Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-gvvz8 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-23T23:01:41.408Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Democracy and the Notwithstanding Clause

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  30 May 2024

Michael Pal*
Affiliation:
Faculty of Law, University of Ottawa, Canada

Abstract

This article focuses on the relationship between democracy and the notwithstanding clause in s.33 of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms. A number of scholars argue that s.33 is inherently ‘democratic’, as it is an assertion of legislative supremacy. The most influential such theory is Jeremy Waldron’s. This article offers a democracy-based critique of Waldron’s democracy-based account of the notwithstanding clause. The argument that the notwithstanding clause is necessarily ‘democratic’ ignores the constitution of the legislature through elections and the risk of self-dealing by the legislative branch, adopts an idealistic view of legislatures at odds with the reality of executive dominance and party discipline, and over-relies on the assumption that the electorate will ensure retrospective accountability for misuse of s.33. Contrary to Waldron and those who have adopted his arguments in Canada in the context of the Charter, the article argues we can be democrats and have faith in the capacities of legislators and voters while still maintaining skepticism about the uses to which the notwithstanding clause may be put. In short, s.33 is not inherently democratic. The political morality of each use of the notwithstanding clause—including whether it helps or harms democracy—must be assessed on a case-by-case basis.

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BYCreative Common License - NC
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0/), which permits non-commercial re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original article is properly cited. The written permission of Cambridge University Press must be obtained prior to any commercial use.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of University of Western Ontario (Faculty of Law)

I. Introduction

While the ‘notwithstanding clause’ in s.33 of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms Footnote 1 “has emerged as [the Charter’s] most controversial provision,” the death of the clause has been proclaimed many times since 1982.Footnote 2 Outside of Quebec,Footnote 3 s.33 had been invoked sparingly until recently.Footnote 4 The degree of political restraint reached the point where scholars began to consider whether s.33 had fallen into “desuetude,”Footnote 5 if there was a constitutional convention against its use outside of Quebec,Footnote 6 or if it was “simply irrelevant.”Footnote 7 The era of political restraint appears to be over.Footnote 8 Ontario invoked s.33 for the first time in 2021Footnote 9 and openly considered using it in another case,Footnote 10 both times in relation to political rights. Quebec’s recent use of s.33 in legislation on state secularismFootnote 11 and language rightsFootnote 12 has been particularly controversial.

This article focuses on the relationship between s.33 and democracy in general and the use of the notwithstanding clause in relation to political rights in particular. A number of scholars have advocated for more frequent use of the notwithstanding clause on explicitly democratic grounds.Footnote 13 While the debates about the notwithstanding clause have often centered around the separation of powers, dialogue theory, and so on, proponents of the use of s.33 have rooted their arguments in the democratic legitimacy of the legislative branch, namely Parliament and the provincial legislatures. The most influential theory of the legitimacy of the notwithstanding clause is Jeremy Waldron’s democracy-based account.Footnote 14 Waldron’s reasoning has been directly adopted by some who argue for the democratic legitimacy of s.33.Footnote 15

This article offers a democracy-based critique of Waldron’s democracy-based account of the notwithstanding clause.Footnote 16 In brief, Waldron’s argument as applied to s.33 goes as follows.Footnote 17 In a society with inevitable disagreement about moral principles, the right of political participation ensures each citizen has a say in matters affecting their interests. Most importantly, it demonstrates the respect owed to each individual as a political equal capable of deliberating about politics, including the substance of rights. Political participation in a representative democracy culminates in the institution of the legislature, which has superior democratic legitimacy in comparison with the unelected judiciary. Democracy requires that the legislature be the venue for resolving conflicts about rights, including political rights. In this argument, legislative invocation of s.33 possesses an unimpeachable democratic pedigree. Allowing courts to decide moral matters or to resolve disputes about constitutional rights is a repudiation of political equality and is, therefore, anti-democratic. In the most robust version of this argument, concern about potential misuse of s.33 reflects undue cynicism as to the intentions of legislators and an elitist tendency to look down on voters by doubting their capacity to deliberate. Skepticism of s.33 has therefore sometimes been characterized not as trepidation about the potential misuse of state power, but as revealing reticence about democracy itself.Footnote 18

This article argues that there are contradictions at the heart of the Waldron-ian account of democracy and s.33, as the notwithstanding clause itself can be used to subvert democracy. Waldron’s argument is explicitly conditional on healthy democratic institutions already being in place and the right of political participation, which he calls the “right of rights,” being well-protected.Footnote 19 Such preconditions cannot be assumed, even in a country with a long democratic tradition such as Canada. The actual as opposed to the ideal operation of the main institutions of constitutional democracy, especially the legislature, must be assessed. The scope of s.33 also leaves significant room for the “right of rights” to be unduly restricted. Even though s.33 is inapplicable to the right to vote (s.3) and some structural democratic rights (ss.4-5), it applies to freedom of political expression and association (s.2) as well as equality rights (s.15), which are all directly relevant to elections. If Waldron is correct that invocations of s.33 are legitimate because of the democratic nature of a representative legislature, then uses of the notwithstanding clause that harm electoral accountability or political participation should be seen as illegitimate even on his own account. They are illegitimate for being inconsistent with the very reason that he argues we should respect the legislature in the first place. A truly democratic account of the notwithstanding clause must accept, in other words, limits on its use where the right to political participation, electoral accountability, or democracy writ large is in peril. The democratic legitimacy of any particular use of s.33 must be assessed in this light.

This article proceeds as follows. Section II sets out Waldron’s defence of s.33 on democratic grounds, including the centrality of political participation to his theory. Section III articulates the democracy-based critique of s.33. I will argue that Waldron’s account: 1) ignores the constitution of the legislature itself through elections; 2) assumes an ideal legislature with robust checks on political behaviour; and 3) over-estimates the capacity of elections to discipline misuse of s.33. As a result, the democracy-based defence of s.33 as articulated to date has failed to satisfactorily address the potential risks to democracy from misuse of the notwithstanding clause. That account is deficient for not recognizing limits on the legitimate uses of s.33. Section IV argues that the potential for s.33 to be used so as to harm political participation or electoral accountability remains a serious concern. In short, while the text of s.33 excludes ‘Democratic Rights’ in ss.3-5 of the Charter from s.33, many of the freedoms that make elections truly free and fair are still subject to the clause.Footnote 20 Section V concludes by considering the implications of these arguments.

II. The Democracy-Based Defence of s.33

a) The Waldron-ian Account

The main argument by proponents of more frequent invocation of s.33 by legislative bodies is based in a particular account of democracy. Whether used in response to a judicial decision striking down a statute as invalid on Charter grounds or pre-emptively in anticipation of such a result,Footnote 21 s.33 allows legislatures to have the final say on the rights and freedoms to which it applies.Footnote 22 As Jeffrey Goldsworthy writes, “the most powerful and popular argument against the judicial enforcement of constitutional rights maintains that it is undemocratic for unelected judges to invalidate laws enacted by a democratically elected legislature.”Footnote 23 While the democratic argument for constitutional interpretation by legislatures has several variations, the argument’s most thorough articulation comes from Jeremy Waldron. Waldron has also shaped the Canadian debate.Footnote 24 It is therefore worthwhile setting out in some detail Waldron’s claims regarding political participation, judicial review, and the legislature, as well as on s.33.

Waldron starts from the premise that there will be genuine differences in society that must be respected as to how rights should be interpreted.Footnote 25 The foundational right in a democracy is political participation, the “right of rights.”Footnote 26 Waldron rejects instrumental accounts of the rights to vote and participate in politics.Footnote 27 We should instead respect a right of political participation, Waldron argues, because of the “denigration that is involved when one person’s views are treated as of less account than the views of others on a matter that affects him as well as the others.”Footnote 28 The “peculiar insult” in denying a right of political participation to a person is due to the impact on the person’s “own rights and interests,” which are affected without their input.Footnote 29 Denying political rights means rejecting the excluded individual’s “capacity to decide responsibly” or to deliberate on the matter at issue.Footnote 30 The right of political participation stems from the “capacity of ordinary people for intelligent and conscientious moral deliberation.”Footnote 31 If we are to take seriously the equal moral worth of each individual and their capacities, we must respect their right to participate.

Given the inevitability of conflicting interpretations of rights and clashes between rights, we must collectively decide which institution is the preferred venue for resolving those conflicts. For Waldron, the answer is the legislature chosen by the people exercising their right to participate on equal terms and populated by legislators whose capacity to deliberate should also be respected. Waldron’s “central objection to judicial review is that it denies (or at least curtails) citizens’ ‘right to democratic participation’.”Footnote 32 Legislatures are the preferred institution in which to make decisions about “what rights we have.”Footnote 33 It is elitist and anti-democratic to have a “judicial aristocracy”Footnote 34 or “scholarly or judicial elite”Footnote 35 substitute their view as to how to resolve disputes about rights for that of the electorate channeled through the legislature. Judicial review is “politically illegitimate,” as “privileging majority voting among a small number of unelected and unaccountable judges … disenfranchises ordinary citizens and brushes aside cherished principles of representation and political equality.”Footnote 36 His method focuses on proceduresFootnote 37 for resolving disputes about rights, rather than an instrumental assessment of which institution is better able to provide specific outcomes.Footnote 38 Waldron’s claim that legislatures are generally superior to courts for resolving complex moral disputes is therefore based in the right of political participation, the equal moral worth of the individuals who elect the legislature, and the capacity of legislators to deliberate, rather than a weighing of which institution has been historically or is likely to be in the future the best rights protector.

