Article contents
Justice and the War of Reasons
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 09 June 2015
Extract
No one has ever adequately described, either in poetry or in private conversation, what the very presence of justice or injustice in his soul does to a man, even if it remains hidden from gods and man....
- Type
- Research Article
- Information
- Copyright
- Copyright © Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 1988
References
Many people have made helpful comments or asked difficult questions.I would like especially to thank Patricia Andrews, Richard Bronaugh, Leonard Kaplan, Steven Leahy, Carl Rasmussen, Andrew Segal and Zigurds Zile.
1. Gadamer, H.-G. Truth and Method (New York: Continuum, 1975) at 10–19.Google Scholar
2. Bernard Williams writes of them in Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1985).Google ScholarPubMed
3. See Lehman, W. “How to Interpret a Difficult Statute” (1979), Wis L. Rev. 489;Google Scholar Lehman, W. “Rules in Law” (1984), 72 Geo. L.J. 71;Google Scholar Lehman, W. “How We Make Decisions” (1986), Institute for Legal Studies Working Paper, ser. 1, No. 5.Google Scholar
4. Gadamer, Truth and Method, supra, n. 1.Google Scholar
5. Id. at 10-39.
6. Id. at 274-78.
7. Rawls, J. A Theory of Justice. (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1971). at 71;Google Scholar accord Rawls, “Justice as Fairness,” in Philosophy, Politics and Society (2nd series) (Oxford, Blackwell 1962) at 132,n. 2.Google Scholar
8. Aristotle says so explicitly in Nicomachean Ethics (hereafter NE) at 1103b 26.
9. I take up, in “Rules in Law”, supra. n. 3, the question whether rules can tell us what to do. If they cannot, that fact should encourage exploration of the possibility that good action will come out of interior states, as the Greeks say.
10. Kurtz, P. A Secular Humanist Declaration, in In Defense of Secular Humanism. 14, 18 (1983). Google Scholar
11. See, e.g., Skinner, B.F. Beyond Freedom and Dignity (New York: Knopf, 1971) at 12.Google Scholar
12. Maclntyre, A. After Virtue (Indiana: Notre Dame University Press, 1981).Google Scholar
13. Sartre, J.-P. Being and Nothingness, An Essay on Phenomenological Ontology (New York: Philosophical Library, 1956) at 67–70.Google Scholar
14. Williams, Ethics, supra n. 2, at 196.Google Scholar
15. See Lehman, “Rules of Law,” supra n. 3, at 1598.Google Scholar That it is misconceived I shall speak of more here, too. Its deep rootedness is suggested by George Fletcher’s recent conference on Kantian legal theory, papers from which have been published at “Symposium on Kantian Legal Theory” (1987), 87 Colum. L. Rev. 421.Google Scholar
16. Bok, S. Lying: Moral Choice in Public and Private Life (New York: Pantheon Books, 1978) at 25.Google Scholar
17. See, e.g., Freud, S. Civilization and Its Discontents (Strachey, J. ed. 1961) at 78–90.Google Scholar
18. Plato, Republic at 439 (Jowett trans., Random House ed., ed. 1937 Vol. 1 at 703).Google Scholar
19. E.g. Hume, D. The Philosophical Works of David Hume (1898) Vol. 2 at 193–97.Google Scholar
20. See Freud, Civilization and its Discontents, supra n. 17 at 91–97.Google Scholar
21. Plato, Republic at 439.Google Scholar
22. Id.at 443-44 (Jowett trans., supra n. 18, at 707-08). It is the further insight of Gadamer that practical application of this sort regrounds the alienated moral or legal text. See supra n. 1.
23. Compare Nasr, S.H. Knowledge and the Sacred (New York: Crossroad 1981) at 1. “In the beginning Reality was at once being, knowledge, and bliss....” Prof. Nasr distinguishes between reason and discernment or sapience, but the distinction seems to be that which I describe below as larger and smaller notions of reason.Google Scholar
24. Compare Moline, J. Plato’s Theory of Understanding (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1981). at 29–31, 52-78.Google Scholar
25. Which Bergson was later to call the knowledge contained in words. Bergson, H. The Creative Mind (New York: Philosophical Library, 1946) at 37.Google Scholar
