Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-7cvxr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-23T23:49:06.158Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Multidimensionality and the Matrix: Identifying Charter Violations in Cases of Complex Subordination

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  18 July 2014

Kerri A. Froc
Affiliation:
University of Ottawa, [email protected]

Abstract

The failure of the Supreme Court of Canada to give more than lip service to “context” when considering claims under s. 15 of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms arises largely from the Court's analytic framework, which resists recognizing the social relations of power inherent in complex cases of oppression. The precise nature of the flaws in the Court's analysis is demonstrated in a number of thoughtful feminist critiques that received recognition in the recent decision in R. v. Kapp. While it is too soon to tell whether the Court intends to depart completely from the past decade of s. 15 jurisprudence, equality-seeking groups now have greater opportunities to advance alternative theoretical frameworks for Charter interpretation. This article discusses one such framework, multidimensionality theory, which focuses on the interaction of systems of oppression, conceptualized as an invisible matrix—a vast network of complex, overlapping, interactive, and mutually reinforcing systems. The operation of the systems obscures their effects, and their complexity renders outcomes difficult to predict when they interconnect at sites of subordination and privilege. One can expose the operation of the systems by looking at particular sites of oppression/privilege and considering the contradictions or “inexplicability” of the circumstances based on one system alone. The author argues that the failure of the Charter claim at the heart of the Supreme Court's decision in Native Women's Association of Canada v. Canada demonstrates the need for courts to employ multidimensionality theory in cases of complex oppression. In NWAC, multidimensionality theory reveals that the “dominant” Aboriginal groups were involved in the negotiation/performance of hegemonic masculinities within a racial/colonial context that provided them with justification to suppress NWAC's independent promotion of the interests of Aboriginal women in constitutional negotiations with the government, and that the government was complicit in this performance. By framing the freedom of expression issue as whether NWAC had a “special” right to a speaking platform, and the equality issue as exclusively one of determining whether NWAC could prove the other groups were “male dominated,” the Court fragmented considerations of patriarchy from those of racism and colonization, distorting the synergistic effect of the systems of oppression and reinforcing colonial ideology.

Résumé

L'incapacité de la Cour suprême du Canada de tenir vraiment compte du « contexte » lorsqu'elle considère les demandes sous l'article 15 de la Charte canadienne des droits et libertés découle, en grande partie, de son cadre analytique, soit un cadre qui rejette le concept des relations sociales de pouvoir dans les cas complexes d'oppression. Les contraintes de ce cadre analytique ont été soulignées dans un certain nombre de critiques féministes importantes, soit des critiques ayant eu un impact sur la décision récente R c. Kapp. Bien qu'il soit encore trop tôt pour déterminer si la Cour a l'intention de se départir du type de jurisprudence de l'article 15 caractéristique de la dernière décennie, les groupes faisant la promotion de l'égalité ont désormais de meilleurs chances de mettre de l'avant des cadres théoriques alternatifs dans l'interprétation de la Charte. Cet article explore l'un de ces cadres théoriques : la théorie de la multidimensionnalité. Cette théorie examine les interactions des systèmes d'oppression, à savoir des systèmes conceptualisés comme une matrice invisible ou encore comme un réseau de systèmes complexes et interactifs qui se chevauchent et se renforcent mutuellement. Selon cette perspective, les manifestations des systèmes d'oppression sont obscurcies par leur fonctionnement tandis que la complexité de ces systèmes rend leurs manifestations difficiles à prévoir lorsque ceux-ci interagissent entre eux dans des situations impliquant des subordinations et des privilèges. Il est possible d'exposer le fonctionnement de ces systèmes en examinant les situations particulières d'oppression et de privilège et en considérant les contradictions qui existeraient si de telles conséquences découlaient d'un seul système. Selon l'auteur, l'échec de la Cour suprême du Canada dans la poursuite de l'Association des femmes autochtones du Canada c. Canada représente une preuve que les cours ont besoin d'employer la théorie de la multidimensionnalité dans les cas complexes d'oppression. La théorie de la multidimensionnalité révèle comment les groupes autochtones dominants étaient impliqués dans la négociation ainsi que la performance des masculinités hégémoniques dans un contexte racial et colonial. Ce contexte servait à justifier la suppression des efforts de l'AFAC, à savoir la promotion des intérêts des femmes autochtones au sein des négociations constitutionnelles avec le gouvernement. Ce cadre théorique révèle aussi la complicité du gouvernement dans cette suppression. En interprétant la notion de liberté d'expression comme fondée sur le besoin de déterminer si l'AFAC avait des droits « spéciaux » de faire des revendications et en interprétant la notion d'égalité comme étant exclusivement le besoin de déterminer si l'AFAC était capable de prouver que les autres groupes étaient dominés par les hommes, la Cour a écarté les considérations patriarcales des considérations raciales et coloniales, provoquant ainsi une déformation des effets synergiques des systèmes d'oppression et renforçant l'idéologie coloniale.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Law and Society Association 2010

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms, Part I of the Constitution Act, 1982, being Schedule B to the Canada Act 1982 (U.K.), 1982, c. 11 [Charter]Google Scholar.

