosure—both to individuals and to communities. Previous SCC decisions in Canada (Attorney General) v Bedford and Canada (Attorney General) v PHS Community Services Society considered the harms of criminalization to vulnerable groups such as sex workers and people who use drugs, yet no such consideration has been given to PLWH. These recent judicial shifts away from justifying criminal law prohibitions based on moralism or ideas of offensiveness sit uneasily beside the Cuerrier and Mabior decisions. At present, law perpetuates the suffering of PLWH by creating additional emotional and physical harms that flow from stigmatization, criminalization, and incarceration. Criminalization promotes harm by discouraging HIV testing (Bennett, Draper, and Frith Reference Bennett, Draper and Frith2000; Lee Reference Lee2014) and causes harm to the accused, and to PLWH more broadly, as they are routinely identified in sensational media coverage and thus outed to their friends, family, and community as always-already sexual predators (Kilty and Bogosavljević Reference Kilty and Bogosavljević2019; McClelland Reference McClelland2019), yet there is no evidence that criminalization actually encourages disclosure. Using criminal law is the most, rather than least, restrictive response possible, where, upon incarceration, PLWH experience limited or lack of access to harm reduction measures, which elevates HIV risk in this environment (Kilty Reference Kilty, Hundmarch, Orsini and Gagnon2018). We contend that judgements about what is just or unjust cannot be reduced to how one might feel, for doing so would sustain and conceal certain kinds of violence (Ahmed Reference Ahmed2004), such as that experienced by PLWH at the hands of the state.

The facts in the Supreme Court of Canada’s 2012 decision R v DC exemplify this point well (R v DC, 2012 SCC 48, [2012] 2 SCR 626). DC is a woman who had charges brought against her by a long-term male partner, who, apart from their first sexual encounter, knew she was HIV-positive throughout their four-year relationship. When DC reported to the authorities that the complainant was violently abusing her and her son, he retaliated by reporting to the police that she did not disclose her HIV status prior to their first sexual encounter four years earlier. This case is but one example of the unintended harms that are born from criminalizing HIV nondisclosure, demonstrating that law’s protective intention, as stated above by Justice Cory in Cuerrier, is inherently flawed. If we classify the emotional harm flowing from nondisclosure as a social or relational harm, we can begin to address the ways in which “the harms individuals experience arise from wider relationships in which they are embedded [and capture] the consequential or secondary harms that result beyond the original individual harmed to have an impact on other connected individuals and communities” (Pemberton Reference Pemberton2015, 3), such as the wider HIV positive community. Thinking of nondisclosure as an emotional harm allows us to go beyond transforming the immediate circumstances of the harm in question to imagine and work towards social transformation.

IV Alternative Justice Possibilities for the Emotional Harm of HIV Nondisclosure

Transformative justice (TJ) initiatives offer an alternative approach that counters the hostile environment created by our optimistic attachment to the criminal law as the primary mechanism for pursuing justice for the harms caused by HIV nondisclosure. A transformative justice approach that is grounded in the politics of penal abolition, the Black Liberation movement, Indigenous justice, and queer/trans resistance can be conceptualized as a framework for responding to harm without creating additional harm. Indeed, TJ is distinct from restorative justice (RJ) approaches precisely because restoration entails returning to the same conditions that maintain structural violence, while transformation requires challenging and changing the systems that led to the harm in question (Kim Reference Kim2018; Smith Reference Smith and Ptacek2010).

By reframing the harm experienced from HIV exposure as social and emotional, we can consider alternative forms of accountability and healing to address the root causes of the problem to “generate solutions and healing there, such that the conditions that create injustice are transformed” (Brown Reference Brown, Dixon and Piepzna-Samarasinha2020, 107). Transformative justice requires consensual voluntary participation and may therefore not be a viable option for all cases. It promotes healing between the offended and offending parties within the community and civil society, which enables us to consider the “complex effects of injustice on social life as well as individuals” (Ahmed Reference Ahmed2004, 197). The first step in this approach, is to listen to the “why” when trying to determine the causes of harm, “even—especially—when we are scared of the answer” (Brown Reference Brown, Dixon and Piepzna-Samarasinha2020, 107). Doing so creates possibilities for understanding and for developing and expressing empathy with the person committing the wrongdoing. If we ask why someone fails to disclose their serostatus to their sexual partners, we realize that people may do so for fear of rejection or violent reprisal, as a coping mechanism, to protect loved ones from emotional distress and so on (Rouleau, Côté, and Cara Reference Rouleau, Côté and Cara2012; Squire Reference Squire, Davis and Manderson2014). Therefore, not disclosing can be the “right” thing to do in that moment for that person. Asking “why” questions also allows us to resist law’s power to determine the truth, as Smart (Reference Smart1989) so convincingly urges us to do, thereby creating the conditions to better understand the different truths about nondisclosure as they are materially experienced by PLWH. For example, in a recent interview calling for an end to HIV criminalization in Canada, J.M., a woman convicted of aggravated sexual assault for nondisclosure, stated that “it was never my intent to infect anyone, and I haven’t, and I make it a point to take my medication, so I do not infect anyone” (Wilson Reference Wilson2022).