In writing explicitly on s.33, Waldron applies his existing theory of the democratic legitimacy of the legislature based in the right of political participation. Section 33 is taken to be the ultimate articulation of parliamentary supremacy in the Canadian context, though a flawed one. In his view, s.33 does not go far enough in ensuring parliamentary supremacy over the courts. That is partly why Waldron classifies Canada as a system of strong rather than weak form judicial review, despite the notwithstanding clause.Footnote 39 Waldron wishes s.33 were used more often, but he sees it as too limited to ultimately foster a fully empowered democratic majority. Waldron therefore critiques the text of s.33 for being worded so as to imply that the legislature is ‘overriding’ the Charter. Footnote 40 The implication flowing from the text is that the legislature is overriding a particular right or freedom rather than offering its own interpretation that happens to genuinely differ from that of the courts. He also views the time-based limits on its use imposed by the 5-year sunset clause as overly restrictive.Footnote 41 Whatever his critiques of the particular ways in which the text of the Charter limits the reach of the notwithstanding clause, Waldron’s theory lends itself to a robust defence of s.33 on democratic grounds.

One possible response to Waldron’s argument that judicial review is democratically illegitimate is that it was political majorities in Canada who freely chose to entrench a bill of rights.Footnote 42 If political majorities have democratic legitimacy, then the decision in 1982 to entrench the Charter should be respected as should the subsequent decisions not to invoke s.33.Footnote 43 Waldron flatly rejects this line of argument.Footnote 44 He claims that if a legislature turns itself by legal means into a dictatorship, that doesn’t justify the choice on democratic grounds. Democracy has simply “been extinguished democratically,” as Jeffrey Goldsworthy puts it in summarizing Waldron’s view.Footnote 45 A democracy choosing an entrenched bill of rights in Waldron’s account means nothing less than “voting democracy out of existence, at least so far as a wide range of issues of political principle is concerned.”Footnote 46

United by concern for how best to preserve democracy, scholars have taken up versions of Waldron’s core arguments against judicial review in the context of the notwithstanding clause.Footnote 47 Now-Justice Grant Huscroft adopts Waldron’s reasoning in his academic analysis of the Charter and the notwithstanding clause.Footnote 48 Huscroft seeks to critique dialogue theory and, therefore, focuses to a large extent on the separation of powers.Footnote 49 He writes for example that,

I suspect that many proponents of dialogue theory would prefer that important decisions be made by the Supreme Court of Canada rather than Canadian legislatures. They cannot bring themselves to admit this essentially elitist position, however, because democracy has a greater hold on the public imagination than judicial review. For all of its imperfections, democracy affords a voice to the people who are governed, and for their part, the people rightly expect that they should be involved in making the decisions that concern them.Footnote 50

Huscroft picks up on Waldron’s claim that allowing judicial review on rights grounds undermines the individual’s right to political participation, understood mainly as the right to have a say on matters that affect them.

Dwight Newman also argues for more frequent use of s.33 primarily on what appear to be democratic grounds. He adopts a version of Waldron’s argument, though one that departs from it by setting out some general categories of illegitimate legislative action. Newman critiques extreme skepticism of legislatures’ capacity to deliberate and of s.33 as contrary to “the very idea of democratic governance,” which rests on faith in elected representatives.Footnote 51 Like Waldron, he emphasizes political constraints on s.33: “Parliamentarians and legislatures contemplating the use of the notwithstanding clause must act in a politically responsible manner.”Footnote 52 He goes beyond Waldron by setting out some specific limits on s.33. He writes that the notwithstanding clause’s “routine” use is objectionable and that it “would not be appropriate to have legislatures excessively involved in second-guessing judicial decisions on an everyday basis.”Footnote 53

Jeffrey Goldsworthy’s comparative analysis of parliamentary sovereignty has Canada as a prominent case study, including detailed consideration of s.33.Footnote 54 He argues that s. 33 is a sign of respect for the wisdom of the electorate, which selects representatives, rather than merely an institutional division of labour granting power over constitutional interpretation to the legislature in some circumstances. To doubt the wisdom of the electorate is anti-democratic in his argument, as on Waldron’s. “[All democrats] should have considerable faith in the inherent intelligence, knowledge and virtue of the electorate.”Footnote 55 Goldsworthy argues that s.33 offers the possibility of more democratic constitutional politics than one dominated by courts: “In principle, an override clause such as s.33 should help legislators resist the democratic debilitation that might otherwise attend the legalization of rights.”Footnote 56 It is courts that threaten democracy on his account, not the majority acting contrary to minority interests. Goldsworthy’s account echoes Waldron’s in tying the legitimacy of the legislature to the respect owed to the electorate and in viewing s.33 as the ultimate assertion of the authority of the democratically elected legislature in Canada.

III. A Democracy-Based Critique of the Notwithstanding Clause

a) Introduction

The democracy-based accounts of s.33 set out above generally do not address the threat to democracy from the misuse of the notwithstanding clause in ways that substantially undermine representative democracy. This section lays out a democracy-based critique of the democratic defence of the notwithstanding clause. It makes three main critiques.

First, Waldron’s account of democracy and s.33 ignores the constitution of the legislature through elections. Some laws passed by the legislature using the generally-accepted procedures would undermine the representativeness or democratic legitimacy of the legislature itself. Waldron’s account in particular is explicitly based on several assumptions, which set aside this possibility of legislative misbehaviour. For his theory to be correct, Waldron requires us to assume away the risk that self-dealing legislatures will at times craft election laws that hinder fair terms of democratic competition or restrict the right of rights. This willing suspension of disbelief wishes away some of the most pressing problems for contemporary democracy, including the prospect of a legislature that is composed of an appreciable number of members who are hostile to the institutions and rights that make democracy possible.

Second, the legislature in the democratic account of s.33 is envisioned in an idealized fashion, rather than assessed on its actual performance. The critique that Waldron views the legislature in overly optimistic terms has long been a standard one.Footnote 57 What is worthy of further elaboration in the context of s.33 is the degree to which Waldron’s account rejects any evaluation of the actual performance of legislatures, courts, and executives in securing or undermining rights. The many critics of judicial review post-Charter have catalogued in great detail the failings of courts and how they actually operate. The defenders of s.33, however, do not engage in a similarly skeptical manner with the actual operation of the legislature. They are idealists about legislatures, but realists about courts. They are following Waldron in that respect, who mounts an abstract defence of legislatures as an institution. I argue instead that it is unpersuasive to adopt a one-sided account of institutions. In the context of s.33 we need to assess the likelihood that the legislature will act irresponsibly, even if it acts responsibly most of the time on most issues. The gravity of s.33’s potential misuse for Canadian democracy requires no less.Footnote 58 Even though s.33 does not apply to the democratic rights in ss.3-5 of the Charter, there is still much room for it to have an impact on political participation through s. 2 and s.15.

Third, the defences of s.33 as democratic require heavy reliance on electoral accountability as disciplining governments and legislatures. The text of s.33(3) imposes a 5-year sunset clause on invocations of the notwithstanding clause, which facilitates periodic electoral accountability since there must be a general election at least every five years.Footnote 59 If the courts cannot check legislatures because s.33 has been invoked, then the electorate can, as the theory goes. The implication of that claim is that if misuses of s.33 can be checked at the ballot box, then there is less reason to worry about the notwithstanding clause being used to undermine democracy. For a variety of reasons, however, elections are imperfect accountability mechanisms if the goal is retrospective accountability. The realistic prospect of the sunset clause facilitating electoral accountability should not be over-stated.

If the critiques of Waldron’s account have salience, then uses of s.33 which harm electoral democracy are illegitimate, even on Waldron’s own reasoning. They contradict the very reason that Waldron’s account tells us that s.33 exists. Waldron’s theory is unable to justify limits on political rights because of the foundational nature of political participation to his account. The legislature has legitimacy by virtue of being chosen by free and equal citizens exercising their right to political participation. The right of rights has special primacy in Waldron’s account. On Waldron’s logic, if s. 33 in the Canadian constitutional order is the ultimate assertion of legislative sovereignty, then it is legitimate because of its democratic pedigree. If the legislature uses the notwithstanding clause in a manner that harms the right of political participation or electoral competition, however, then it forfeits that legitimacy. Using s.33 to harm the right of rights means denying equal concern and respect to individuals who have a stake, because their rights or interests are affected, and who have a capacity to deliberate. The reason for respecting the legislature as the institution in which to resolve disputes about rights, on Waldron’s own argument, dissolves if the legislature opts to thwart the right of rights or was elected under conditions that were less than free and fair. Under such conditions, the legislature cannot be assumed to be the institution which best reflects respect for rights holders.

Most importantly, his theory fails to provide resources that would allow us to distinguish democracy-enhancing from democracy-harming actions by the legislature. Waldron assigns political legitimacy to institutions, rather than focusing on outcomes for rights holders, and then deliberately ignores the actual functioning of those bodies. Waldron’s idealized portrait of legislatures therefore incorporates no concrete limits on how they should use their authority. In his verve to mount as robust a defence of legislatures as possible, he fails to give due credence to the basic reality that any state power can be misused. One of the central challenges for constitutional democracy in Canada in a world where the notwithstanding clause is regularly used is how to assess the political legitimacy of those exercises of legislative power. Waldron’s theory does not provide guidance.

b) The Constitution of the Legislature Through Elections

One of the defining and enduring challenges of contemporary democracy is the problem of self-dealing by legislatures. Representatives are elected by the laws established by the legislature to structure elections. Elected representatives compete in the game, but also shape its rules. There is an ongoing risk, therefore, that legislatures will design the rules of the game to favour themselves in some way, rather than acting public-mindedly in legislating the operation of elections.Footnote 60 Whether laws are crafted to facilitate a particular partisan outcome or to protect incumbents, there is plentiful evidence of self-dealing on election laws in countries with long democratic track records, including parliamentary democracies.Footnote 61

If there is a risk of behaviour by the legislature that targets political rights, insulates its members from the full force of electoral accountability, and so on, then the presence of s.33 exacerbates the challenge. Contemporary democracies have a variety of accountability mechanisms applicable to those wielding public power. Elections, political checks within the legislature and executive including conventions of responsible government, review by the courts, dissent expressed within political parties, independent institutions such as the election commission, the media, and so on all act to discipline political behaviour. Elections are not the only accountability mechanism, but they are an indispensable and defining one for democracy to exist. Section 33 provides the opportunity for the legislature to undermine electoral accountability by stymying judicial invalidation of laws that would otherwise be found to violate democratic rights.