2 [1999] 1 S.C.R. 497 [Law]. No interveners, women's groups or otherwise, were heard in this “age discrimination” case. The Law test required claimants, among other things, to demonstrate differential treatment through the use of a “comparator group,” explained in later cases to be a group whose relevant personal characteristics “mirror” those of the claimant except for those used in the impugned legislative provision. It also required claimants to prove discrimination through a violation of their “human dignity,” using four contextual factors. In subsequent decisions, the analysis usually turned upon the “correspondence” factor, that is, on the correspondence between the distinction and the claimant's actual characteristics and circumstances.

3 Granovsky v. Canada (Minister of Employment and Immigration), [2000] 1 S.C.R. 703.

4 Nova Scotia v. Walsh, [2002] 4 S.C.R. 325.

5 Gosselin v. Québec, [2002] 4 S.C.R. 429.

6 Auton (Guardian ad litem of) v. British Columbia (A.G.), [2004] 3 S.C.R. 657.

7 Hodge v. Canada (Minister of Human Resources Development), [2004] 3 S.C.R. 357.

8 Trociuk v. British Columbia (A.G.), [2003] 1 S.C.R. 835.

9 Where I use “subordination” and “oppression” throughout this article, rather than “equality” or “discrimination,” this is a deliberate attempt to expand the discussion of anti-subordination strategy beyond the use of s. 15. Here I specifically adopt Iris Marion Young's conception of the “five faces of oppression”: exploitation, marginalization, powerlessness, cultural imperialism, and violence: Young, Iris Marion, Justice and the Politics of Difference (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1990)Google Scholar. To this list I would add colonization, which must be understood first as a spacialized racial domination: Razack, Sherene, “Gendered Racial Violence and Spacialized Justice: The Murder of Pamela George,” in Race, Space and the Law: Unmapping a White Settler Society, ed. Razack, Sherene (Toronto: Between the Lines, 2002), 129Google Scholar.

10 See, e.g., Fyfe, James, “Dignity as Theory: Competing Conceptions of Dignity at the Supreme Court of Canada,” Saskatchewan Law Review 70 (2007), 1Google Scholar; Faraday, Fay, Denike, Margaret, and Stephenson, Kate, eds., Making Equality Rights Real: Securing Substantive Equality under the Charter (Toronto: Irwin Law, 2006)Google Scholar; McIntyre, Sheila and Rodgers, Sanda, eds., Diminishing Returns: Inequality and the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms (Markham, ON: LexisNexis Canada, 2006)Google Scholar; Majury, Diana and Gilbert, Daphne, “Critical Comparisons: The Supreme Court of Canada Dooms Section 15,” Windsor Yearbook of Access to Justice 24 (2006), 124Google Scholar; Lessard, Hester, “Mothers, Fathers, and Naming: Reflections on the Law Equality Framework and Trociuk v. British Columbia (Attorney General),” Canadian Journal of Women and the Law 16 (2004), 165Google Scholar; Gilbert, Daphne, “Time to Regroup: Rethinking Section 15 of the Charter,” McGill Law Journal 48 (2003), 627Google Scholar; and Baines, Beverley, “Law v. Canada: Formatting Equality,” Constitutional Forum 11, 3 (2000), 65Google Scholar.

11 [2008] 2 S.C.R. 483 at paras. 21–24.

12 In the 1980s television series Dallas, the reintroduction of the deceased character Bobby Ewing was accomplished by explaining his death as a dream on the part of his wife, Pam.

13 This fruit of the feminist critique may ultimately prove bitter if these decisions, rather than encouraging courts to head in a new analytical direction, cause them to retreat to a more confined interpretation of discrimination, namely as the perpetuation of prejudice and stereotype and not “also vulnerability, powerlessness, oppression, stigmatization, marginalization, devaluation, and disadvantage more broadly”: Jonnette Watson Hamilton, “The End of Law: A New Framework for Analyzing Section 15(1) Challenges,” ABlawg.ca, posted February 20, 2009, http://ablawg.ca/wp-content/uploads/2009/10/blog_jwh_ermiskin_scc_feb2009.pdf. I recognize that these decisions carry this risk, as well as presenting opportunities.

14 See Hutchinson, Darren Lenard, “Commentary: New Complexity Theories: From Theoretical Innovation to Doctrinal Reform,” University of Missouri–Kansas City Law Review 71 (2002), 431Google Scholar.

15 Hutchinson, Darren Lenard, “Out Yet Unseen: A Racial Critique of Gay and Lesbian Legal Theory and Political Discourse,” Connecticut Law Review 29 (1997), 561Google Scholar; Hutchinson, Darren Lenard, “Identity Crisis: ‘Intersectionality,’ ‘Multidimensionality,’ and the Development of an Adequate Theory of Subordination,” Michigan Journal of Race and Law 6 (2001), 285Google Scholar.