The second step involves asking, “what can this teach me/us about how to improve our humanity?” (Brown Reference Brown, Dixon and Piepzna-Samarasinha2020, 108). Asking this question allows us to take harmful events as learning opportunities and to recognize and transform the root causes of violence in our communities (i.e., poverty, lack of access to education, stigma, racism, patriarchy, and other forms of structural violence) rather than merely responding to injustices as they happen, in ways that do not offer opportunities for accountability and healing for those directly impacted by the violence. If we understand that PLWH choose not to disclose their serostatus because of ingrained HIV-related stigma and fear of a variety of possible harmful consequences associated with disclosure, we are better able to see the importance of creating the kind of socio-political and cultural conditions where PLWH feel safe and supported to disclose their status to their sexual partners. By criminalizing HIV nondisclosure, we are creating an ever more hostile environment for PLWH that increases, rather than limits, HIV-related stigma. Indeed, initiatives move us away from focusing on the individual causes of violence to examine the structural causes (Kim Reference Kim2018). As such, these justice practices empower communities to address harm without relying on a punitive criminal justice system that promotes further harm to individuals and communities, thus urging a different affective relation to the harm of HIV nondisclosure.

For example, WomenatthecentrE is a survivor-led non-profit organization in Canada working to end gender-based violence (GBV). Their Transformative Accountability and Justice Initiative (TAJI) is a voluntary program that “wraps the survivor and aggressor in compassion and kindness, leaving shame behind” while promoting transformation, healing, and accountability (WomenatthecentrE, 2021). TAJI connects survivors and aggressors with individual support teams made up of community advocates, other survivors, and people working in the GBV sector and offers a series of workshops and a counselling program.Footnote 7 During the workshops, survivors examine the societal conditions that lead to GBV and have access to trauma counselling, while aggressors learn about consent, toxic masculinity, patriarchy, empathy, and why “hurt people hurt people.” Aggressors also develop a “personal accountability and transformation statement” that contextualizes the harm they caused and outlines how they will demonstrate accountability (e.g., strategies for maintaining healthy relationships with women) (WomenatthecentrE, 2021). If both parties agree, staff will facilitate communication or meetings between them. For nondisclosure cases, peer and professional staff members working with AIDS Service Organizations could be involved in this kind of support and mediation work, which they have long provided in relation to safer sex practices, HIV, and what it means to live with the illness (Kinsman Reference Kinsman1996). This article contends that if there is no intentional transmission of HIV, there should be no crime. Instead, alternative transformative justice responses to HIV nondisclosure in which people can work through the emotional harms they have experienced and/or committed by better understanding the social conditions that contribute to them would be distinctly community-based rather than components of a diversionary sentencing process.

By transforming the socio-political and cultural conditions that enabled the harm in the first place, transformative justice efforts cultivate accountability, healing, resilience, and safety. These alternative forms of justice can involve difficult emotional processes that require time, patience, and a willingness to engage in tough conversations. In other words, it is “not about pack hunting an external enemy, it’s about deep shifts in our own ways of being” (Brown Reference Brown, Dixon and Piepzna-Samarasinha2020, 108). While we might be inclined to devise mechanisms of accountability for those doing the harming (as we have done with criminal law), a transformative justice approach emphasizes that mechanisms of accountability should be jointly decided by the person who was harmed, the person who committed the harm, and, where relevant, various community representatives. In this way, “communities are also sites for prevention, intervention, and transformation, spaces where interventions can be imagined, initiated, and implemented” (Kim Reference Kim2018, 227). As such, there is no one-size-fits-all method of responding to violence, harm, and injustice in our communities. Complex problems demand multi-faceted responses.

