Article contents
Bays, Beaches, and Bioethical Barkings
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 25 March 2011
Extract
From my flat on the eighth floor, I enjoy the panoramic view of the bay and beaches of Montevideo. Except for days of rain and stormy weather—which happen often in these months of winter—the beach is frequented by dogs and their masters and mistresses. I have a passion for dogs, and every morning and afternoon I take short breaks to watch from my window the playfulness of my four-feeted soulmates. They differ in race, color, and size, but from a bird’s-eye view, these differences are negligible, as are the differences in their behavior: they all stop to sniff and deposit their “biological fingerprints” at exactly the same places, they leap and jump around, they move back and forward in different directions, always close to water—a few of them even risk brief visits into the water—and always ahead of their guardians, though not too far away from them. Only occasionally do I observe barking confrontations. Often, however, I see them joined in ceremonial acts aimed at repeatedly outshining each other with regard to “depositional” pace and outreach.
- Type
- Special Section: Methodology in Philosophical Bioethics
- Information
- Copyright
- Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2011
References
1. Häyry, M.Rationality and the Genetic Challenge: Making People Better? Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press; 2010.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
2. See note 1, Häyry 2010:38.
3. See note 1, Häyry 2010:38.
4. See note 1, Häyry 2010:33ff.
5. See note 1, Häyry 2010:18.
6. See note 1, Häyry 2010:32.
7. See note 1, Häyry 2010:18.
8. See note 1, Häyry 2010:33 and 36.
9. See note 1, Häyry 2010:32.
10. As explicitly stated by Häyry himself: ”I do not aim in this book to criticise other ethicists’ views at a normative level” (p. 30).
11. See note 1, Häyry 2010:27.
12. See note 1, Häyry 2010:27.
13. See note 1, Häyry 2010:31.
14. See note 1, Häyry 2010:32.
15. See note 1, Häyry 2010:32.
16. Throughout the book he makes reference to some of them, but no female scholar is attributed with the same level of critical attention and space as are his six male pets.
17. Foucault, M.The History of Sexuality, Volume 1: The Will to Knowledge. London: Penguin; [1976] 1998.Google Scholar
18. Agamben, G. Homo Sacer: Sovereign Power and Bare Life. Heller-Roazen, trans. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press; 1998.Google Scholar
19. Lévinas, E. Otherwise than Being, or, Beyond Essence. Lingis A, trans. London: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers; 1982.Google ScholarLévinas, E. Ethics and Infinity. Cohen, RA, trans. Pittsburgh, PA: Duquesne University Press; 1982.Google Scholar
20. For this approach, see, e.g., London, AJ. Justice and the human development approach to international research. Hastings Center Report 2005;35(1):24–37.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
21. Caplan, A. The Havasu ‘Baaja tribe and informed consent. The Lancet. Epub 2010 Jul 13.Google Scholar
22. See note 1, Häyry 2010:33.
23. See note 1, Häyry 2010:34.
24. See note 1, Häyry 2010:36.
25. Freedman, B. Equipoise and the ethics of clinical research. New England Journal of Medicine 1987;317:141–5 at p. 144.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
26. See note 1, Häyry 2010:37: “The possibility of measuring rationalities can lead to a temptation to compare them and to elevate one of them above the others. I believe that this temptation should be resisted.” See note 1, Häyry 2010:179: “If different approaches (or rationalities or methods of genethics) cannot be universally graded and put into order, as I am saying, then conflicting normative views cannot be put into one rational order, either, and we have no philosophical way of telling once and for all whether we should or should not engage in procreative selection, reproductive or therapeutic cloning, genetic engineering, or considerable life extension.”
- 1
- Cited by