16 Ehrenreich, Nancy, “Subordination and Symbiosis: Mechanisms of Mutual Support Between Subordinating Systems,” University of Missouri–Kansas City Law Review 71 (2002), 251Google Scholar.

17 Kwan, Peter, “Jeffrey Dahmer and the Cosynthesis of Categories,” Hastings Law Journal 48 (1997), 1257Google Scholar; Kwan, Peter, “Complicity and Complexity: Cosynthesis and Praxis,” DePaul Law Review 49 (2000), 673Google Scholar.

18 Arriola, Elvia R., “Gendered Inequality: Lesbians, Gays, and Feminist Legal Theory,” Berkeley Women's Law Journal 9 (1994), 103Google Scholar.

19 Valdes, Francisco, “Sex and Race in Queer Legal Culture: Ruminations on Identities and Inter-connectivities,” Southern California Review of Law and Women's Studies 5 (1995), 25Google Scholar; Iglesias, Elizabeth M. and Valdes, Francisco, “Expanding Directions, Exploding Parameters: Culture and Nation in LatCrit Coalitional Imagination,” University of Michigan Journal of Law Reform 33 (2000), 203Google Scholar.

20 Frye, Marilyn, The Politics of Reality: Essays in Feminist Theory (Trumansburg, NY: Crossing Press, 1983), 45Google Scholar.

21 The Matrix, written and directed by Wachowski, Andy and Wachowski, Larry (Burbank, CA: Warner Bros., 1999)Google Scholar.

22 See, e.g., Vasiliou, Iakovos, “Reality, What Matters, and the Matrix,” in Philosophers Explore The Matrix, ed. Grau, Christopher (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005)Google Scholar; Vasiliou discusses enslavement and deception as the two moral backgrounds of the film.

23 [1994] 3 S.C.R. 627 [NWAC].

24 Harris, Angela P., “Race and Essentialism in Feminist Legal Theory,” in Critical Race Theory: The Cutting Edge, 2nd ed., ed. Delgado, Richard and Stefancic, Jean (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 2000), 263Google Scholar.

25 Crenshaw, Kimberlé, “Mapping the Margins: Intersectionality, Identity, Politics and Violence Against Women of Colour,” Stanford Law Review 43 (1991), 1244CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

26 Ibid., n. 7.

27 Iyer, Nitya, “Disappearing Women: Racial Minority Women in Human Rights Cases,” Canadian Journal of Women and the Law 6 (1993), 25Google Scholar.

28 Iyer, Nitya, “Categorical Denials: Equality Rights and the Shaping of Social Identity,” Queen's Law Journal 19 (1993), 179Google Scholar.

29 Hutchinson, “Identity Crisis,” 310.

30 On this point see Arriola, “Gendered Inequality,” 129.

31 As Nancy Levitt writes, “In one sense, post-intersectionality [multidimensionality] moved intersectional concepts to the systemic level.” Levitt, Nancy, “Introduction: Theorizing the Connections among Systems of Subordination,” University of Missouri–Kansas City Law Review 71 (2002), 227Google Scholar.

32 Hutchinson, , “Identity Crisis,” 290Google Scholar.

33 Hutchinson, , “Out Yet Unseen,” 640–41Google Scholar.

34 Kwan, “Jeffrey Dahmer,” 1281–82.

35 See Eherenreich, , “Subordination and Symbiosis,” 254–55Google Scholar.

36 Carbado, Devon W. and Gulati, Mitu, “The Fifth Black Woman,” Journal of Contemporary Legal Issues 11 (2001), 707Google Scholar.

37 Ehrenreich's example is that of white women, who “struggle against stereotypes that suggest they are vulnerable, asexual and naturally suited to nurturing.” Ehrenreich, , “Subordination and Symbiosis,” 274Google Scholar.

38 Grillo, Trina, “Anti-essentialism and Intersectionality: Tools to Dismantle the Master's House,” Berkeley Women's Law Journal 10 (1995), 18Google Scholar; Wildman, Stephanie, “Language and Silence: Making Systems of Privilege Visible,” in Critical Race Theory: The Cutting Edge, 2nd ed., ed. Delgado, Richard and Stefancic, Jean (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 2000), 661Google Scholar.

39 Nash, Jennifer C., “Re-thinking Intersectionality,” Feminist Review 89, 1 (2008), 13CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

40 Ibid., citing Wacquant, Loïc, “For an Analytic of Racial Domination,” in Political Power and Social Theory II, ed. Davis, D.E. (Greenwich, CT: Jai Press, 1997), 221–34Google Scholar.