Conclusion

Speaking to the intimate connection between emotions and justice, Ahmed (Reference Ahmed2004, 202) writes that “justice is not simply a feeling. And feelings are not always just. But justice involves feelings.” This article has shown that certain emotions reflect and reinforce (and are in turn reinforced by) law’s moralist underpinnings and offers a context-sensitive moral case for changing the law. While the imprecision of the harm principle has led some scholars to question its utility (Duff Reference Duff2001; Feinberg Reference Feinberg1987), we suggest that it can be useful as a general principle, but only if we unpack how morality operates under the guise of harm to justify the regulation and criminalization of conduct deemed “immoral” (Harcourt Reference Harcourt1999). This led us to consider the criminalization of HIV nondisclosure as a problematic state response to a kind of emotional harm that would be better addressed by transformative justice approaches. The emotional harm that follows nondisclosure is an affective response that results in an emotional reading of the “HIV-positive Other.” This reading draws the boundaries between self and Other, such that the presumed victim holds no responsibility for sexual decision-making and is thus always-already innocent while the HIV-positive person is presented as an ever-present threat to the body politic whose freedom should be limited.

To this end, we argue for a more transformative agenda that moves away from carceral punishment towards an abolitionist ethos that can facilitate social justice. While law is often presumed to reflect the triumph of reason over emotion, this misapprehension denies the fact that human beings reason with and through their emotions (Cova, Deonna, and Sander Reference Cova, Deonna and Sander2015). Canada’s criminal legal approach to HIV nondisclosure reflects longstanding cultural fears of the virus and of the populations historically associated with it. The result is a problematic use of criminal law, which subsequently generates the very real unintended effects of discouraging HIV testing (Lee Reference Lee2014), increasing the number of PLWH in prison settings where there is limited access to harm reduction technologies (Kilty Reference Kilty, Hundmarch, Orsini and Gagnon2018), perpetuating HIV stigma and shame (Kirkup Reference Kirkup2015), and criminalizing emotional harm while failing to consider the emotional impact of criminalization on PLWH. Living with HIV does not reflect moral failure or a kind of inherent immorality, yet the moralist discourses that shore up Canada’s criminal legal approach to HIV nondisclosure uphold HIV exceptionalism and perpetuate further emotional harm to PLWH, without any evidence that criminalization increases the likelihood of disclosure or curbs onward transmission. In this way, the criminalization of HIV nondisclosure is a failed public health strategy that reifies the problematic emotional attachments we make to both law and HIV and that, in the end, does more harm than good.

Footnotes

*

We would like to thank Michael Orsini, Steven Bittle, Jennifer Chandler, Jeff Bradley, Thomas McMorrow, and the anonymous reviewers for their thoughtful comments and suggestions on various versions of this article.

1 For the purposes of the criminal law in Canada, a low viral load is less than 1,500 copies per millilitre of blood. According to a report by UNAIDS (2018), having an undetectable or suppressed viral load is below 200 copies per millilitre of blood, thereby significantly reducing the risk of transmission. In common parlance, advocates and medical experts now use the term U=U, or undetectable=untransmissible. Since viral loads can fluctuate for various reasons, the Justices felt that “antiretroviral therapy, alone, still exposes a sexual partner to a realistic possibility of transmission” (R v Mabior, 2012, para 101).

2 The Mabior decision contributed to Canada’s overly broad use of criminalization by instructing the lower courts to prosecute exposure incidents where condoms were used, which ignores that condom use demonstrates an ethic of care for one’s partner and thus an intent to protect, rather than to do harm. When condoms are used correctly, scientific experts have confirmed that HIV cannot be transmitted (Barré-Sinoussi et al. Reference Barré-Sinoussi, Karim, Albert, Bekker, Beyrer, Cahn and Calmy2018). The Canadian Coalition to Reform HIV Criminalization (2017) argues that condom use should reduce the risk to such a degree that the state should not prosecute nondisclosure when a condom is used.

3 We distinguish the emotional harm that occurs due to HIV nondisclosure from the emotional abuse experienced by victims of intimate partner violence. Whereas the former involves a sense, feeling, or interpretation of emotional harm by the complainant, the latter refers to “nonverbal behaviour or attitudes that are designed to control, subdue, punish, or isolate the other person through the use of humiliation or fear” (Karakurt and Silver Reference Karakurt and Silver2013, 804).

4 There was a publication ban on revealing the complainants’ identities; we are using initials to protect the defendant’s identity, as well.

5 Justice Hood’s term psychological harm positions the emotions experienced from nondisclosure as clinical symptoms of trauma. Such explanations are couched in medico-legal discourses that individualize and pathologize emotions. We contend that the emotional harm that occurs from nondisclosure is relational, an affective force that signals people’s responsibilities to each other and the world around them.