Waldron assumes away this problem by relying on four explicit assumptions in his argument on the merits of legislatures as the preferred institution for resolving disputes about rights. Waldron’s argument assumes the presence of: 1) “democratic institutions in reasonably good working order, including a representative legislature elected on the basis of universal adult suffrage”; 2) judicial institutions “in reasonably good order”; 3) a societal commitment to individual and minority rights; and 4) “persisting, substantial, and good faith disagreement about rights … among the members of the society who are committed to the idea of rights.”Footnote 62

Adopting these assumptions is tantamount to assuming away the strongest objections to his democracy-based critique of judicial review. These assumptions allow Waldron to say that even if courts and legislatures are both operating in “good order,” legislatures remain the preferred and most legitimate institution in which to resolve disputes about rights. They also mean, however, that he does not address breaches of political morality by the legislature, including legislative action that harms the right of rights.Footnote 63 In the Canadian context, the concrete risk is that legislative supremacy facilitated by regular use of s.33 and unchecked by the courts or other institutions could lead to the diminution of minority rights of political participation.Footnote 64

Waldron does provide further details regarding what he means by the assumption of healthy “democratic institutions.”Footnote 65 He says for the assumption to hold, elections must be “fair and regular.”Footnote 66 He assumes the presence of bicameralism, deliberation within the legislative bodies, internal procedures for passing laws, the presence of parties, and so on. He tries to set aside any critique of his account by stating: “None of this is meant to be controversial; it picks out the way in which democratic legislatures usually operate.… I am assuming that the democratic institutions are in reasonably good order. They may not be perfect.”Footnote 67 He then goes on to stipulate a culture that respects “political equality” as part of his argument.Footnote 68

None of these details address the prospect of unhealthy democratic institutions or the particular problem of self-dealing. The closest he gets to acknowledging this critique is to write that, “It is sometimes said that elective institutions are incapable of reforming themselves because legislators have an entrenched interest in the status quo.”Footnote 69 He acknowledges that this concern may be a relevant one, but confines its salience to the United States and claims, “It is patently false elsewhere.”Footnote 70 The only example he provides to substantiate this general claim about democracy globally is one particular example from New Zealand, namely the transition from a first past the post to a mixed-member proportional system (MMP) in the 1990s.Footnote 71 There is plentiful evidence in the political science literature, however, that choice of electoral system is one of the areas of legislative or government authority where self-dealing is most clearly evident.Footnote 72 The evidence isn’t that legislatures are always bad faith actors, but that self-dealing by legislatures is a pervasive and ongoing problem that Waldron unduly downplays.

The right of political participation is so integral to Waldron’s theory that he argues it should not be limited to further other rights or principles.Footnote 73 Section 33 allows legislatures a nearly unfettered hand to restrict political participation, however, with the exception of the right to vote. I agree with Waldron that the right of rights is indeed special and requires unique protection, given that it is foundational to self-government. Waldron’s insistence on a pure theory of legislative supremacy, however, amounts to unilateral disarmament in the ongoing struggle to preserve democratic governance. Rather than seeking to check potentially serious consequences for democracy of its misuse, Waldron’s theory simply asks us to trust the legislature. A defence of s.33 on the basis that legislatures always have democratic legitimacy in all of their actions ignores the serious consequences for democracy if the notwithstanding clause is misused to limit political participation and free and fair elections. It also stands in contradiction with Waldron’s own adoption of the right of rights as the centrepiece of his theory of institutional legitimacy.

c) The Non-Ideal Legislature

The advent of the Charter forced Canada to wrestle with the presence of a written bill of rights enforceable by the courts alongside the tradition of parliamentary sovereignty.Footnote 74 With newfound authority granted by the framers and embraced by the judiciary, the courts have deservedly come under intense scrutiny in the 40 years of living with the Charter. The advocates for more frequent use of the notwithstanding clause have been unsparing in their criticism of the actual operation of courts, as opposed to their theoretical role in rights protection. Legislatures deserve equal scrutiny, especially if they are going to be more forceful in exercising the powers granted to them in s. 33. We should not be realists about courts but idealists about legislatures.Footnote 75

While writing in the political constitutionalist tradition,Footnote 76 Waldron’s lack of skepticism with regard to the legislature is at odds with one of the leading lights of that line of thought, J.A.G. Griffith.Footnote 77 Griffith in his famous “The Political Constitution” argues for healthy skepticism toward all institutions wielding public power, the legislature included.Footnote 78 Tom Poole writes that,

‘The Political Constitution’ is no paean for democracy, then, but is better read as a diatribe aimed at instilling a rigorous scepticism into constitutional thinking. We should—indeed, if we value our freedoms, must—be sceptical in the face of all claims and justifications for power, whether the claim comes from a judge [or a] politician.Footnote 79

The Waldron-ian lack of skepticism toward the legislature is reflected in the writing of Canadian scholars who apply categories to understand how the notwithstanding clause has been used to date. Janet Hiebert sets out four categories for how s.33 has been invoked.Footnote 80 The first is political protest in the early years of the Charter, particularly Quebec’s “omnibus and retroactive” use of s.33 from 1982-1985.Footnote 81 Quebec purported to apply the notwithstanding clause to all legislation, which led to the decision of the Supreme Court of Canada in Ford v Quebec in 1988 setting procedural limits on s.33’s invocation.Footnote 82 The second and third are forms of risk aversion in the face of uncertainty about how the courts would interpret the Charter.Footnote 83 Such risk aversion can lead legislatures to pre-emptively use s.33 even prior to the invalidation by the courts of a statute for non-compliance with the Charter. Hiebert provides examples mainly from the early years of the Charter as evidence of the relevance of these categories.Footnote 84 The fourth and most important category is political disagreement over judicial interpretation of the Charter. It is here that Parliament or a legislature would offer a different interpretation of a Charter right or freedom than do the courts. The now much-recited argument that it is a misnomer to label s.33 as the ‘override’ provision rests primarily on this category. On this theory, the legislature is merely offering a different interpretation of a provision.

While not explicit on the underlying normative assumptions, Hiebert like Waldron does not address the possibility that the legislature functions less than ideally. Hiebert’s four categories do not include one for misuse of s.33 in regard to political participation rights or otherwise. That legislatures do not always behave in a perfectly deliberative fashion, or that they may engage in self-dealing in setting election law, or that they may discriminate against an unpopular minority are simply not part of the categories. Hiebert does draw a distinction between constitutional interpretations put forward by Parliament in “good faith,” as opposed to “rolling the dice” where the law seems certain to be ruled unconstitutional.Footnote 85 That distinction, however, goes to the likelihood of a law being invalidated by the courts, not whether the legislature is acting in good faith. Hiebert proposes technical changes to the role of the Minister of Justice and Parliamentary committees in assessing possible invocations of s.33 and constitutional interpretations.Footnote 86 While such reforms have merit as a general matter, it is hard to see them acting as a robust enough check against a determined government.

A potential response to skepticism of legislatures is that the public-mindedness of responsible legislators protects against misuse of s.33. Waldron argues that we should have faith that “voters and legislators are capable of focusing their deliberations on the general good.”Footnote 87 Concern for the possibility that s.33 will be misused, however, doesn’t turn on an anti-democratic rejection of the capacity of voters and legislators. As Aileen Kavanagh put it in an early critique of Waldron: “Capacity for moral judgement is not inconsistent with moral fallibility.”Footnote 88

There are also structural reasons to worry about the actual as opposed to idealized performance of Canadian legislatures, particularly around checking governments and engaging in deliberation about rights. Canadian politics is characterized by high levels of party discipline, executive dominance, and the centralization of power in the Prime Minister or Premier’s office.Footnote 89 There is plenty of evidence that shows that political checks within legislatures are not as robust as they should be. The House of Commons may also operate very differently than a provincial legislature with no upper house, less media scrutiny, and so on. While legislators of course have agency, to be blunt they are often closely directed by the executive.

The role of the executive is generally under-theorized in Waldron’s considerable oeuvre. For example, he does not engage with judicial review of executive action in administrative law, which is generally seen even by political constitutionalists as legitimate.Footnote 90 Most importantly in relation to political legitimacy, Waldron fails to account for a strong executive that in contemporary democracies tends to dominate the legislature. Many other leading constitutional theories have not adequately engaged with the reality of executive dominance of the legislature.Footnote 91 For Waldron, it is a particularly serious omission. To the extent that the executive dominates the legislature, then the hierarchy of political legitimacy that he advances with the legislature at the top is less persuasive. If what is formally legislative action is tightly controlled by the executive in practice most of the time on most issues, then the search for political legitimacy is not purely a contrast between the courts and the legislature, but between the courts and the executive as well. If it is not the elected executive but its unelected components that direct the government, Waldron’s claims are even harder to sustain. Put bluntly, the question is not always, “Should nine unelected lawyers in robes or the elected legislature decide?” It can also be, “Should unelected political staffers in the Prime Minister’s Office decide?” The answer to such a question is messier than the artificial zero-sum competition over political legitimacy set up by Waldron between courts and legislatures.