41 Hutchinson, “Identity Crisis,” 303.

42 Peterson v. Bodlovich, [2000] WL 702126 (7th Cir.).

43 Hutchinson, “Identity Crisis,” 305–6 (emphasis added). In Canada, while not explicitly relying on multidimensionality theory, interveners Equality for Gays and Lesbians Everywhere (EGALE) et al. attempted to guide the Supreme Court of Canada on how sexual orientation discrimination can exist coextensively with discrimination based on family status in Canada (A.G.) v. Mossop, [1993] 1 S.C.R 554. While the Supreme Court accepted this idea in principle, it resisted seeing Mossop as anything but a case of discrimination on the basis of sexual orientation (which was not covered under the federal human rights statute). See Freeman, Jody, “Defining Family in Mossop v. DSS: The Challenge of Anti-essentialism and Interactive Discrimination for Human Rights Litigation,” University of Toronto Law Journal 44 (1994), 41CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

44 De Santis v. Pacific Tel. & Tel. Co., 607 F.2d 327 (9th Cir. 1979).

45 Rabidue v. Osceola Ref. Co., 805 F.2d 611 (6th Cir. 1986), cited in Arriola, “Gendered Inequality,” 138. See, however, Price Waterhouse v. Hopkins, 490 U.S. 228 (1989), in which a woman's dismissal for failure to act in a “feminine” way was recognized as sex discrimination.

46 Arriola, “Gendered Inequality,” 138.

47 [1995] 2 S.C.R. 513 at 601.

48 (2003), 9 B.C.L.R. (4th) 338 (S.C.).

49 Jette, Maura, “Sticks and Stones: Jubran v. Board of Trustees and the Relationship between Homophobic Harassment and Sex Discrimination,” Journal of Law and Equality 2 (2003), paras. 5354Google Scholar.

50 North Vancouver District No. 44 v. Jubran (2005), 253 D.L.R. (4th) 294, 2005 BCCA 201.

51 Harris, Angela P., “Gender, Violence, Race, and Criminal Justice,” Stanford Law Review 52 (2000), 785–86CrossRefGoogle Scholar. The concept of “hegemonic masculinity” is discussed in greater detail below.

52 [1993] 4 S.C.R. 695.

53 Johnson, Rebecca, Taxing Choices: The Intersection of Class, Gender, Parenthood and the Law (Vancouver: UBC Press, 2002), ixGoogle Scholar.

54 Ibid., 139.

55 Ehrenreich, , “Subordination and Symbiosis,” 273Google Scholar.

56 Ehrenreich, Nancy S., “O.J. Simpson and the Myth of Gender/Race Conflict,” University of Colorado Law Review 67 (1996), 931Google Scholar.

57 Ehrenreich, , “Subordination and Symbiosis,” 259Google Scholar.

58 Ibid, at 257, 292 (citing Pyke, Karen D., “Class-Based Masculinities: The Interdependence of Gender, Class, and Interpersonal Power,” Gender and Society 10 (1996), 527), 293CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

59 Razack, Sherene, “‘Outwhiting the White Guys’: Men of Colour and Peacekeeping Violence,” University of Missouri–Kansas City Law Review 71 (2002), 334Google Scholar. See also Cho, Sumi, “Understanding White Women's Ambivalence Towards Affirmative Action: Theorizing Political Accountability in Coalitions,” University of Missouri–Kansas City Law Review 71 (2002), 399Google Scholar (criticizing the theory of compensatory subordination as giving white women a “pass” for their behaviour and discounting the material benefits accruing to their families as a result of white male privilege).

60 Razack, , “Outwhiting the White Guys,” 340–41Google Scholar.

61 Ehrenreich, , “Subordination and Symbiosis,” 295–97Google Scholar.

62 See note 23.

63 NWAC at 649.

64 NWAC president Gail Stacey-Moore, in her affidavit before the Court, noted that this was part of a historical pattern of exclusion. With respect to the 1992 Charlottetown constitutional consultations specifically, she described how she was included in the AFN's Constitutional Working Group, but only in circumstances in which she was a “minority voice.” There were also issues surrounding AFN's withdrawal of an offer to give money to NWAC for a women's conference as part of the consultations and NWAC's having to fight to secure a small number of delegates to the other scheduled conferences. NWAC (Evidence, Affidavit of Gail Stacey-Moore, Case on Appeal) at paras. 77, 82–84.

65 Isaac, Thomas and Maloughney, Mary Sue, “Dually Disadvantaged and Historically Forgotten? Aboriginal Women and the Inherent Right of Aboriginal Self-Government,” Manitoba Law Journal 21 (1992), paras. 35Google Scholar; Anderson, Kim, A Recognition of Being: Reconstructing Native Womanhood (Toronto: Sumach Press, 2000), 6568Google Scholar. See also Mclvor v. Canada (Registrar, Indian and Northern Affairs), 2007 BCSC 827 at para. 9, aff'd on narrower grounds 2009 BCCA 153, leave to appeal to the S.C.C. dismissed, [2009] S.C.C.A. No. 234.

66 Thobani, Sunera, Exalted Subjects: Studies in the Making of Race and Nation in Canada (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 2007), 49Google Scholar. See also Anderson, , A Recognition of Being, 6970Google Scholar; Lawrence, Bonita, “Real” Indians and Others: Mixed Blood Urban Native Peoples and Indigenous Nationhood (Vancouver: UBC Press, 2004), 4647Google Scholar. As these authors argue, this goal was achieved by reducing the numbers of status Indians through the discriminatory “marrying out” provisions of the Indian Act (discussed below) and by taking control of lands out of the hands of women, bypassing traditional systems of matrilineal inheritance and decision making, such as that among the Iroquois (Haudenosaunee).