6 There are a small number of cases where the Crown attempted to prosecute the nondisclosure of other sexually transmitted infections, but these have been rare, again exemplifying a degree of HIV exceptionalism in criminal law. For example, in R v J, [2002] NBQB 340 the accused was acquitted for not disclosing they had Hepatitis C on the basis that a transmission risk of “less than 1 percent” was not “significant”.

7 WomenatthecentrE’s C6 counselling program considers the following 6 ‘C’s: context, consequence, communication, care, culture, and control.

References

References

Adam, Barry D., Corriveau, Patrice, Elliott, Richard, Globerman, Jason, English, Ken, and Rourke, Sean. 2015. HIV disclosure as practice and public policy. Critical Public Health 25 (4): 386397.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Ahmed, Sarah. 2004. The Cultural Politics of Emotion. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.Google Scholar
Bandes, Susan A. 1996. Empathy, narrative, and victim impact statements. University of Chicago Law Review 63 (2): 361412.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bandes, Susan A. 2016. Share your grief but not your anger: Victims and the expression of emotion in criminal justice. In the Expression of Emotion: Philosophical, Psychological and Legal Perspectives, ed. Abell, Catherine and Smith, Joel, 263286. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barré-Sinoussi, Françoise, Karim, Salim S. Abdool, Albert, Jan, Bekker, Linda-Gail, Beyrer, Chris, Cahn, Pedro, Calmy, Alexandra, et al. 2018. Expert consensus statement on the science of HIV in the context of criminal law. Journal of the International AIDS Society 21 (7). https://doi.org/10.1002/jia2.25161CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bennett, Rebecca, Draper, Heather, and Frith, Lucy. 2000. Ignorance is bliss? HIV and moral duties and legal duties to forewarn. Journal of Medical Ethics 26:915.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Berlant, Lauren. 2011. Cruel Optimism. Durham: Duke University Press.Google Scholar
Berlant, Lauren. 2000. The subject of true feeling: Pain, privacy, and politics. In Transformations: Thinking Through Feminism, ed. Ahmed, Sarah, Kilby, Jane, Lury, Celia, McNeil, Maureen, and Skeggs, Beverley, 3347. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Bogosavljević, Katarina, and Kilty, Jennifer M.. 2021. “Now, the question here is who to believe”: Criminalizing HIV nondisclosure, emotions, and determinations of credibility in R. v. T.S. Emotions and Society 3 (2): 209225. https://doi.org/10.1332/263169020X16014084980811CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brown, Adrienne Maree. 2020. What is/isn’t transformative justice? In Beyond Survival: Strategies and Stories from the Transformative Justice Movement, ed. Dixon, Ejeris and Piepzna-Samarasinha, Leah Lakshmi, 107108. Chico, CA: AK Press.Google Scholar
Buchanan, Kim Shayo. 2015. When is HIV a crime? Sexuality, gender and consent. Minnesota Law Review 99 (4): 12311342.Google Scholar
Canadian Coalition to Reform HIV Criminalization. 2017. End Unjust HIV Criminalization: Community Consensus Statement. Retrieved from: http://www.aidslaw.ca/site/wp-content/uploads/2017/07/CCRHC_Backgrounder-and-Draft-Community-Consensus-Statement_final_EN_25July2017.pdfGoogle Scholar
Chalmers, James. 2002. The criminalisation of HIV transmission: Ethics, law and medicine. Journal of Medical Ethics 28 (3): 160163.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ciambrone, Desire’e. 2001. Illness and other assaults on self: The relative impact of HIV/AIDS on women’s lives. Sociology of Health & Illness 23 (4): 517540.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cova, Florian, Deonna, Julien, and Sander, David. 2015. Introduction: Moral emotions. Topoi, 34 (2): 397400.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cvetkovich, Ann. 2003. An Archive of Feeling: Trauma, Sexuality and Lesbian Public Cultures. Durham: Duke University Press.Google Scholar
Dilts, Andrew. 2022. Carceral enjoyments and killjoying the social life of social death. In Building Abolition: Decarceration and Social Justice, ed. Struthers-Montford, Kelly and Taylor, Chloë, 196223. Abingdon: Routledge.Google Scholar
Duff, Robin Antony. 2001. Harms and Wrongs. Buffalo Criminal Law Review 5 (1): 1345.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ehrlich, Susan. 2012. Perpetuating—and resisting—rape myths in trial discourse. In Sexual Assault in Canada: Law, Legal Practice and Women’s Activism, ed. Elizabeth, Sheehy A., 389408. Ottawa: University of Ottawa Press.Google Scholar