One of the early defenders of s.33, Peter Russell, qualified his support for the provision on an evaluation of how legislatures actually operate.Footnote 92 He argued that while over-reliance on judicial review should be critiqued, support for the notwithstanding clause should be conditional on it being “properly used,” by which he meant “only after a reasoned debate in the legislature.”Footnote 93 While Russell was optimistic that Canadian legislatures mostly behaved deliberately,Footnote 94 more recent studies have shown that there is little evidence of serious deliberation regarding the notwithstanding clause within legislatures when s.33 is invoked.Footnote 95

Some advocates of s.33 have responded to concerns about the functioning of the legislature by dismissing them as the fault of courts and the Charter. To the extent that legislatures operate in a less than ideal fashion, that is because courts through judicial review have usurped the legislature’s constitutional role,Footnote 96 therefore leading to ‘democratic debilitation’.Footnote 97 The argument makes the claim that while the deliberative features of legislatures as interpreters of rights may have diminished in response to judicial supremacy post-Charter, legislative capacity can be built back up in short order.Footnote 98 Normalizing the use of s.33 would lead to the resuscitation of legislatures.

To say that the failings of legislatures are the fault of courts is unpersuasive. The argument assumes without providing evidence that the atrophying of the legislature’s role in interpreting the Constitution is primarily a result of the Charter itself and the expansion of judicial power. Substantiating the causal claim that the Charter has led to democratic debilitation would require establishing some golden age for Parliament and the provincial legislatures prior to 1982 characterized by deep deliberation about rights compared with the post-1982 reality. No such evidence has been provided. Part of the motivation for an entrenched bill of rights in the first place was the uneven commitment to rights by legislatures and governments prior to 1982. Even without the Charter, structural barriers to meaningful deliberation on rights by the legislature would remain, such as party discipline, executive dominance, and the role of unelected political staffers.

It is important to be clear that I am in no way arguing that only legislatures and executives can behave anti-democratically. Judges sometimes make errors, issue decisions shaped by their personal political preferences, defend the institutional interests of the judiciary, or, even, act with hostility toward democracy. There are prominent instances of courts harming the right of rights. For example, the United States Supreme Court’s current majority is hindering democracy and deliberately tilting the electoral playing field.Footnote 99 Waldron’s warning that courts often err and do not always protect rights remains powerful, especially in the context of judges acting as partisans.Footnote 100 The possibility that a court might behave anti-democratically is certainly one that must be taken seriously.

A default view that legislatures protect rights and that any decision-making by courts is unavoidably anti-democratic, however, is one-sided. A more even-handed approach than Waldron’s should recognize that democracy is always vulnerable and that there are multiple pressure points. All institutions wielding public power are fallible and should be scrutinized. The scale of the likely risks to democracy in any given system must be carefully evaluated. Part of that assessment is a context-specific one about which branch is more likely to protect rights and which is more likely to hinder their realization.

In some of his more recent work, Waldron has conceded that political majorities may not always be reliably on the side of rights protection for some unpopular minorities, for whom the courts are the best institutional ally. He argues that “criminals and criminal suspects” can be seen as the “beneficiaries of judicial review” in New Zealand, for example.Footnote 101 Waldron is here relaxing his famous four assumptions and accepting some of the basic premises of political process theory espoused by John Hart ElyFootnote 102 and encapsulated in the famous Footnote #4 from the decision of the United States Supreme Court in Carolene Products.Footnote 103 Carolene Products opined that judicial review should protect “discrete and insular minorities” and Ely was particularly concerned with the political rights of such groups.Footnote 104 While expressing reservation about making too much of the point, Waldron concedes that “any general account of the value or otherwise of judicial review ought to include a sober assessment of those cases (whether many or few) where political circumstances make it unlikely that minorities will be able to secure their rights through the ordinary political process.”Footnote 105

If the political process regularly fails certain minorities, then we should certainly be attuned to the possibility that s.33 can and will be used in a way that harms minority rights. If the political process is likely to fail them and the courts are barred from intervening by s.33, then minorities will be in a distinctly precarious position. It is hard to sustain the argument that all uses of s.33 are ‘democratic’ if used to harm the political rights of discrete and insular minorities. Viewed in this light, the potential misuse of s.33 is not a boutique concern or remote possibility, but a defining challenge given the particular make-up of Canadian constitutional democracy.

d) Imperfect Electoral Accountability

The account of the notwithstanding clause as having impeccable democratic credentials also rests on a particular set of assumptions as to how elections operate. Arguments that the notwithstanding clause should be used more regularly tend to emphasize that the public gets to pass judgment at the ballot box on invocations of s.33. If a government and legislature choose to attack the political rights of a minority group and shield it from judicial review by use of s.33, the wisdom of the disapproving electorate remains as the ultimate check.

Waldron and Goldsworthy’s deep faith in the wisdom of the electorate as a collective and in the capacity of individual citizens to deliberate is the foundation of their defence of political majorities. The electorate’s role is to deliberate about rights and public policy and to elect representatives who will exercise their judgment.Footnote 106 Elections are the ultimate accountability mechanism if elected representatives err and, on this theory, legislatures can be punished for misuse of s.33 by voters.Footnote 107 In sum, the account of s.33 as democratic relies on an assumption that elections are mechanisms of retrospective political accountability.

This account finds resonance in the text of s.33. Section 33(3) states that a declaration made under s.33(1) “shall cease to have effect five years after it comes into force.”Footnote 108 Five years is the maximum duration of Parliament or a provincial legislature under s.4(1) of the Charter. Section 33(3) therefore ensures the electorate has the opportunity to pass judgment on the legislature’s invocation of s.33 prior to its expiration.Footnote 109 Section 33(3) has little impact, however, if the notwithstanding clause has been used to diminish the political rights of those likely to oppose the invocation of s.33. The idea of elections as mechanisms of retrospective accountability for misuse of s.33 evaporates if the notwithstanding clause is used in a fashion that harms the right of political participation to a non-trivial extent.

Imagine a legislature that banned a political party in a province. Such actions could plausibly be seen by the courts as being primarily a matter of freedom of association, which is protected in s.2 of the Charter and subject to the notwithstanding clause.Footnote 110 The capacity of the electorate to fulfill its constitutional role in holding a government and legislature to account would be hindered if that party had a substantial level of support. If the political rights of the electorate are reduced through invocation of s.33 and the harm is beyond the reach of courts to remedy, it will be of great consequence whether the restriction is significant enough to hinder electoral accountability.

Robert Leckey and Eric Mendelsohn offer a more compelling view on the role of the electorate in relation to s.33. In their assessment, s. 33(3) makes clear that the “legitimacy [of legislatures] in matters concerning the notwithstanding clause derives from democratic support” and that “the use of the notwithstanding clause requires the electorate’s ongoing, or at least episodic, democratic consent.”Footnote 111 They rightfully encourage us to focus on “the electorate’s ability to play the constitutional role assigned to it by subsection 33(3).”Footnote 112 The capacity of the electorate to fulfill its constitutional role may in fact be hindered by uses of s.33 that harm political participation at a non-trivial level.

Elections are also not necessarily straightforward mechanisms of retrospective accountability. The electorate must consider multiple factors in its deliberations. The electorate sits in judgment of the decision to invoke s.33, the justifications on offer for doing so, the quality of deliberation in the legislature on the matter, the impact on rights and freedoms, and the alternate vision of the constitution that the legislature substitutes for the actual or anticipated one of the courts. Even where voters may consider an invocation of s.33 to be abhorrent, however, the prospect of imposing retrospective accountability may reasonably be outweighed by other considerations viewed from the perspective of an individual voter. Voters may favour re-electing the government when considering alternate possible governing parties. Other issues than s.33 may dominate the political campaign and seem the most important basis upon which to cast a ballot. There has been no Canadian political campaign in recent memory in which the decision to use s.33 dominated the discussion among voters. In other words, voters may reason prospectively about the government and policies they want in the future rather than focusing on retrospective accounting for past political misdeeds.

Assuming as we should and as Waldron and Goldsworthy would have us do that voters are well-intentioned and highly capable, the electorate may still opt not to punish misuse of s.33 for valid reasons. While it is certainly possible that voters will cast ballots on the basis of s.33, the assumption that elections provide a robust check should not be over-stated. Being skeptical of elections as mechanisms of retrospective accountability does not reflect doubt as to the capacities of voters. Rather, it reflects a nuanced and realistic understanding of how elections actually operate.

IV. The Text of the Charter and the Problem of Scope

While the preceding portions of the article have largely addressed the relationship between s.33 and democracy generally, it is worth considering in more detail the particular ways that the notwithstanding clause can be used in relation to democratic rights and freedoms. This section addresses what one can call the scope of the notwithstanding clause and the potential impact of its more frequent use on democratic rights and freedoms. Section 33 applies only to sections 2 and 7-15 of the Charter, but not to sections 3-5,Footnote 113 which are grouped under the heading of ‘Democratic Rights’.Footnote 114 As a consequence, s.33 cannot be used in relation to the right to vote contained in s.3.

One argument available to those who wish to see the notwithstanding clause invoked more frequently is therefore that any potential harms to democratic rights are insignificant, because the text of the Charter precludes the use of s.33 in relation to them. In my view such an argument is unpersuasive. This section makes two main points.

First, the exclusion of sections 3-5 from the scope of s.33 was a meaningful design choice that reveals underlying normative commitments about the need to protect democracy. Recognition that the notwithstanding clause can be misused in a manner that harms political participation and the legislature’s democratic legitimacy is built into the text of the notwithstanding clause.

Second, the text adopts a solution to protecting core electoral rights and freedoms from the notwithstanding clause that is at best partial and incomplete. Many rights and freedoms essential to flourishing democratic competition are outside of sections 3-5 and are thus potentially subject to the notwithstanding clause. These most importantly include the freedom of association and expression in s.2 and the equality rights in s.15. In other words, the risk to democratic rights and freedoms remains considerable even if ss.3-5 are excluded from the scope of s.33.

a) The Exclusion of Sections 3-5 and Its Underlying Meaning

The exclusion of sections 3-5 from the ambit of s.33 is significant because these provisions protect core democratic rights. Section 3 enshrines the right of each citizen to voteFootnote 115 and to stand as a candidateFootnote 116 in federal and provincial elections. Section 3 also guarantees the “meaningful participation”Footnote 117 of individuals and their “effective representation”Footnote 118 when electoral boundaries are drawn. Unlike s.3, which pertains directly to the rights of individual citizens, sections 4 and 5 operate as structural protections for free and fair elections.