26. Aristotle, NE 111lb to 1113a.
27. For a brief survey of the dispute, see Meeks, W. “Law Versus Grace and the Problem of Ethics” in The Writings of St. Paul (New York: Norton, 1972) at 215.Google Scholar
28. see e.g, “Inaugural Address at Northwestern University” by Stephen Toulmin, The Recovery of Practical Philosophy (Apr. 23, 1987).Google Scholar
29. E.g, Meeks, Law versus Grace, supra n. 27, at 274.Google Scholar
30. See Simon Callow, Being an Actor (Penguin Books, 1985) at 164–69.Google ScholarPubMed
31. Aristotle, NE at 1095b.
32. E.g, Calvin, John Institutes of the Christian Religion (Baillie, J. McNeil, J. & Van Dusen, H. eds., 1960) at 35–37.Google Scholar
33. I take Paul’s contrast between law and faith to be an account of this choice we have in how to lead our lives. Seeking salvation by following the law is an active pursuit contrasted with the faith by which we become passive receptors of grace. Romans 9:30-33. I am here closer to Rudolf Bultmann’s interpretation of Paul (e.g. in Theology of the New Testament (1951) than to Krister Stendahls (“The Apostle Paul and the Introspective Conscience of the West”, in Meeks supra n. 27 at 422-34). We need not throw out an existential interpretation of St. Paul either because Paul, as Stendahl reads him, was not personally anguished by guilt the way Luther was, or because, as Stendahl rightly emphasizes, Paul’s reflections on Jewish law were motivated by the need to explain how Gentile converts were to be integrated into the followershp of a Jewish prophet. It is not necessary to be filled with self-loathing to have the insight Paul obviously had.The resolution Paul claims for himself and promises to others is the result of a surrendering of the pretense of conscious control of the path to salvation; it is a surrender some make more easily than others. It was Paul’s genius that in trying to find a resolution for the place of Gentiles in Christianity he found a set of terms in which to represent the promise of Christianity. The force of that message has, however, always been most powerfully felt by those, like Augustine and Luther, for whom Paul’s understanding was illustrated in anguishing personal experiences
34. Wittgenstein, L. Tractatus Logico-Phihsophicus (Pears, D. & McGuiness, B. trans., 2nd ed. 1963) at 51.Google Scholar
35. See Lehman, “How We Make Decisions” supra n. 3, at 1963) at 35–45 Google Scholar
36. See, e.g., Maclntyre, supra n. 12 at 51.Google Scholar
37. Calvin, Institutes of the Christian Religion, supra n. 32, at 78–81.Google Scholar
38. See, “Lectures in Frankfurt, W. Germany” Beyond Modernity (May 6, 13, 20, 27 & June 3, 1987).Google Scholar
39. Rorty, R. “The Contingency of Language” London Rev. Books, April 17, 1986 at 3, col. 1;Google Scholar see also Rorty, R. “The Contingency of Selfhood” London Rev. Books, May 8, 1986, at 11, col. 1;Google Scholar Rorty, R. “The Contingency of Community” London Rev. Books, July 24, 1986, at 10, col. 1.Google Scholar
40. Williams, Ethics, supra, n. 2, at 18.Google Scholar
41. Id at 41-43.
42. SeeRorty, R. Rorty, The Contingency of Community supra n. 39.Google Scholar
43. Gilligan, C. In a Different Voice: Psychological Theory and Women’s Development (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1982).Google Scholar
44. Kohlberg, L. The Philosophy of Moral Development (San Francisco: Harper & Row, 1981) at 412.Google ScholarPubMed
45. Id at 101-89.
46. Id at 345-48.
47. Weinrib, E. “Law as a Kantian Idea of Reason” (1987), 87 Colum. L. Rev. 422.Google Scholar
48. Weinrib, E. “Toward a Moral Theory of Negligence Law” (1983), 2 Law & Phil 37.Google Scholar
49. Williams, pursues this point as well in “Justice as a Virtue” , in Moral Luck (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1981) 83.37.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
50. Aristotle, NE, 1129a.
51. Hutcheson, J. “The Judgement Intuitive: The Function of the Hunch in Judicial Decision” (1929), 14 Cornell L.Q. 274.Google Scholar
52. Gardner, J. On Moral Fiction (New York: Basic Books, 1978) at 12 105-26.Google Scholar
53. Hutcheson, , The Judgement Intuitive, supra, n. 51, at 286–87.Google Scholar
54. Aristotle says these are attributes of the excellent person. NE at 1166a.
55. “Lectures in Frankfurt, W. Germany,” Habermas, Jurgen Law and Morality (n.d., 1987).Google Scholar
56. Sagan, C. Dragons of Eden (New York: Random House, 1977) at 205–06.Google Scholar
57. Plato, Republic at 443.Google Scholar
- 1
- Cited by