Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-t8hqh Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-23T19:05:16.221Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Discussion Foucault, Agamben, and Arbour J.’s Dissent in Gosselin

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  20 July 2015

Get access

Extract

In Gosselin v. Quebec, the Supreme Court of Canada considered whether the Quebec legislature violated the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms by failing to provide unemployed adults under the age of 30 (young adults) with the level of social assistance provided to other unemployed adults. A majority of the Court concluded that the underinclusive legislation in question was not unconstitutional. The case gave rise, however, to one of the most progressive and intriguing dissenting opinions in Canadian constitutional history-a dissent made all the more interesting by the fact it was written by a judge who would later become the United Nations High Commissioner for Human Rights: Louise Arbour. Her dissent focused on the proper interpretive approach to s. 7 of the Charter, which states: “Everyone has the right to life, liberty and security of the person and the right not to be deprived thereof except in accordance with the principles of fundamental justice.” She argued that the “right to life” contained in s. 7 entails a number of positive rights, including the right to a minimum level of social assistance.This paper argues that Arbour J.’s dissent in Gosselin reveals an inherent flaw with the very concept of rights; namely, that they presuppose the state’s authority to exclude whole populations from the protection of law. The argument has four parts. Part I reads Arbour J.’s approach to the constitutional questions raised in Gosselin as broadly sympathetic to Foucault’s understanding of power in the modern era. Part II claims that Arbour J.’s judgment presumes that formal legal regulations, and not other, informal mechanisms of power, chiefly bear the burden of governing life. Part III examines Agamben’s critique of Foucault to show why Arbour J.’s privileging of state governance of well being is problematic; in particular, that the greater the formalization and centralization of the mechanisms by which life is governed, the greater the prospect of exclusion of groups and classes from rights regimes altogether. Finally, Part IV explains that Arbour J.’s concession to juridification is driven by an inherent problem with rights, and that the difficulties she runs into cannot be avoided; that exclusion from the rights framework is built into the very concept of rights.

Type
Discussions
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 2008

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

I am grateful to Richard Bronaugh, Barry Hoffmaster, John Paterson, Carissima Mathen, Tony Carty and Natalia Alvarez-Molinaro for their comments on earlier drafts of this paper. The usual disclaimer applies.

1. Gosselin v. Quebec (Attorney General), [2002] 4 S.C.R. 429.Google Scholar

2. Ibid. at para. 345.

3. Foucault, Michel, The History of Sexuality, vol. 1: An Introduction, trans. by Hurley, Robert (New York: Vintage, 1990)Google Scholar [Foucault, Sexuality].

4. Gosselin, supra note 1 at para. 342.

5. Note that Foucault does not claim that sovereign power has been entirely eclipsed. See Foucault, Michel, Security, Territory, Population, ed. by Senellart, Michel, trans. by Burchell, Graham (New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2007) [Foucault, Security].Google Scholar

6. Deleuze, Gilles, Foucault, trans. by Hand, Sean (London; New York; Harrisburg: Continuum International Publishing Group, 2006) at 24.Google Scholar

7. See Hunt, Alan & Wickham, Gary, Foucault and Law: Towards a Sociology of Law as Governance (London: Pluto Press, 1994)Google Scholar, noting that this is consistent with the Austinian conception of law.

8. Foucault, Sexuality, supra note 3 at 94-95.

9. See Ericson, Richard V. and Haggarty, Kevin D., Policing the Risk Society (Toronto, ON: University of Toronto Press, 1997).Google Scholar

10. Genel, Katia, “The Question of Biopower: Foucault and Agamben” (2006) 18 Rethinking Marxism 43 at 46.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

11. Foucault, Michel, Society Must Be Defended, ed. by Bertani, Mauro & Alessandro|Fontana, trans. by Macey, David (England: Penguin Books, 2004) at 241 [Foucault, Society].Google Scholar

12. Genel, supra note 10 at 48. For an example of one such regulatory instrument—the passport—see Torpey, John, The Invention of the Passport: Surveillance, Citizenship and the State (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000).Google Scholar

13. Foucault, Sexuality, supra note 3 at 94.

14. Foucault, Society, supra note 11 at 249-50; Genel, supra note 10 at 47; Gratton, Peter, “A ‘Retroversion’ of Power: Agamben via Foucault on Sovereignty” (2006) 9 Critical Rev. of Int’l Social & Political Phil. 445 at 448.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

15. Gosselin, supra note 1 at para. 346.

16. Ibid. at para. 347.

17. Consider the comments of the Australian High Court in Roach v. Electoral Commissioner, [2007] HCA 43.Google ScholarPubMed

18. We can go further, and observe that the s. 8 right to be free from unreasonable searches and seizures, as well as the s. 10(b) right to counsel, also presuppose institutional frameworks; i.e., mechanisms by which warrants and counsel can be obtained. Thus, see R. v. Hape, 2007 SCC 26 Google ScholarPubMed, where LeBel J. noted that the Charter could not apply extraterritorially because many foreign states lack the appropriate infrastructure to give effect to ss. 8 and 10(b) rights.

19. See Hunt & Wickham, supra note 7.

20. Gosselin, supra note 1 at para. 365, citing Dunmore v. Ontario (Attorney General), [2001] S.C.J. No. 87 Google ScholarPubMed, [2001] 3 S.C.R. 1016 at paras. 24-26.