Section 4 sets five years as the maximum time between elections, as discussed in the section on electoral accountability. While legislation now often sets fixed election dates, s. 4(1) sets “an upper limit [between elections] to ensure regular accountability to the electorate” as a constitutional matter.Footnote 119 It works as an indirect guarantee of regular elections.Footnote 120 The Court of Appeal for Alberta held that s. 4(1) codifies “the government’s right to call a general election at any time during the period of five years.”Footnote 121 There has been little litigation on s.4 because in the Charter era, legislatures have respected the five year maximum.Footnote 122

Section 5 requires the House of Commons and provincial legislatures to meet at least once a year.Footnote 123 It is based on earlier Canadian constitutional provisions and long-standing British tradition. One of the vulnerabilities of parliamentary democracy is that Parliament may simply not be convened on a regular basis. If it is not, then the executive may continue to act without having to test the confidence of the House. Particularly after an election that signals a likely change in government, a refusal to convene the legislature for an unreasonable amount of time undermines parliamentary democracy.

While not encompassing all of the minimum core of democracy, a universal franchise, regular and routine elections, and a requirement for the legislature to meet annually are necessary conditions for parliamentary democracy.Footnote 124 All of the potential abuses by legislatures or governments of democratic rights that would have been made possible by an application of s.33 to ss.3-5 have long pedigrees in Canada, the U.K., and elsewhere. The framers anticipated Canada’s future on the basis of these past experiences. Prior to the Charter, for example, Parliament and the provincial legislatures repeatedly denied groups of citizens the right to cast a ballot, for partisan reasons or with discriminatory intent, against groups deemed unworthy.Footnote 125

The text of the Charter therefore identifies misuse of s.33 in relation to democratic rights as one of the potential flaws in the new, post-1982 constitutional order that needed to be addressed in advance. The best interpretation of the exclusion of ‘democratic rights’ from the scope of s.33’s is an attempt to prevent legislatures or executives from undermining regular elections, transitions between governments, and a broad-based electorate of all adult citizens. The notwithstanding clause is structured in such a way as to attempt to minimize the chance that irresponsible legislative action could permanently harm the democratic foundations of the Canadian constitutional order.

b) The Problem of Scope

The exclusion of these ‘democratic rights’ as labelled in the Charter itself from s.33 is therefore an important and consequential decision and a recognition of the fragility of democracy. Sections 3-5 of the Charter, however, do not come close to covering all of the rights and freedoms directly relevant to ensuring a flourishing democracy. A host of other relevant Charter rights and freedoms to full realization of the ‘right of rights’ are still subject to s.33.

Freedom of political expression in s.2(b) ensures that individuals and groups can criticize the government and campaign for or against political parties and candidates. Section 2 also protects freedom of the press, which is undeniably important in a democracy. Pre-Charter, restrictions on the media or criticism of the government were sometimes imposed, especially by the Provinces.Footnote 126 Freedom of association protects the capacity of individuals to organize themselves collectively into political parties, interest groups, ‘third party’ election advertisers, and so on.Footnote 127 The equality right in s.15 guarantees that candidates and voters cannot be treated differentially on the basis of prohibited grounds in a manner that is discriminatory. There may be instances where s.15 rather than s.3 applies.

In many Charter cases involving political participation, it will be clear whether s.2, or s.3 or s.15 or some other provision is the applicable one. Where there is less clarity, the threshold question of which provision applies to a particular Charter claim ends up being consequential, as it determines whether s.33 can be invoked or not.Footnote 128 This fact has always been the case since the introduction of the Charter in 1982, but was previously of marginal importance in the context of less regular use of s.33. The stakes are therefore high for categorizing a claim as either falling within or outside of the scope of s.33. While the text of s.33 prevents some of the worst potential outcomes for democracy, it still applies to rights and freedoms that have a significant role in ensuring a functioning electoral process.

V. Conclusion: Implications for Canadian Democracy

This article has argued that the prevailing theory of the legitimacy of the notwithstanding clause does not and, indeed cannot, establish all uses of s.33 by the legislature as ‘democratic’. Waldron’s commitment to democracy is an admirable one. Yet his theory cannot do the work that advocates for more frequent or regular use of s.33 in Canada claim that it does. Waldron’s account of democracy and judicial review is akin to a scientific theory that appears valid in the lab, but that fails under real world conditions. Waldron assumes away challenges that are central to the life of Canadian constitutional democracy.

Contrary to Waldron and his defenders, acknowledging the potential misuse of legislative power through s.33 does not entail faint-heartedness about democracy and does not compel us to adopt an elitist account that sneers at voters. We can be democrats with an optimistic account of the good intentions of most elected representatives, most of the time, while still recognizing the fallibility of legislatures and the structural barriers that operate against rights protection. We can respect the deliberative capacities and political judgement of voters without assuming that the electorate will always punish abuses of minority rights. We can be skeptical of the merits of the likely or potential uses of s.33 by legislatures without adopting the view that courts are infallible. Whether a particular decision by Parliament or a provincial legislature is democracy enhancing or detracting requires the political community to make such an assessment on a case-by-case basis.

Debates around the notwithstanding clause over its first 40 years have tended to focus on its general impact, rather than how it is used in relation to specific rights or freedoms.Footnote 129 Particular attention to the relationship between s.33 and political rights and freedoms, however, is warranted in the current environment. The political restraint that allowed Canadians the luxury of not having to consider the full range of uses to which s.33 could be put appears to have dissolved. By placing the right to vote and some structural democratic rights outside of the scope of the notwithstanding clause, the text of s.33 prevents some exercises of the notwithstanding power in relation to democracy. There is still significant scope, however, for s.33 in relation to political participation. Given the potential consequences, special attention should be paid to the application of s.33 to political rights and freedoms.

If the basis for the notwithstanding clause is democracy, then on Waldron’s own account, invoking s.33 in a manner that harms the ‘right of rights’ should be seen as illegitimate. Equality of political participation is the foundation for his conclusion that the legislature possesses democratic legitimacy. If political participation is restricted, then the legislature’s legitimacy is reduced. While misuse of legislative authority so as to harm democracy has always been a theoretical concern with accounts that emphasize parliamentary sovereignty, such concerns are heightened in the context of more regular use of s.33. Unprincipled use of s.33 against the political rights and freedoms of unpopular minorities or political opponents would have serious, negative consequences for Canadian democracy.

Acknowledgments

This article benefitted greatly from feedback on presentations at The Public Law Conference at University College Dublin, the University of British Columbia Allard School of Law, and the University of Texas-Austin. I would like to thank in particular David Dyzenhaus, Gavin Phillipson, Margot Young, Hoi Kong, Richard Mailey, Vanessa MacDonnell, Peter Oliver, Aileen Kavanagh, Gerard Kennedy, Léonid Sirota, Ido Porat, Eric Adams, Victor Ramraj, Vrinda Narain, Robert Leckey, Martha Jackman, Kerri Froc, Gerard Kennedy, Catherine Dauvergne, and Patrick Baud for feedback, discussion, and/or comments. I would also like to thank the editors of the Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence and the reviewers of this article. Maddie Bell provided excellent research assistance.

References

1. See Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms, Part I of the Constitution Act, 1982, being Schedule B to the Canada Act 1982 (UK), 1982, c 11 [Charter].

2. Janet L Hiebert, “The Notwithstanding Clause: Why Non-use Does Not Necessarily Equate with Abiding by Judicial Norms” in Peter Oliver, Patrick Macklem & Nathalie Des Rosiers, eds, The Oxford Handbook of the Canadian Constitution (Oxford University Press, 2017) 695 at 695.

3. See Guillaume Rousseau & François Côté, “A Distinctive Quebec Theory and Practice of the Notwithstanding Clause: When Collective Interests Outweigh Individual Rights” (2017) 47:2 RGD 343.

4. See Hiebert, supra note 2 at 698; Janet L Hiebert, “Compromise and the Notwithstanding Clause: Why the Dominant Narrative Distorts Our Understanding” in James B Kelly & Christopher P Manfredi, eds, Contested Constitutionalism: Reflections on the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms (UBC Press, 2009) 107; Tsvi Kahana, “The Notwithstanding Mechanism and Public Discussion: Lessons from the Ignored Practice of Section 33 of the Charter” (2001) 44:3 Canadian Public Administration 255; Tsvi Kahana, “Understanding the Notwithstanding Mechanism” (2002) 52:2 UTLJ 221 [Kahana, “Understanding Notwithstanding”]; Jeffrey Goldsworthy, Parliamentary Sovereignty: Contemporary Debates (Cambridge University Press, 2010) at 204; Eric M Adams & Erin R J Bower, “Notwithstanding History: The Rights-Protecting Purposes of Section 33 of the Charter” (2022) 26:2 Rev Const Stud 121.

5. Richard Albert, “Advisory Review: The Reincarnation of the Notwithstanding Clause” (2008) 45:4 Alta L Rev 1037 at 1038.

6. “[I]ndeed, a constitutional convention against [s.33]’s use may have formed everywhere except in Quebec.” Goldsworthy, supra note 4 at 204. On Quebec’s use of s.33, see Rousseau & Côté, supra note 3; Noura Karazivan & Jean-François Gaudreault-DesBiens, “Rights Trivialization, Constitutional Legitimacy Deficit, and Derogation Clauses: The Example of Quebec’s Laïcity Act” (2020) 99 SCLR 2d 487.