67 S.C. 1869, c. 6.

68 S.C. 1876, c. 18.

69 Lawrence, , “Real” Indians and Others, 50Google Scholar. Lawrence points out that the practice of defining “Indianness” based on marriage or descent along the male line began in 1850 in provincial legislation (Protection of Lands and Property of the Indians in Lower Canada, S.C. 1850, c. 42) prior to the passage of the British North America Act. Ibid., 32).

70 Ernestine, LilianneKrosenbrink-Gelissen, , Sexual Equality as an Aboriginal Right: The Native Women's Association of Canada and the Constitutional Process on Aboriginal Matters, 1982–1987 (Saarbrucken, Germany: Verlag Breitenbach, 1991), 52Google Scholar.

71 Fiske, Jo-Anne, “Political Status of Native Indian Women: Contradictory Implications of Canadian State Policy,” American Indian Culture and Research Journal 19, 2 (1995), 6CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

72 Lawrence, , “Real” Indians and Others, 50Google Scholar.

73 As Lawrence states, the Indian Act “provides a conceptual framework that has organized contemporary First Nations life in ways that have been almost entirely naturalized, and that governs ways of thinking about Native identity.” Ibid., 25.

74 Canada (A.G.) v. Lavell; Isaac v. Bedard, [1974] S.C.R. 1349 [Lavell].

75 R.S.C. 1970, c. 1–6.

76 S.C. 1960, c. 44.

77 NWAC (Evidence, Affidavit of Gail Stacey-Moore, Case on Appeal) at para. 28.

78 Green, Joyce, “Taking Account of Aboriginal Feminism,” in Making Space for Indigenous Feminism, ed. Green, Joyce (Winnipeg: Fernwood Publishing, 2007), 26Google Scholar. Green (30) and Lawrence, “Real” Indians and Others, 57–58, document other accounts of harassment of and violence against Aboriginal women advancing their rights by male leaders and members of their communities.

79 See, e.g., Cree leader Harold Cardinal's work, The Rebirth of Canada's Indians (Edmonton: Hurtig Publishing, 1977), 109–11Google Scholar (discussing the reaction of Aboriginal leaders to constitutional challenges to s. 12(1)(b) of the Indian Act) and Lawrence, , “Real” Indians and Others, 58Google Scholar (relating the Native Indian Brotherhood's description of the provision as “a benevolent process to protect Indians from the white men who married Indian women”).

80 Lavell at 1360.

81 As Stacey-Moore stated in her affidavit, “if there is one group which represents us as off-Reserve Aboriginal women, exiles in our own land, it is NWAC.” NWAC (Evidence, Case on Appeal) at para. 32.

82 Ibid, at para. 25, quoting the Report of the Aboriginal Justice Inquiry of Manitoba (Winnipeg: Aboriginal Justice Inquiry, 1991)Google Scholar.

83 Jamieson, Kathleen, Indian Women and the Law in Canada: Citizens Minus (Ottawa: Advisory Council on the Status of Women, 1978), 91Google Scholar.

84 The UN Human Rights Committee found that s. 12(b) of the Indian Act breached art. 27 of the Covenant on Civil and Political Rights, which requires that persons belonging to ethnic, religious, or linguistic minorities not be “denied the right, in community with the other members of their group, to enjoy their own culture, to profess and practise their own religion, or to use their own language”: Lovelace v. Canada, Report of the Human Rights Committee, UN GAOR, 36th Sess., Supp. No. 40, Annex 18, 16, UN Doc. AQ/ 36/40(1977).

85 An Act to amend the Indian Act, S.C. 1985, c. 27. See Mclvor, Sharon, “Self Government and Aboriginal Women,” in Ten Years Later: The Charter and Equality for Women, ed. Jackson, Margaret A. and Banks, N. Kathleen (Vancouver: Simon Fraser University, 1996), 170Google Scholar, on the impact of the coming into force of Charter s. 15.

86 Green, Joyce, “Constitutionalizing the Patriarchy: Aboriginal Women and Self-Government,” Constitutional Forum 4, 4 (1993), 113Google Scholar. The remaining discriminatory aspects, including the failure to extend full status to descendants of a matrilineal ancestor who lost status under the old legislation, were successfully challenged by Sharon Mclvor: Mclvor v. Canada, cited at note 65 above.

87 Green, “Constitutionalizing the Patriarchy”; Isaac and Maloughney, “Dually Disadvantaged and Historically Forgotten,” paras. 26–27.

