Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-l7hp2 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-26T05:20:44.696Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Vulnerability and Trustworthiness

Polestars of Professionalism in Healthcare

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  09 March 2016

Abstract:

Although recent literature on professionalism in healthcare abounds in recommended character traits, attitudes, or behaviors, with a few exceptions, the recommendations are untethered to any serious consideration of the contours and ethical demands of the healing relationship. This article offers an approach based on the professional’s commitment to trustworthiness in response to the vulnerability of those seeking professional help. Because our willingness and ability to trust health professionals or healthcare institutions are affected by our personality, culture, race, age, prior experiences with illness and healthcare, and socioeconomic and political circumstances—“the social determinants of trust”—the attitudes and behaviors that actually do gain trust are patient and context specific. Therefore, in addition to the commitment to cultivating attitudes and behaviors that embody trustworthiness, professionalism also includes the commitment to actually gaining a patient’s or family’s trust by learning, through individualized dialogue, which conditions would win their justified trust, given their particular history and social situation.

Type
Departments and Columns
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2016 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Notes

1. Hippocrates, The Physician, I. In: Jones WHS, trans. Hippocrates. Vol. II. Loeb Classical Library. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press; 1967, at 311.

2. I am grateful to Mark Wicclair for suggesting the distinction between “patient-based” and “patient-focused” standards for professional behavior.

3. Richard Cruess and Sylvia Cruess provide an historical survey of the uses and connotations of “professionalism” as understood by physicians themselves, and in the literature of medical ethics and the social sciences, in Cruess, RL, Cruess, SR. Teaching medicine as a profession in the service of healing. Academic Medicine 1997;72(11):941–52.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed My interpretation of the predominantly profession-based character of this history draws primarily on the following sources: Edelstein, L. The professional ethics of the Greek physician. Bulletin of the History of Medicine 1956;30:392418Google ScholarPubMed; Starr, P. The Social Transformation of American Medicine. New York: Basic Books; 1982Google Scholar; Berlant, JL. Profession and Monopoly: A Study of Medicine in the United States and Great Britain. Berkeley: University of California Press; 1975Google Scholar; Larson, MS. The Rise of Professionalism: A Sociological Analysis. Berkeley: University of California Press; 1977Google Scholar; Johnson, TJ. Professions and Power. New York: Macmillan; 1972Google Scholar; Gallagher, WT. Ideologies of professionalism and the politics of self-regulation in the California state bar. Pepperdine Law Review 1995;22(2):485628Google Scholar; Goode, WJ. Community within a community: The professions. American Sociological Review 1957;22:194200;CrossRefGoogle Scholar and Pellegrino, ED. Professionalism, profession and the virtues of the good physician. Mount Sinai Journal of Medicine 2002;69(6):378–84.Google ScholarPubMed For a discussion of Percival and his near contemporary, the Edinburgh physician John Gregory, disputing the characterization of medical ethics from this period as predominantly profession based, and arguing that Starr, Berlant, and others have misread Percival as having been simply concerned with “medical etiquette” rather than with “medical ethics” in a more modern sense, see McCullough, L. John Gregory and the Invention of Professional Medical Ethics and the Profession of Medicine. New York: Springer; 1998.Google Scholar For a similar argument concerning Percival, see Pellegrino ED. Percival’s Medical Ethics: The moral philosophy of an 18th-century English gentleman. Archives of Internal Medicine 1986;146(11):2265–9. Scholars have also pointed to strands of thought concerning physicians’ moral responsibilities to patients within the ancient and classical world that articulate something more closely approximating a patient-based approach; see, for example, the tradition exemplified by the first-century author Scribonius Largus, discussed by Edelstein and by Edmund Pellegrino in Pellegrino, ED. Toward a reconstruction of medical morality: The primacy of the act of profession and the fact of illness. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 1979;4(1):3256.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

4. Wear, D, Castellani, B. The development of professionalism: Curriculum matters. Academic Medicine 2000;75(6):602–11, at 603.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

5. Cruess, R, McIlroy, JH, Cruess, S, Ginsburg, S, Steinert, Y. The professionalism mini-evaluation exercise: A preliminary investigation. Academic Medicine 2006;81(10 Suppl):S74S78.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

6. See note 5, Cruess et al. 2006, at S76.

7. Medical Professionalism Project of the American Board of Internal Medicine. Medical professionalism in the new millennium: A physician charter. Annals of Internal Medicine 2002;136(3):243–6.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