7. Grant Huscroft, “Constitutionalism from the Top Down” (2007) 45:1 Osgoode Hall LJ 91 at 96.

8. A sign of the fact that s.33 is now on the table is the concerted interest by scholars in whether there is a role for courts after its invocation. See Grégoire Webber, “Notwithstanding Rights, Review, or Remedy? On the Notwithstanding Clause and the Operation of Legislation” (2021) 71:4 UTLJ 510; Robert Leckey & Eric Mendelsohn, “The Notwithstanding Clause: Legislatures, Courts, and the Electorate” (2022) 72:2 UTLJ 189; Robert Leckey, “Advocacy Notwithstanding the Notwithstanding Clause” (2019) 28:4 Const Forum Const 1; Maxime St-Hilaire & Xavier F Ménard, “Nothing to Declare: A Response to Grégoire Webber, Eric Mendelsohn, Robert Leckey, and Léonid Sirota on the Effects of the Notwithstanding Clause” (2022) 29:1 Const Forum Const 38; Geoffrey Sigalet, “Legislated Rights as Trumps: Why the Notwithstanding Clause Overrides Judicial Review” (2023) 61:1 Osgoode Hall LJ; Brian Bird & Kristopher Kinsinger, “Constitutional Exegesis, Animating Principles and City of Toronto” (2022) 110 SCLR 2d 38 at 54-55.

9. Working Families v Ontario, 2021 ONSC 4076 struck down campaign finance spending limits on third party/interest group spending in the pre-electoral period as a violation of freedom of political expression in s.2(b) of the Charter. Ontario then amended the law to include an invocation of s.33. The amended legislation was found to be Charter-compliant in Working Families v Ontario, 2021 ONSC 7697 before being struck down as a violation of the right to vote in s.3 of the Charter by a 2-1 margin in Working Families v Ontario, 2023 ONCA 139.

10. Toronto (City) v Ontario (AG), 2021 SCC 34 upheld the constitutionality of the Province of Ontario reducing the number of Toronto municipal electoral wards and their boundaries in the middle of a municipal election.

11. See Hak c Procureure générale du Québec, 2021 QCCS 1466, where the legislation prohibited some religious minorities from specific positions in the public sector in service of state secularism or laïcité. The legislation was recently upheld by the Quebec Court of Appeal with a decision released on February 29, 2024. See World Sikh Organization of Canada v Attorney General of Quebec, 2024 QCCA 254.

12. See Bill 96, An Act Respecting French, the official and common language of Québec, 2nd Sess, 42nd Leg, Québec, 2021 (assented to 1 June 2022), SQ 2022, c 14.

13. Russell writes “We have much less chance of realizing [the deliberative] democratic ideal, if … we give judges the last word, the ultimate say, on rights issues raised by the Charter. To exclude citizens and their elected legislators from the ultimate determination of these issues is to exclude them from resolving questions of justice which should be at the very heart of political life.” Peter H Russell, “Standing Up for Notwithstanding” (1991) 29:2 Alta L Rev 293 at 300. Dwight Newman maintains: “The presence of the notwithstanding clause is challenging for those adhering to theories in which governments must always be constrained. At their extreme, such theories effectively presume that governments will generally act irresponsibly in respect of rights. The notwithstanding clause, not making such a presumption that would implicitly deny the very idea of democratic governance, precisely calls upon governments to make deliberate, responsible choices.” Dwight Newman, “Canada’s Notwithstanding Clause, Dialogue, and Constitutional Identities” in Geoffrey Sigalet, Grégoire Webber & Rosalind Dixon, eds, Constitutional Dialogue: Rights, Democracy, Institutions (Cambridge University Press, 2019) 209 at 226. Manfredi states that “rights-based judicial review taken to its extreme becomes an anti-democratic power wielded by courts to alter the fundamental character of a nation’s constitution without significant popular participation or even public awareness.” Christopher P Manfredi, “The Day the Dialogue Died: A Comment on Sauvé v Canada” (2007) 45:1 Osgoode Hall LJ 105 at 123. See also Christopher P Manfredi, Judicial Power and the Charter: Canada and the Paradox of Liberal Constitutionalism, 2nd ed (Oxford University Press, 2001); Grant Huscroft, “Rationalizing Judicial Power: The Mischief of Dialogue Theory” in Kelly & Manfredi, supra note 4, 50 at 61.

14. Waldron writes at times specifically of s.33. His general arguments for parliamentary sovereignty and against judicial review can also be extended into the context of s.33. On the substance, in my view, there is little daylight between his general views on parliamentary sovereignty and judicial review on the one hand and his specific ones on s.33 on the other. His most relevant works are: Jeremy Waldron, “The Core of the Case” (2006) 115:6 Yale LJ 1346 [Waldron, “Core of the Case”]; Jeremy Waldron, “A Rights-Based Critique of Constitutional Rights” (1993) 13 Oxford J Leg Stud 18 [Waldron, “Rights-Based Critique”]; Jeremy Waldron, Law and Disagreement (Oxford University Press, 1999); Jeremy Waldron, “Some Models of Dialogue between Judges and Legislators” in Grant Huscroft & Ian Brodie, eds, Constitutionalism in the Charter Era (LexisNexis Butterworths, 2004) 7; Jeremy Waldron, Political Political Theory: Essays on Institutions (Harvard University Press, 2016) [Waldron, Political Political Theory].

15. Huscroft, for example, refers to “the standard objections dialogue theorists raise in opposition to coordinate interpretation—concerns about tyranny of the legislative majority and the inappropriateness of legislatures being judge in their own cause, and so on.” Huscroft, supra note 13 at 57. He then writes: “All of these standard objections have been dispatched by Jeremy Waldron” ( ibid at 64, n 35) and cites Waldron, “Core of the Case”, supra note 14 at 1395-1401.

16. Goldsworthy has the view that some of Waldron’s arguments are inapplicable to the Charter because they are made in the context of systems where rights are beyond legislative override. In my view, given the abstract nature of Waldron’s arguments, this is not a serious impediment to a good-faith application of his views to the Canadian context. See Goldsworthy, supra note 4 at 206.

17. See generally Waldron, supra note 14.

18. See Newman, supra note 13 at 226.

19. Waldron, Law and Disagreement, supra note 14 at 232, quoting William Cobbett as cited in LJ MacFarlane, The Theory and Practice of Human Rights (Temple Smith, 1985) at 142.

20. Section 33 applies to s. 2 (fundamental freedoms), s.7 (life, liberty, and security of the person), rights in the criminal justice system (s.8-14), and equality rights (s.15). Sections 2 and 15 are the most important in relation to political participation. See Charter, supra note 1.

21. On whether s.33 should be invoked pre-emptively or only after invalidation by a court, see Brian Slattery, “A Theory of the Charter” (1987) 25:4 Osgoode Hall LJ 701; Kahana, “Understanding Notwithstanding”, supra note 4 at 224; Paul C Weiler, “Rights and Judges in a Democracy: A New Canadian Version” (1984) 18 U Mich JL Ref 51; Paul C Weiler, “Of Judges and Rights, or Should Canada Have a Constitutional Bill of Rights?” (1980) 60:2 Dal LJ 205; Lorraine Weinrib, “Learning to Live with the Override” (1990) 35 McGill LJ 541; Kent Roach, “Dialogic Judicial Review and its Critics” (2004) 23 SCLR 2d 49 at 61.

22. Section 33(3) imposes a 5-year sunset period. Section 33(4) requires that the declaration be renewed every five years for it to remain in effect. Section 33(5) subjects each subsequent invocation to the 5-year rule. See Charter, supra note 1.

23. Goldsworthy, supra note 4 at 204.

24. See Huscroft, supra note 13 at 57, 64, n 35.

25. See Waldron, Law and Disagreement, supra note 14 at 101.

26. Ibid at 232.

27. See ibid at 243. For a critique of Waldron that argues we should focus on outcomes rather than procedure, see Aileen Kavanagh, “Participation and Judicial Review: A Reply to Jeremy Waldron” (2003) 22:5 Law & Phil 451 at 465-69.

28. Waldron, Law and Disagreement, supra note 14 at 238.

29. Ibid.

30. Ibid .

31. Goldsworthy, supra note 4 at 208.

32. Kavanagh, supra note 27 at 452.

33. Waldron, Law and Disagreement, supra note 14 at 244.

34. Ibid at 248.

35. Ibid at 244.

36. Waldron, “Core of the Case”, supra note 14 at 1353.

37. Kavanagh states: “Waldron argues that a result-driven approach … is unavailable to us, because we disagree about what those results should be. The only alternative, according to Waldron, is an account of political authority based solely on good procedures.” Kavanagh, supra note 27 at 452-53.

38. Waldron’s proceduralism does not guarantee that people’s interests will be equally considered, but merely that they can “participate on equal terms.” Waldron, Law and Disagreement, supra note 14 at 213. He has made some concessions in later work that legislatures may be particularly bad at respecting the rights of some minorities, including those convicted of crimes. See Jeremy Waldron, “‘Who Wants Juristocracy?’ Who Indeed?” in Shelley Griffiths, Mark Henaghan & Ferrere Rodriguez, eds, The Search for Certainty: Essays in honour of John Smillie, (Thomson Reuters, 2016) 1 [Waldron, “Who Wants Juristocracy?”].

39. See Waldron, “Core of the Case”, supra note 14 at 1356-57. He says his choice of categorizing Canada that way is “affected only slightly by the formal availability of the override” ( ibid at 1357). Mark Tushnet has made the related point that weak form judicial review has the tendency to drift into strong form review over time. See Mark Tushnet, “New Forms of Judicial Review and the Persistence of Rights-and Democracy-Based Worries” (2003) 38 Wake Forest L Rev 813.