88 Green, ibid. In the midst of this litigation, the court granted a mandatory interlocutory injunction requiring the Sawridge band to reinstate 11 women to their band list (Sawridge Band v. Canada, 2003 FCT 347, aff'd 2004 FCA 16). Eventually, the action was dismissed (2008 FC 322, aff'd 2009 FCA 123) because the plaintiffs decided not to call further evidence, and proceeded to the Federal Court of Appeal on an unsuccessful application for the trial judge to recuse himself on the basis of bias. Massive cost awards were made against the plaintiffs in favour of the Crown, NWAC, and other interveners as a result of the plaintiffs' conduct during the litigation.

89 Green, , “Constitutionalizing the Patriarchy,” 113Google Scholar.

90 There was no dissent in NWAC. L'Heureux-Dubé J. disagreed with the majority analysis while concurring with the disposition of the case on the facts. McLachlin J. also wrote an extremely short concurring opinion on the basis that the Charter does not apply to the “freedom of governments to choose and fund their advisors on matters of policy.” NWAC at para. 91.

92 Ibid, at para. 23.

93 Two bedrock texts of legal feminism on this point are Williams, Susan, “Feminist Legal Epistemologies,” Berkeley Women's Law Journal 8 (1993), 6Google Scholar; and MacKinnon, Catharine, Feminism Unmodified: Discourses on Life and Law (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1987)Google Scholar.

94 Lawrence, Charles III, “If He Hollers Let Him Go: Regulating Racist Speech on Campus,” Duke Law Journal (1990), 474Google Scholar, advances the argument that expression and equality are read hierarchically in dominant culture—namely, expression is included in the “regular” rights of “everyone,” whereas equality is a “special right” for “a minority of different people.”

95 NWAC at paras. 44, 45.

96 [1993] 2 S.C.R. 955 at 1041–42 [Haig], cited in NWAC at 655 [emphasis added].

97 L'Heureux-Dubé J. was hardly a proponent of a “watertight compartments” approach to Charter rights, as this excerpt might suggest. She concurred in Andrews v. Law Society of British Columbia, [1989] 1 S.C.R. 143 at 195, where Mclntyre J. stated (representing the majority on this point) that “[t]he section 15(1) guarantee is the broadest of all guarantees. It applies to and supports all other rights guaranteed by the Charter.”

98 NWAC at para. 86.

99 Ibid, at para. 50.

100 See Thobani, , Exalted SubjectsGoogle Scholar, and in particular her searing analysis in chapter 5 (“Reforming Canadians: Consultations and Nationalizations”), where she outlines how the Canadian public was constructed as white during two consultations on immigration and social security policy in the mid-1990s.

101 NWAC at para. 50.

102 Ibid. at paras. 53, 54, 55.

103 In the rewritten NWAC decision by Sharon McIvor, Teressa Nahanee, and Mary Eberts (part of the Women's Court of Canada Project, Canadian Journal of Women and the Law 18, 1 (2006), 67Google Scholar, the authors also maintain that it is a matter of constitutional obligation pursuant to s. 35.1 of the Constitution Act, 1982, that federal and provincial governments consult “representatives of aboriginal peoples of Canada” before any constitutional amendments relating to the rights of Aboriginal peoples are made.

104 NWAC at para. 53. The falsity of the symmetry is not only its construction of men as the “subordinated” group when it comes to the abortion issue but also its assumption that biological “fathers” of embryos have an equal, but opposing, legal interest in the decision as to whether to terminate a pregnancy. This reasoning was rejected in Tremblay v. Daigle, [1989] 2 S.C.R. 530.

105 NWAC at para. 57.

106 Ibid. at para. 75.

107 The Court first considered this question as part of the s. 2(b) argument but later identifies it as “relat[ing] more closely to an equality argument under s. 15” and as “better characterized as a s. 15 Charter argument” (at paras. 58, 76). In its three-paragraph decision on s. 15, the Court further states that “[t]he lack of evidentiary basis for the arguments with respect to ss. 2(b) and 28 is equally applicable to any arguments advanced under s. 15(1) of the Charter in this case” (at para. 78). Therefore, I believe that the Court considered whether the four funded groups were “male dominated” as part of the s. 15 argument proper.

108 Ibid. at paras. 59, 66.

109 Ibid. at para. 59.

110 Pinard, Danielle, “Institutional Boundaries and Judicial Review—Some Thoughts on How the Court Is Going About Its Business: Desperately Seeking Coherence,” Supreme Court Law Review (2nd ser.) 25 (2004), 222Google Scholar.

111 See NWAC at para. 62: “To the best of Ron Rivard's [executive director of MNC] knowledge, NWAC does not speak for, nor represent the Metis women of Canada.”

112 It is not that the number of women in organizations is unimportant in considerations of inclusiveness but, rather, that in addition to imposing differing evidentiary standards, the Court did not conduct a probing analysis of how Aboriginal women raising gender issues were treated within the funded groups. Further, a “numbers count” in isolation does not recognize the fact that NWAC represents a marginalized and disenfranchised group of Aboriginal women whose exclusion has a particular and gendered consequence for the negotiations. In contrast to the Supreme Court's scepticism, the Federal Court of Appeal emphasized NWAC's role as a “grassroots organization founded and led by aboriginal women” and its record of national activism as the “recognized national voice of and for aboriginal women”: [1992] F.C.J. No. 715 at para. 3 [NWAC (FCA)].