8. See note 7, Medical Professionalism Project of the American Board of Internal Medicine 2002, at 244.

9. Levinson, W, Ginsburg, S, Hafferty, FW, Lucey, C. Understanding Medical Professionalism. New York: McGraw Hill; 2014, at 3.Google Scholar

10. Lesser, CS, Lucey, CR, Egener, B, Braddock, CH III, Linas, SL, Levinson, W. A behavioral and systems view of professionalism. JAMA 2010;304(24):2732–7.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

11. See note 9, Levinson et al. 2014, at 3–11.

12. See note 9, Levinson et al. 2014, at 7.

13. See note 10, Lesser et al. 2010, at 2734.

14. See note 9, Levinson et al. 2014, at 7.

15. Additional lists such as these, which seem to have been derived in a similar manner, can be found in Van de Kamp K, Vernouij-Dessen MJFJ, Grol RPTM, Bottema JAM. How to conceptualize professionalism: A qualitative study. Medical Teacher 2004;26(8):696–702; Green, M, Zick, A, Makoul, G. Defining professionalism from the perspective of patients, physicians, and nurses. Academic Medicine 2009;84(5):566–73;CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed Accreditation Council for Graduate Medical Education. Advancing Education in Medical Professionalism: An Educational Resource from the ACGME Outcome Project; 2004; available at http://www.usahealthsystem.com/workfiles/com_docs/gme/2011%20Links/Professionalism%20-%20Faculty%20Dev..pdf (last accessed 29 Apr 2015); and Reynolds PP, Martindale J. Development of the Medical Professionalism Behavior Assessment Tool. Abstract presented at the Annual Conference of the Association for Medical Education in Europe, Milan, Italy, 2014 Aug 30–Sept 3.

16. Goldberg, J. Humanism or professionalism? The white coat ceremony in medical education. Academic Medicine 2008;83:715–22, at 717.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

17. Examples of self-serving compromises that can be masked by appeals to “professionalism” might include lucrative participation in pharmaceutical company speakers bureaus (“colleague education”), refusals to speak publicly about substandard practice on the part of a colleague (“maintaining public confidence”), or resistance to a broadened scope of practice for, e.g., nurse practitioners or physician assistants (“patient safety”).

18. See note 3, Pellegrino 1979, at 44–5.

19. Sokolowski, R. The fiduciary relationship and the nature of professions. In: Pellegrino, ED, Veatch, RM, Langan, JP, eds. Ethics, Trust, and the Professions. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press; 1991:2343, at 27.Google Scholar

20. Welie, JVM. Is dentistry a profession? Part 1. Professionalism defined. Journal of the Canadian Dental Association 2004;70(8):529–32, at 531.Google Scholar

21. Welie, JVM. Is dentistry a profession? Part 2. The hallmarks of professionalism. Journal of the Canadian Dental Association 2004;70(9):599602.Google Scholar An article by Herbert M. Swick that is frequently cited in recent professionalism literature—unlike the writings of Pellegrino, Sokolowski, or Welie, oddly enough—makes similar points, but with much less analysis. See Swick, HM. Toward a normative definition of medical professionalism. Academic Medicine 2000;75(6):612–16.CrossRefGoogle Scholar See also Doukas, DJ. Where is the virtue in professionalism? Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 2003;12:147–54;CrossRefGoogle Scholar note 3, Pellegrino 2002; and, for a deep analysis of professionalism that ranges far beyond medicine, Sullivan, WM. Work and Integrity: The Crisis and Promise of Professionalism in America. 2nd ed.San Francisco: Jossey-Bass; 2005.Google Scholar

22. Rogers, W, Mackenzie, C, Dodds, S. Why bioethics needs a concept of vulnerability. International Journal of Feminist Approaches to Bioethics 2012;5(2):1138, at 12.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

23. Mackenize, C, Rogers, W, Dodds, S, eds. Vulnerability: New Essays in Ethics and Feminist Philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press; 2014, at 1.Google Scholar

24. See note 22, Rogers et al. 2012. See also Spiers, J. New perspectives on vulnerability using emic and etic approaches. Journal of Advanced Nursing 2000;31(3):715–21CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed; Sellman, D. Towards an understanding of nursing as a response to human vulnerability. Nursing Philosophy 2005;6:210;CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed and Hoffmaster, B. What does vulnerability mean? Hastings Center Report 2006;36(2): 3845.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

25. Miller, SC. The Ethics of Need. New York: Routledge; 2012, at 37.Google Scholar

26. See note 25, Miller 2012, at 37.

27. Nussbaum, M. Women and Human Development: The Capabilities Approach. New York: Cambridge University Press; 2000.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