40. “[T]he real problem is that section 33 requires the legislature to misrepresent its position on rights. To legislate notwithstanding the Charter is a way of saying that you do not think Charter rights have the importance that the Charter says they have.” Waldron, “Core of the Case”, supra note 14 at 1357, n 34.

41. Goldsworthy sets out his and Waldron’s views on this point in Goldsworthy, supra note 4 at 220.

42. See WJ Waluchow, A Common Law Theory of Judicial Review: The Living Tree (Cambridge University Press, 2009); Lorraine Weinrib, “The Canadian Charter’s Transformative Aspirations” (2003) 19:2 SCLR 2d 17. Geoffrey Sigalet argues that s.33 “is meant to enable legislatures to construct rights in disagreement with courts.” Geoffrey Sigalet, “The Truck and the Brakes: Understanding the Charter’s Limitations and Notwithstanding Clauses Symmetrically” (2022) 105 SCLR 2d 187 at 190.

43. Hiebert attributes its lack of use outside of Quebec to public opinion. See Hiebert, supra note 2 at 700.

44. See Waldron, “Rights-Based Critique”, supra note 14 at 46. Like Waldron, Hiebert rejects the notion that we should accord meaning to the majority’s choice not to invoke s.33. “It is well beyond time for a thoughtful discussion of the notwithstanding clause to dismantle the myths that its use signals disregard for the Charter, or that its lack of use implies respect and agreement for judicial norms about the Charter.” Hiebert, supra note 2 at 710.

45. Goldsworthy, supra note 4 at 209.

46. Waldron, “Rights-Based Critique”, supra note 14 at 46. See also Goldsworthy, supra note 4 at 209. Waldron and Goldsworthy differ on this issue. Goldsworthy to his credit rejects Waldron’s argument. If we should respect the judgment of the majority, Goldsworthy says, we should respect their choice not to use s.33 as democratic. “It would be inconsistent for Waldron to base the right to political participation on the capacity of ordinary people for intelligent and conscientious moral deliberation, but then to doubt that capacity when it comes to deliberating about the use of an override clause” ( ibid at 208).

47. Serafin et al. point out that a focus of those who view s.33 “in a largely positive light” is the claim that the notwithstanding clause “preserves the capacity for democratic engagement.” Stéphane Serafin, Kerry Sun, & Xavier Foccroulle Ménard, “Notwithstanding Judicial Specification: The Notwithstanding Clause Within a Juridical Order” (2023) 110 SCLR 2d at 135. Russell also emphasizes deliberation in legislatures; see Russell, supra note 13.

48. See Huscroft, supra note 13 at 57, 64, n 35.

49. “Dialogue theory offers a convenient rationalization—a way of downplaying, if not denying, the very judicial power dialogue proponents prefer. The dialogue metaphor has come in handy for the [Supreme] Court in this regard and may well continue to do so in future. Beyond this, however, dialogue theory has little to offer Canadian constitutional law” ( ibid at 610). Huscroft is addressing here dialogue theory as articulated in Canada. See also Kent Roach, The Supreme Court on Trial: Judicial Activism or Democratic Dialogue (Irwin Law, 2016); Peter W Hogg & Allison A Bushell, “The Charter Dialogue between Courts and Legislatures (Or Perhaps the Charter of Rights Isn’t Such a Bad Thing After All) (1997) 35 Osgoode Hall LJ 75; Peter W Hogg, Allison A Bushell Thornton & Wade K Wright, “Charter Dialogue Revisited—Or ‘Much Ado About Metaphors’” (2007) 45:1 Osgoode Hall LJ 193; Aileen Kavanagh, “A Hard Look at the Last Word” (2015) 35:4 Oxford J Leg Stud 825.

50. Huscroft, supra note 13 at 61.

51. Newman, supra note 13 at 226.

52. Ibid .

53. Ibid at 224.

54. See Goldsworthy, supra note 4, ch 8.

55. Ibid at 224.

56. Ibid at 222 [emphasis added].

57. See Kavanagh, supra note 27 at 475-76.

58. Section IV considers the scope of s.33 in relation to political participation.

59. “No House of Commons and no legislative assembly shall continue for longer than five years from the date fixed for the return of the writs at a general election of its members.” Charter, supra note 1 at s 4(1).

60. On Canada, see Michael Pal, “Breakdowns in the Democratic Process and the Law of Canadian Democracy” (2011) 57:2 McGill LJ 299; Yasmin Dawood, “Electoral Fairness and the Law of Democracy: A Structural Rights Approach to Judicial Review” (2012) 62:4 UTLJ 499. On the U.K., see Jacob Rowbottom, “Political Purposes, Anti-Entrenchment and Judicial Protection of the Democratic Process” (2022) 42:2 Oxford J Leg Stud 383; Jo Eric Khushal Murkens, “Democracy as the Legitimating Condition in the UK Constitution” (2018) 38:1 LS 42.

61. There is a bevy of examples from around the world: see James Gardner, ed, Comparative Election Law (Edward Elgar, 2022); Samuel Issacharoff, Fragile Democracies (Cambridge University Press, 2017).

62. Waldron, “Core of the Case”, supra note 14 at 1360.

63. The other implication arising from Waldron’s assumptions is that where a culture of rights protection does not exist, his argument for majority-rule through the legislature is no longer defensible even on his own theory. See Kyle L Murray, “Philosophy and Constitutional Theory: The Cautionary Tale of Jeremy Waldron and the Philosopher’s Stone” (2019) 32:1 Can JL & Jur 127 at 156, n 172.

64. Some democracies attempt to get around this problem by empowering election commissions in their constitutions and assigning them significant authority that would otherwise rest with the legislature, executive, or courts, such as the power to veto changes to election law proposed by the legislature. See generally Michael Pal, “Electoral Management Bodies as a Fourth Branch of Government” (2016) 21:1 Rev Const Stud 85; Tarunabh Khaitan, “Guarantor Institutions” (2021) 16 (S1) Asian J Comparative L S40; Mark Tushnet, The New Fourth Branch: Institutions for Protecting Constitutional Democracy (Cambridge University Press, 2021), ch 7.

65. Waldron, “Core of the Case”, supra note 14 at 1361. Erin Delaney convincingly argues that Waldron also assumes a unitary rather than a federal state. See Erin Delaney, “The Federal Case for Judicial Review” (2022) 42:3 Oxford J Leg Stud 733.

66. Waldron, “Core of the Case”, supra note 14 at 1361.

67. Ibid .

68. Ibid .

69. Ibid at 1362, n 48.

70. Ibid .

71. Waldron’s triumphalism about a responsible and reformist legislature in New Zealand is in tension with his general insistence that we should not look to results.

72. For example, Carles Boix shows “that electoral systems derive from the decisions the ruling parties make to maximize their representation.” Carles Boix, “Setting the Rules of the Game: The Choice of Electoral Systems in Advanced Democracies” (1999) 93:3 American Political Science Rev 609 at 609. See also Kenneth Benoit, “Models of Electoral System Change” (2004) 23:3 Electoral Studies 363; Alan Renwick, The Politics of Electoral Reform: Changing the Rules of Democracy (Cambridge University Press, 2010).

73. See Kavanagh, supra note 27 at 457.

74. See Leckey & Mendelsohn, supra note 8 at 203-04, n 68.

75. “Instead of adopting a position of hardened cynicism towards the judiciary alone, what is needed is a ‘healthy constitutional scepticism’ spread across all three branches of government.” Aileen Kavanagh, “Recasting the Political Constitution: From Rivals to Relationships” (2019) 30:1 King’s LJ 43 at 72 [footnotes omitted].

76. I side with those who argue that the legal constitutionalism versus political constitutionalism framing is mostly unhelpful, as any functional system needs both elements. “[J]udicial review should not be posed as an alternative to democratic government, but rather (if at all) as one element within that government.” Kavanagh, supra note 27 at 454. This leads to the suspicion that normative accounts of legal and political constitutionalism blur into one another.… There is no pure theory of legal or political constitutionalism.” Alison L Young, “Dialogue and Its Myths: Whatever People Say I Am, That’s What I’m Not” in Sigalet, Webber & Dixon, supra note 13, 35 at 61 [Young, “Dialogue and Its Myths”.] See also Alison L Young, Democratic Dialogue and the Constitution (Oxford University Press, 2017).

77. Young writes that Griffith and TRS Allan (whom Young views as writing in the legal constitutionalist tradition) “both recognize that the legislature and judiciary play a role in protecting rights, although the roles are different.” Young, “Dialogue and its Myths”, supra note 76 at 61.

78. See JAG Griffith, “The Political Constitution” (1979) 42:1 Mod L Rev 1.

79. Thomas Poole, “Tilting at Windmills: Truth and Illusion in the ‘Political Constitution’” (2007) 70 Mod L Rev 250 at 262 [emphasis in original]. Kavanagh reads Griffith the same way: “Griffith’s positive argument was not based on a romantic or idealised view of how representative government works. In fact, Griffith was deeply distrustful of all those in political power and was acutely aware of the authoritarian and elitist tendencies of all governments.” Kavanagh, supra note 75 at 47 [emphasis in original, footnotes omitted].

80. See Hiebert, supra note 2 at 702. She also adds in a fifth potential use of providing a legislature additional time to respond to a suspended declaration of invalidity. As Hiebert points out, Justice Brown suggested as much in Carter v Canada (AG), 2015 SCC 5 (physician-assisted death).

81. Hiebert, supra note 2 at 698.

82. Ford v Quebec, [1988] 2 SCR 712.

83. She distinguishes here between risk aversion in reaction to uncertainty around interpretation of one of the rights or freedoms of the Charter or around how the limitations analysis in s.1 will be interpreted.