113 To bolster the thin evidence on the record, the Court resorted to citing, as proof of the funded groups' representativeness, a letter from Constitutional Affairs Minister Joe Clark to NWAC seeking to convince them that “[t]he national Aboriginal associations do represent both men and women from their communities. I encourage you to work within your communities to ensure your views are heard and represented through those associations” (NWAC at para. 67).

114 Thobani, , Exalted Subjects, 228Google Scholar.

115 Monture, Patricia. Thunder in My Soul: A Mohawk Woman Speaks (Halifax: Fernwood Publishing, 1995), 147Google Scholar.

116 Affidavit of Gail Stacey-Moore, cited in NWAC (FCA) at para. 91.

117 NWAC (FCA). Razack raises this decision as “reveal[ing] the perils for Aboriginal women raising issues of violence within their communities while under the gaze of white society—a society engaged in drafting a constitution without recognition of Aboriginal self-determination”: Razack, Sherene, Looking White People in the Eye (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1998), 62Google Scholar.

118 Thobani, , Exalted Subjects, 44Google Scholar, also discusses how international law justified the conquest of Canada's Indigenous peoples on the basis that the “savage” and “uncivilized” were “incapable of self-determination.” Chartrand, Larry, “The Political Dimension of Aboriginal Rights” (LLM thesis, Queen's University, 2001), 38Google Scholar, argues that Aboriginal peoples and Europeans initially negotiated nation to nation and that the colonialist ideology of Aboriginal inferiority re-emerged only when Aboriginal communities were weakened by disease and European immigration increased.

119 See Razack, Sherene, Dark Threats and White Knights: The Somalia Affair, Peacekeeping and the New Imperialism (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 2004), 62Google Scholar (noting that racial/colonial domination has a stabilizing effect on both personal and national identity).

120 See, e.g., Cairns, Alan C., Charter versus Federalism: The Dilemmas of Constitutional Reform (Montreal: McGill-Queen's University Press, 1992)Google Scholar, on the role of the Charter in nation building and creating an enhanced sense of Canadian (as distinct from British/French) citizenship. I acknowledge that the constructions of “nationhood” in First Nations communities are much different than Western constructs: Napoleon, Val, “Extinction By Number: Colonialism Made Easy,” Canadian Journal of Law and Society 16 (2001), 113CrossRefGoogle Scholar. However, eliminating definitions of nationhood imposed by colonization and replacing them with self-definitions would require negotiations with federal/provincial governments over self-determination and constitutional amendment. To that extent, I would argue, this would be a relationship between nationhood and constitutional discussions for Aboriginal peoples as well.

121 I am also reminded here of how governments attempted to exclude women, and specifically Aboriginal women who articulated their concerns about whether the equality guarantee would adequately protect them, from the process of negotiating the terms of the Charter: Kome, Penny, The Taking of 28 (Toronto: Women's Press, 1983)Google Scholar.

122 This is not to say that the actual gender identities of the group leaders were all male; in fact, the ITC president was a woman. The point, rather, is that the Western paradigm inherently relies on a construction of political leadership that is white and male—“political power that enables control over others” is one of the privileges of hegemonic masculinity: Angela P. Harris, “Gender, Violence, Race, and Criminal Justice,” 783–84. See also Laroque, Emma, “Métis and Feminist: Ethical Reflections on Feminism, Human Rights and Decolonization,” in Making Space for Indigenous Feminism, ed. Green, Joyce (Winnipeg: Fernwood Publishing, 2007), 66Google Scholar (on the paradox of Canadian anti-colonial movements maintaining non-traditional, gendered distributions of political power).

123 NWAC at para. 65.

124 Ibid. (Evidence, Case on Appeal, Exhibit M to the Affidavit of Gail Stacey Moore) at 279–82.

125 Ibid.

126 Ibid. at 285.

127 NWAC at paras. 62, 63, 64.

128 Cardinal, , Rebirth of Canada's Indians, 111Google Scholar.

129 As Patricia Monture states, “Understanding how patriarchy operates in Canada without understanding colonization is a meaningless endeavour from the perspective of Aboriginal people. The Canadian face is the invisible male perpetrator who unlike Aboriginal men does not have a victim face.” Monture, , Thunder in My Soul, 175)Google Scholar.

130 See the letter from Joe Clark, cited at note 126, regarding evidence of the government's complicity in marginalizing NWAC within constitutional negotiations.

131 Turpel, Mary-Ellen, “Patriarchy and Paternalism: The Legacy of the Canadian State for First Nations Women,” Canadian Journal of Women and the Law 6 (1993), 181Google Scholar.

132 Anderson, , A Recognition of Being, 97Google Scholar.

133 At first blush, this may seem contradictory to my argument that gender subordination is used to justify engaging in and perpetuating colonization. However, the distinction is in the use of women's bodies to script Western notions of civilization, which does not require an actual commitment by the colonizer to provide conditions of equality for racialized women—indeed, such a commitment is proscribed by the performance of hegemonic masculinity.