28. See note 25, Miller 2012, at 41–2.

29. Baier, A. Trust and antitrust. Ethics 1986;96:231–60, at 248.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

30. See note 29, Baier 1986, at 235.

31. Katz, J. The Silent World of Doctor and Patient. New York: The Free Press; 1984, especially at 142–50.Google ScholarPubMed

32. See note 31, Katz 1984, at xiv–xv; emphasis added.

33. Kon, A. The shared decision-making continuum. JAMA 2010;304(8):903–4.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

34. Murray, E, Pollack, L, White, M, Lo, B. Clinical decision-making: Patients’ preferences and experiences. Patient Education and Counseling 2007;65:189–96.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

35. Carrese, JA, Rhodes, LA. Bridging cultural differences in medical practice: The case of discussing negative information with Navajo patients. Journal of General Internal Medicine 2000;15:92–6CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Crawley, LM, Marshall, PA, Lo, B, Koenig, BA. Strategies for culturally effective end-of-life care. Archives of Internal Medicine 2002;136(9):673–9Google Scholar; Wallace, MP, Weiner, JS, Pekmezaris, R, Almendrai, A, Cosiquien, R, Auerbach, C, et alPhysician cultural sensitivity in African American advance care planning: A pilot study. Journal of Palliative Medicine 2007;10(3):721–7.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

36. Corbie-Smith, G, Thomas, SB, St. George, DM. Distrust, race, and research. Archives of Internal Medicine 2002;162(21):2458–63CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Braunstein, JB, Sherber, NS, Schulman, SP, Ding, EL, Powe, NR. Race, medical researcher distrust, perceived harm, and willingness to participate in cardiovascular prevention trials. Medicine 2008;87(1):19.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

37. Felitti, V, Anda, RF, Nordenberg, D, Williamson, DF, Spitz, AM, Edwards, V, et alRelationship of childhood abuse and household dysfunction to many of the leading causes of death in adults: The adverse childhood experiences (ACE) study. American Journal of Preventive Medicine 1998;14(4):245–58, at 245.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed See also Corso, P, Edwards, V, Fang, X, Mercy, J. Health-related quality of life among adults who experienced maltreatment during childhood. American Journal of Public Health 2008;98(6):1094–100.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

38. World Health Organization Commission on the Social Determinants of Health. Closing the Gap in a Generation: Health Equity through Action on the Social Determinants of Health. Geneva: World Health Organization; 2008.Google Scholar

39. Rosenberg, L. Addressing trauma in mental health and substance use treatment. Journal of Behavioral Health Services Research 2011;38(4):428–31.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

40. See note 29, Baier 1986, at 258.

41. The structural conditions affecting patients’ or communities’ trust are not the only factors largely outside the individual practitioner’s immediate control. The institutional environment within which the practitioner works—its policies, procedures, and general atmosphere, which can be more or less welcoming or intimidating, agency-enhancing or agency-sapping, for patients and families—is also likely to affect trust. Additional constraints on professional behavior with patients and families with likely influence on the practitioner’s ability to gain their trust come from institutional approaches to practice management, e.g., expectations regarding practitioner workload and patient volume, management surveillance, and pay-for-performance measures. Some of these issues have been discussed under the heading of “organizational professionalism”; see, e.g., Egener, B, McDonald, W, Rosof, B, Gullen, D. Organizational professionalism: Relevant competencies and behaviors. Academic Medicine 2012;87(5):668–74.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

42. Ginsburg, S, Regehr, G, Lingard, L. Basing the evaluation of professionalism on observable behaviors: A cautionary tale. Academic Medicine 2004;79(10 Suppl):S1S4, at S4.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed It is interesting to note that Ginsburg, despite these substantial misgivings, appears two years after the publication of this critique as one of the coauthors of the report on the exclusively behavioral P-MEX discussed previously, as well as the volume elaborating on the BSVOP; see note 5, Cruess et al. 2006, and note 9, Levinson et al. 2014. For another thoughtful critique of the behavioral approach to the evaluation of trainees’ professionalism, see Misch, DA. Evaluating physicians’ professionalism and humanism: The case for humanism “connoisseurs.” Academic Medicine 2002;77(6):489–95.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed I thank Joseph Carrese for calling this article to my attention.

43. See note 22, Rogers et al. 2012, at 23; note 25, Miller 2012, at 94; note 24, Spiers 2000, at 719.

44. Keats J. Ode to a nightingale. In: Stillinger, J, ed. John Keats: Complete Poems. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press; 1978:279–81, at 280.Google Scholar