84. See Hiebert, supra note 2 at 699. Quebec’s pre-emptive use of s.33 six times in relation to the uncertain constitutionality of pensions, benefits, and the like shows risk aversion in the face of evolving equality rights jurisprudence. For risk aversion in the face of s.1, she cites Quebec’s invocation of s.33 in relation to denominational educational rights on six occasions ( ibid at 700).

85. Ibid at 710.

86. Ibid at 710-11.

87. Waldron, Law and Disagreement, supra note 14 at 417.

88. Kavanagh, supra note 27 at 477.

89. See Herman Bakvis & Steven B Wolinetz, “Canada: Executive Dominance and Presidentialization” in Thomas Poguntke & Paul Webb, eds, The Presidentialization of Politics: A Comparative Study of Modern Democracies (Oxford University Press, 2005) 200; Alex Marland, Whipped: Party Discipline in Canada (UBC Press, 2020); JF Godbout, Lost on Division: Party Unity in the Canadian Parliament (University of Toronto Press, 2020); Peter Aucoin, Mark D Jarvis & Lori Turnbull, Democratizing the Constitution: Reforming Responsible Government (Emond Montgomery, 2011); Donald J Savoie, Democracy in Canada: The Disintegration of our Institutions, (McGill-Queen’s University Press, 2019); Donald J Savoie, Court Government and the Collapse of Accountability in Canada and the United Kingdom (University of Toronto Press, 2008); Donald J Savoie, Governing from the Center: The Concentration of Power in Canadian Politics (University of Toronto Press, 1999).

90. See Adam Tomkins, “What’s Left of the Political Constitution?” (2013) 14:12 German LJ 2275 at 2287. Waldron excepts judicial review of the executive from his argument in Waldron, “Core of the Case”, supra note 14.

91. See Vanessa MacDonnell, “Accounting for a Strong Executive in Constitutional Theory”, Intl J Constitutional L [forthcoming].

92. See Russell, supra note 13 at 298.

93. Ibid at 298, 299.

94. “Legislatures, it is true, may act precipitately and make questionable decisions.… But it is a dreadful distortion to suggest that such impassioned and inconsiderate behaviour is the norm in Canadian legislatures.” Ibid at 301.

95. Léonid Sirota concludes that the level of deliberation in legislatures in contemplating and invoking s.33 is seriously deficient. See Centre for Constitutional Studies, “Legacies of Patriation: Do Legislators Debate Rights When They Make Laws Notwithstanding the Charter?” (27 April 2022) at 00h:21m:30s, online (video): YouTube www.youtube.com/watch?v=cZq3QVJzBvw&t=1290s. See also Robert Leckey, “Legislative Choices in Using Section 33 and Judicial Scrutiny” in Peter L Biro, ed, The Notwithstanding Clause and the Canadian Charter: Rights, Reforms, and Controversies (McGill-Queen’s University Press, 2024) 109.

96. Goldsworthy summarizes the view that judicialisation of politics leads to legislative “apathy and irresponsibility.” Goldsworthy, supra note 4 at 213. See also Waldron, Law and Disagreement, supra note 14 at 254.

97. Mark Tushnet famously argued that judicial review causes the ‘debilitation of democracy’. See Mark Tushnet, “Policy Distortion and Democratic Debilitation: Comparative Illumination of the Countermajoritarian Difficulty” (1995) 84:2 Mich L Rev 245. Sujit Choudhry summarizes Tushnet’s “democratic debilitation” as having two meanings: 1) “dulling the habits of self-government through the removal from the political agenda of the most controversial and important questions of political morality;” and 2) distorting policy by taking choices off the table. Sujit Choudhry, Book Review of Judicial power and the Charter: Canada and the paradox of liberal constitutionalism, 2nd ed, by Christopher P Manfredi (2001) 1:2 Intl J Const L 379 at 382. Manfredi has emphasized the distortion of policy. See Christopher P Manfredi, “Judicial Power and the Charter: Three Myths and a Political Analysis” (2001) 14 SCLR 2d 331 at 335.

98. Echoing one of Tushnet’s two outcomes, Newman writes that “excessive deference to judicial interpretation of rights may well undermine participation in self-government.” Newman, supra note 13 at 225.

99. See James A Gardner, “The Illiberalization of American Election Law: A Study in Democratic Deconsolidation” (2021) 90 Fordham L Rev 423.

100. See Ryan D Doerfler & Samuel Moyn, “The Ghost of John Hart Ely” (2022) 75:3 Vand L Rev 769.

101. Waldron, “Who Wants Juristocracy?”, supra note 38 at 6.

102. See John Hart Ely, Democracy and Distrust: A Theory of Judicial Review (Harvard University Press, 1980); Rosalind Dixon, Democracy and Disfunction (Oxford University Press, 2023).

103. See United States v Carolene Products Co, 304 US 144 at 153 (1938) [Carolene Products].

104. Ibid .

105. Waldron, “Who Wants Juristocracy?”, supra note 38 at 7.

106. Waldron believes that elected representatives are more trustees than delegates—they vote as they see fit for the common good rather than acting as mere mouthpieces for their constituency. See Waldron, Political Political Theory, supra note 14 at 93-144.

107. See Guy Régimbald & Dwight Newman, The Law of the Canadian Constitution, 2d ed (LexisNexis, 2017) at 608.

108. Charter, supra note 1 at s 33(3).

109. See Leckey &Mendelsohn, supra note 8 at 199.

110. The formation of political parties could potentially be seen as covered by s.3 of the Charter, which is outside of the scope of the notwithstanding clause. See Figueroa v Canada (AG), [2003] 1 SCR 912 [Figueroa], which viewed “meaningful participation” by individuals through parties as protected by s.3 ( ibid at 914ff). In my reading, Figueroa, however, does not conclusively resolve whether it is s.3 or s.2 which is invoked in the general regulation of political parties.

111. Leckey & Mendelsohn, supra note 8 at 199.

112. Ibid at 190.

113. Section 33 does not apply to s.6 (mobility rights), official language rights (ss.16-22), minority education rights (s.23), the right against derogation by the Charter from Aboriginal or treaty rights (s.25), multicultural heritage (s.27), and gender equality (s.28).

114. Section 33 is therefore of a more limited scope than s.1 on limitations and s.24 on remedies, each of which on its face applies to all of the rights and freedoms in the Charter. Marion Sandilands and Danielle Bennett conclude that the best theory to explain why some rights are immune from s.33 is one tied to proper recognition of Canada’s federal nature, rather than a “political compromise” or an emphasis on “fundamental rights.” Marion Sandilands & Danielle Bennett, “The Charter’s Federal Spine: Why are Certain Charter Rights Immune from the Notwithstanding Clause?” (2022) 43:2 NJCL 169 at 171.

115. It has been held to protect the right of groups of citizens to cast ballots, including prisoners, non-resident citizens, judges, and those excluded on grounds of mental capacity.

116. See Harvey v New Brunswick (AG), [1996] 2 SCR 876.

117. Figueroa, supra note 110 at 914ff.

118. Reference re Provincial Electoral Boundaries (Saskatchewan), [1991] 2 SCR 158 at 160.

119. Doug Stoltz, “Fixed Date Elections, Parliamentary Dissolutions and the Court” (2010) 33:1 Canadian Parliamentary Rev 15 at 19. The Constitution Act, 1867, s.50 also imposed a five year maximum.

120. “Presumably, the purpose of section 4 is to preserve the democratic character of the House of Commons and legislatures by ensuring that no House of Commons or legislature should last for an excessive period and not reflect the will of the people.” “Charterpedia: Section 4—Maximum duration of legislative bodies” (last modified 31 July 2022), online: Government of Canada www.justice.gc.ca/eng/csj-sjc/rfc-dlc/ccrf-ccdl/check/art4.html.

121. Alberta v Lac La Biche (Town), 1993 ABCA 105 at para 33.

122. “Mindful of this deadline [of 5 years], all governments since Confederation have recommended that the Governor General dissolve Parliament before the date at which such dissolution would have been constitutionally required.” “Expiration of the House of Commons” in Marc Bosc & André Gagnon, eds, House of Commons Procedure and Practice, 3rd ed (House of Commons, 2017) ch 8 at s 7.2.2, online: https://www.ourcommons.ca/procedure/procedure-and-practice-3/ch_08_6-e.html#8-6-2-2

123. See Charter, supra note 1, s 5.

124. See Rosalind Dixon & David E Landau, “Competitive Democracy and the Constitutional Minimum Core” in Tom Ginsburg & Aziz Huq, eds, Assessing Constitutional Performance (Cambridge University Press, 2016) 268; Rosalind Dixon & David E Landau, Abusive Constitutional Borrowing: Legal globalization and the subversion of liberal democracy (Oxford University Press, 2021); David Landau & Rosalind Dixon, “Abusive Judicial Review: Courts Against Democracy” (2020) 53 UC Davis L Rev 1313.

125. For the pre-Charter history, see Elections Canada, A History of the Vote in Canada, 3rd ed (Elections Canada, 2021) 18-124. Sir John A Macdonald is quoted therein from a speech to the Legislative Assembly in 1861: “There is no inalienable right in any man to exercise the franchise” ( ibid at 48).

126. For example, see Alberta (AG) v Canada (AG), [1938] UKPC 46.

127. See Harper v Canada (AG), [2004] 1 SCR 827 at paras 126-27; Libman v Quebec (AG), [1997] 3 SCR 569 at paras 36-27; BC Freedom of Information and Privacy Association v British Columbia (AG), 2017 SCC 6.

128. As recently reaffirmed in Toronto (City) v Ontario (AG), 2021 SCC 34, s.3 does not protect the right to vote in elections other than federal and provincial ones. Municipal elections and elections for First Nations under federal legislation are notably excluded.

129. For an exception that focuses on the rights of the accused, see Kent Roach, “Dialogue or Defiance: Legislative Reversals of Supreme Court Decisions in Canada and the United States” (2006) 4:1 Intl J Const Law 347.