21. Gosselin, ibid. at para. 368.

22. See R. v. Rowbotham et al. (1988), 41 C.C.C. (3d) 1 at 65-66 (Ont. C.A.).Google ScholarPubMed

23. See British Columbia (Attorney General) v. Christie, 2007 ScC 21 at paras. 16-17Google Scholar; B.C.G.E.U. v. British Columbia (Attorney General), [1988] 2 S.C.R. 214.Google Scholar

24. Chaoulli v. Quebec (Attorney General), 2005 SCC 35.Google ScholarPubMed

25. See Health Insurance Act, R.S.Q., c. A-29, s. 15; Hospital Insurance Act, R.S.Q., c. A-28, s. 11.

26. Charter of Human Rights and Freedoms, R.S.Q., c. C-12 [Quebec Charter].

27. Chaoulli, supra note 24 at para. 119.

28. Gosselin, supra note 1 at para. 370.

29. Ibid. at para. 372.

30. Ibid. at para. 375.

31. Ibid. at para. 378.

32. Ibid. at para. 380.

33. Ibid. at para. 381.

34. Dunmore, supra note 20 at para. 29.

35. See Baier v. Alberta, 2007 SCC 31.Google Scholar

36. Habermas, Jurgen, The Theory of Communicative Action, vol. 2: Lifeworld and System: A Critique of Functionalist Reason, trans. by McCarthy, Thomas (Cambridge: Polity Press, 1995) at 357.Google Scholar

37. See Dunmore, supra note 20.

38. Gosselin, supra note 1 at para. 382 [emphasis added].

39. Ibid. at para. 308.

40. See Foucault, Sexuality, supra note 3 at 133-59; Hunt & Wickham, supra note 7.

41. See especially Agamben, Giorgio, Homo Sacer: Sovereign Power and Bare Life, trans. by Heller-Roazen, Daniel (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1998).Google Scholar

42. See Hart, H.L.A., The Concept of Law, 2d ed. (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1994) at chs. 2-5.Google Scholar

43. Ibid.

44. This is, of course, a recurring theme in the history of Western political philosophy at least since Hobbes.

45. See Hart, supra note 42 at ch. 5.

46. See Fitzpatrick, Peter, “Bare Sovereignty, Homo Sacer and the Insistence of Law” in Norris, Andrew, ed., Politics, Metaphysics, and Death: Essays on Giorgio Agamben’s Homo Sacer (Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 2005) at 56.Google Scholar

47. See Foucault, Security, supra note 5.

48. Foucault, Sexuality, supra note 3 at 136.

49. Agamben, Homo Sacer, supra note 41 at 6.

50. Schmitt, Carl, Political Theology: Four Chapters on the Concept of Sovereignty, trans. by Schwab, George (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 2005) at 1.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

51. Agamben, Homo Sacer, supra note 41 at 4.

52. Ibid. at 8.

53. See Agamben, Giorgio, Remnants of Auschwitz: The Witness and the Archive, trans. by Heller-Roazen, Daniel (New York: Zone Books, 1999).Google Scholar

54. See Agamben, Giorgio, Means Without End: Notes on Politics, trans. by Binetti, Vincenzo & Casarino, Cesare (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 2000) at ch. 2Google Scholar; Rajuram, P.K. & Grundy-Warr, C., “The irregular migrant as Homo Sacer: Migration and detention in Australia, Malaysia, and Thailand” (2004) 42 International Migration 33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

55. See Agamben, Giorgio, State of Exception, trans. by Attell, Kevin (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 2005) at 34 Google Scholar; Gratton, supra note 14 at 456-57; Zizek, Slavoj, “Are we in a war? Do we have an enemy?” (2002) 24:10 London Review of Books 3.Google Scholar

56. See Pratt, Geraldine, “Abandoned Women and Spaces of Exception” (2005) 37 Antipode 1052.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

57. See Agamben, Homo Sacer, supra note 41 at 166.

58. See the discussion in Genel, supra note 10 at 46.

59. Foucault, Society, supra note 11 at 260.

60. Mills, Catherine, “Contingency, Responsibility, and the Law: A Response” (2004) 3 Google Scholar borderlands e-journal http://www.borderlandsejournal.adelaide.edu.au/v013n01_2004/mills_contingency.htm.

61. See Agamben, Homo Sacer, supra note 41 at 50-55.

62. See Haig v. Canada, [1993] 2 S.C.R. 995 at 1039Google Scholar, cited in Dunmore, supra note 20 at para. 23 [emphasis added].

63. See Dunmore, ibid. at paras. 20-22.

64. Thus, see the Supreme Court’s recent decision in Baier, supra note 35, where no mention is made of Arbour J.’s dissenting opinion, despite the fact that Baier turns on the underinclusiveness of legislation.

65. Gosselin, supra note 1 at para. 81.

66. 1 borrow the term from Torpey, supra note 12.

67. See Arbour, Louise, “In Our Name and On Our Behalf” (Paper presented at Chatham House, February 2006)Google Scholar, available online: http://www.chathamhouse.org.uk/files/3375_ilparbour.pdf.

68. Ibid. at 10-11.

69. But see Roach, Kent, September 11: Consequences for Canada (Montreal, PQ: McGill-Queens University Press, 2002) at ch. 2.Google Scholar