134 Kerri A. Froc, “Will Watertight Compartments Sink Women's Charter Rights? The Need for a New Theoretical Approach to Women's Multiple Rights Claims under the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms” (LL.M. major paper, University of Ottawa, 2008)Google Scholar.

135 Williams, Susan, Truth, Autonomy, and Speech: Feminist Theory and the First Amendment (New York: New York University Press, 2004)Google Scholar.

136 Ibid., 160.

137 Ibid., 153, 161, 209, 212. In the Canadian context, Richard Moon has also advocated for an understanding of expression as relational and constitutive (i.e., having an effect on thoughts and perceptions): Moon, Richard, “The Relationship of Communication,” in The Constitutional Protection of Freedom of Expression (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 2000), 4049Google Scholar.

138 That the control over construction of identity is a key aspect of reinstated women's legal struggle is supported by a study quoted by John Borrows, who notes that the primary reason people applied for registration as status Indians in the aftermath of Bill C-31 was personal identity (41%), and that 77% of those whose status was restored were women: Borrows, John, “Contemporary Traditional Equality: The Effect of the Charter on First Nation Politics,” University of New Brunswick Law Journal 43 (1994), 34Google Scholar.

139 NWAC at para. 66: “Thus, it was not exclusively the position of NWAC that the Charter be maintained.”

140 Ibid. at para. 71. As the Court itself recognized, the allocation of money for “women's issues” was not voluntary on the part of the funded groups, but required by the funding agreement with the government.

141 The Court notes at para. 69 that NWAC was able to express itself “directly to the Government” by making submissions to the Beaudoin-Dobbie Committee. The recent “rewriting” of NWAC by Sharon McIvor et al. as part of the Women's Court of Canada project highlights the disparity even in this forum: the committee spent a day with each of the funded groups, whereas NWAC was limited to written submissions. McIvor et al., para. 25.

142 Monture, , Thunder in My Soul, 217Google Scholar.

143 See, e.g., Borrows, John, “Listening for a Change: The Courts and Oral Tradition,” Osgoode Hall Law Journal 39 (2001), 1Google Scholar.

144 In the words of Edward Said, “[S]tories … become the method colonized people use to assert their own identity and the existence of their own history … As one critic has suggested, nations themselves are narrations”: Said, Edward, Culture and Imperialism (New York: Vintage, 1993), xiiiGoogle Scholar. The potency of language in subverting colonialism was recognized by the state in the Canadian residential school context, where students were punished harshly for speaking Indigenous languages: Chrisjohn, Roland D. and Young, Sherri L., The Circle Game: Shadows and Substance in the Indian Residential School Experience in Canada (Penticton, BC: Theytus, 1997), 3133Google Scholar; Royal Commission on Aboriginal Peoples, Report of the Royal Commission on Aboriginal Peoples (Ottawa: Indian and Northern Affairs Canada, 1996), 372Google Scholar.

145 Anderson, , A Recognition of Being, 130–33Google Scholar, discusses Indigenous stories, particularly those pertaining to women, and the respectful manner in which women are addressed in Indigenous languages as colonial resistance.

146 Joyce Green speaks of the fact that Aboriginal women seeking to advance their human rights are accused of “betraying the cause of Aboriginal liberation by invoking colonial, Western, white or feminist analysis and remedies” and are subsequently defined as “non-community members, and therefore voiceless”: Green, Joyce, “Canaries in the Mines of Citizenship: Indian Women in Canada,” Canadian Journal of Political Science 34 (2001), 729CrossRefGoogle Scholar. This was NWAC's predicament in the case before the Court.

147 See Williams, Susan, “Democracy Theory, Feminist Theory, and Constitutionalism: Models of Equality and the Challenges of Multiculturalism” (Paper presented to the International Conference of Feminist Constitutionalism, February 2009)Google Scholar, for further elaboration of the process that governments may follow to ensure that internal vulnerable minorities within what Williams calls “minority cultural groups” are not harmed in implementing self-determination.

148 See note 90 above for the articulation of this principle by McLachlin J. (as she then was). Sopinka J. also quoted with approval a passage from American case law stating that a government has “freedom to choose its advisors.” NWAC at para. 56.

149 Green, Joyce, “Balancing Strategies: Aboriginal Women and Constitutional Rights in Canada,” in Making Space for Indigenous Feminism, ed. Green, Joyce (Winnipeg: Fernwood Publishing, 2007), 148Google Scholar.

150 R.S.C. 1985, c. H-6. S. 3.1 was added in 1998.

151 [1998] 1 S.C.R. 493 at para. 82.

152 [1999] 2 S.C.R. 203.

153 While sex discrimination was not addressed directly in Corbiere, the selection of this “intersectional” ground had direct implications for Aboriginal women, given their history of expulsion from reserves under the discriminatory “marrying out” provisions of the Indian Act.

154 Law. at paras. 93, 94.