Eisenberg, Avlana K. 2015. Criminal infliction of emotional distress. Michigan Law Review, 113 (5): 607662.Google Scholar
Feinberg, Joel. 1987. The Moral Limits of the Criminal Law Volume 1: Harm to Others. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grant, Isabel. 2008. The boundaries of the criminal law: The criminalisation of the non-disclosure of HIV. The Dalhousie Law Journal, 31:123180.Google Scholar
Grant, Isabel. 2020. The complex legacy of R. v. Cuerrier: HIV nondisclosure prosecutions and their impact on sexual assault law. Alberta Law Review, 58 (1): 4582.Google Scholar
Harcourt, Bernard. 1999. The collapse of the harm principle. The Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology, 90:109194.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hastings, Colin, Massaquoi, Notisha, Elliott, Richard, and Mykhalovskiy, Eric. 2022. HIV Criminalization in Canada: Key Trends and Patterns (1989–2020). Report: Canadian HIV/AIDS Legal Network. Retrieved from https://www.hivlegalnetwork.ca/site/hiv-criminalization-in-canada-key-trends-and-patterns-1989-2020/?lang=enGoogle Scholar
Hillyard, Paddy, and Tombs, Steve. 2007. From “crime” to social harm?. Crime, Law, and Social Change 48:925.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
HIV/AIDS Legal Network. 2019. The Criminalization of HIV Non-Disclosure in Canada. Retrieved from: http://www.aidslaw.ca/site/the-criminalization-of-hiv-non-disclosure-in-canada-report/?lang=enGoogle Scholar
Hochschild, Arlie. 1979. Emotion work, feeling rules, and social structure. American Journal of Sociology 85 (3): 551575.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Karakurt, Günnur, and Silver, Kristin E.. 2013. Emotional abuse in intimate relationships: The role of gender and age. Violence and Victims 28 (5): 804821.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kilty, Jennifer M. 2018. Institutionalizing risk in the “daddy state”: Carceral spaces as HIV risk environments. In Seeing Red: HIV/AIDS and Public Policy in Canada, ed. Hundmarch, Suzanne, Orsini, Michael, and Gagnon, Marilou, 79101. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kilty, Jennifer M., and Bogosavljević, Katarina. 2019. Emotional storytelling: Sensational media and the creation of the HIV sexual predator. Crime, Media, Culture, 15 (2): 279299.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kilty, Jennifer M., Orsini, Michael, and Balogh, Peter. 2017. Critical bioethics in the time of epidemic: The case of the criminalization of HIV/AIDS nondisclosure in Canada. Aporia: The Nursing Journal, 49 (1): 918.Google Scholar
Kim, Mimi E. 2018. From carceral feminism to transformative justice: Women-of-colour feminism and alternatives to incarceration. Journal of Ethnic & Cultural Diversity in Social Work 27 (3): 219233.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kinsman, Gary. 1996. “Responsibility” as a strategy of governance: Regulating people living with AIDS and lesbians and gay men in Ontario. Economy and Society 25 (3): 393409.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kirkup, Kyle. 2015. Releasing stigma: Police, journalists and crimes of HIV non-disclosure. Ottawa Law Review 46 (1): 127160.Google Scholar
Lee, Sun Goo. 2014. Criminal law and HIV testing: Empirical analysis of how at-risk individuals respond to the law. Yale Journal of Health Policy, Law, and Ethics 14 (1): 194238.Google ScholarPubMed
Loutfy, Mona, Tyndall, Mark, Baril, Jean-Guy, Julio, S. G. Montaner, Kaul, Rupert, and Hankins, Catherine. 2014. Canadian consensus statement on HIV and its transmission in the context of criminal law. The Canadian Journal of Infectious Diseases and Medical Microbiology 25 (3): 135140.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Lupton, Deborah. 2013. Risk and emotion: Towards an alternative theoretical perspective. Health, Risk, & Society 15 (8): 634647.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
MacKinnon, Emily, and Crompton, Constance. 2012. The gender of lying: Feminist perspectives on the non-disclosure of HIV status. University of British Columbia Law Review 45 (2): 407447.Google Scholar
McClelland, Alexander. 2019Lock this whore up”: Legal violence and flows of information precipitating personal violence against people criminalized for HIV-related crimes in Canada. European Journal of Risk Regulation 10 (1): 132147.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McGlynn, Clare, and Westmarland, Nicole. 2019. Kaleidoscopic justice: Sexual violence and victim-survivors’ perceptions of justice. Social & Legal Studies 28 (2): 179201.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miller, Karen-Lee. 2013. Purposing and repurposing harms: The victim impact statement and sexual assault. Qualitative Health Research 23 (11): 14451458.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Pemberton, Simon. 2015. Harmful Societies: Understanding Social Harm. Bristol: Policy Press.Google Scholar
Rouleau, Geneviève, Côté, José, and Cara, Chantal. 2012. Disclosure experience in a convenience sample of Quebec-born women living with HIV: A phenomenological study. BMC Women’s Health, 12(37): 3747.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smart, Carol. 1989. Feminism and the Power of Law. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Smith, Andrea. 2010. Beyond restorative justice: Radical organizing against violence. In Restorative Justice and Violence Against Women, ed. Ptacek, James, 255278. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Squire, Corinne. 2014. HIV disclosure: Practices, knowledges and ethics. In Disclosure in Health and Illness, ed. Davis, Mark and Manderson, Lenore, 138152. Abingdon: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stewart, Hamish. 2010. The limits of the harm principle. Criminal Law and Philosophy 4 (1): 1735.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tynan, Lauren. 2021. What is relationality? Indigenous knowledges, practices and responsibilities with kin. Cultural Geographies, 28 (4): 597610.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
UNAIDS. 2018. Undetectable = Untransmittable: Public Health and HIV Viral Load Suppression. https://www.unaids.org/sites/default/files/media_asset/undetectable-untransmittable_en.pdfGoogle Scholar
Watney, Simon. 1996. Policing Desire: Pornography, AIDS and the Media (3rd ed.). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Weait, Mathew. 2016. HIV and the meaning of harm. In Criminalising Contagion: Legal and Ethical Challenges of Disease Transmission and the Criminal Law, ed. Stanton, Catherine and Quirk, Hannah, 1834. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weait, Mathew. 2007. Intimacy and responsibility: The criminalisation of HIV transmission. Abingdon: Routledge-Cavendish.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wemmers, Joanne. 2013. Victims’ experiences in the criminal justice system and their recovery from crime. International Review of Victimology 19 (3): 221233.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilson, Katelyn. 2022. “I do not infect anyone,” Fighting for change to end HIV non-disclosure prosecution. CTV News Barrie: February 2. https://barrie.ctvnews.ca/i-do-not-infect-anyone-fighting-for-change-to-end-hiv-non-disclosure-prosecution-1.5765502Google Scholar
WomenatthecentrE. 2021. WomenatthecentrE’s Transformative Accountability & Justice Initiative (TAJI): Information Package. https://womenatthecentre.com/wp-content/uploads/Transformative%20Accountability%20%20Justice%20Initiative%20-%20INFO%20PACKAGE%20%20June%202021.pdfGoogle Scholar
Young, Diane. 2015. Individual rights and the negotiation of governmental power: The risk of HIV transmission and Canadian criminal law. Social & Legal Studies 24 (1): 113134.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Canada (Attorney General) v Bedford, 2013 SCC 72.Google Scholar
Canada (Attorney General) v PHS Community Services Society, 2011 SCC 44.Google Scholar
R v Cuerrier, [1998] 2 SCR 371.Google Scholar
R v CAT, 2016 NSSC 134.Google Scholar
R v CAT, 2018 NSCA 13.Google Scholar
R v DC, 2012 SCC 48, [2012] 2 SCR 626.Google Scholar
R v J, [2002] NBQB 340.Google Scholar
R v Mabior, 2012 SCC 47, [2012] 2 SCR 584.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
R v Kirkpatrick, 2022 SCC 33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
R v TS, [2007] SJ No 150 [Smith, 2007], Decision.Google Scholar
Canada (Attorney General) v Bedford, 2013 SCC 72.Google Scholar
Canada (Attorney General) v PHS Community Services Society, 2011 SCC 44.Google Scholar
R v Cuerrier, [1998] 2 SCR 371.Google Scholar
R v CAT, 2016 NSSC 134.Google Scholar
R v CAT, 2018 NSCA 13.Google Scholar
R v DC, 2012 SCC 48, [2012] 2 SCR 626.Google Scholar
R v J, [2002] NBQB 340.Google Scholar
R v Mabior, 2012 SCC 47, [2012] 2 SCR 584.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
R v Kirkpatrick, 2022 SCC 33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
R v TS, [2007] SJ No 150 [Smith, 2007], Decision.Google Scholar