Article contents
Discontinuing Life Support in an Infant of a Drug-Addicted Mother: Whose Decision Is It?
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 03 August 2009
Extract
“Ethical dilemmas…are rarely simple and stark but are, instead, multifaceted, complex, and gut wrenching for parents and care givers alike.” This is never more the case than when one must treat vulnerable babies who are not, nor ever can be competent to offer us some guidance about that treatment. The ethical problems are heightened when the parents, or the single mother, are incompetent to make decisions themselves, for example, because of drug addiction. In such cases, when the baby is premature and suffering the effects of the drugs the mother has taken, and the mother herself is either no longer available for consultation or so damaged by her own addiction that she is not a reliable decisionmaker, the usual trend In the United States is to initiate treatment and continue until it is virtually certain that the infant will die.
- Type
- Special Section: The Unborn and the Newly Born: Seeking Ethical Standards
- Information
- Copyright
- Copyright © Cambridge University Press 1997
References
Notes
1. Stahlman, MT. Ethical issues in the nursery: priorities versus limits. Journal of Pediatrics 1990;116:167–70.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
2. Ryan, CA, Byrne, P, Kuhn, S et al. , No resuscitation and withdrawal of therapy in a neonatal and a pediatric intensive care unit in Canada. Journal of Pediatrics 1993;124:534–8.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
3. Clark, FI. Intensive care treatment decision: the roots of our confusion. Pediatrics 1994;94:98–101.Google ScholarPubMed
4. Walters, JW. Approaches to ethical decision making in the neonatal intensive care unit. American Journal of Diseases of Children 1988; 142:825–30.Google ScholarPubMed
5. Smedira, NG, Evans, BH, Grais, LS et al. , Withholding and withdrawal of life support from the critically ill. NEJM 1990;322:309–15.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
6. Facing tragic decisions with parents in the neonatal intensive care unit. Clinical Perspectives in Pediatrics 1992;89:119–22.Google Scholar
7. Silverman, WA. Overtreatment of neonates? a personal retrospective. Pediatrics 1992;90:971–6.Google ScholarPubMed
8. Sinclair, JC, Torrance, GW. From probability to preference. In: Goldworth, A, Silverman, W, Stevenson, DK et al. , eds. Ethics and Perinatology. New York: Oxford University Press, 1995:120–45.Google Scholar
9. Thomasma, DC. Abstract medical knowledge, newborns, and uncertainty: a challenge to philosophy of medicine. In: Goldworth, et al. 1995:146–62. See note 8.Google Scholar
10. Muraskas, J, Marshall, PA, Gianopolous, JG et al. , Neonatal viability in the 1990's: held hostage by technology, 02. 23, 1996. Submitted to Journal of Perinatology.Google Scholar
11. However, that commitment is not always possible, especially in light of media attention. See our analysis of the Lakeberg case: Thomasma, DC, Muraskas, J, Marshall, PA et al. , What we learned from the Lakeberg twins. Hastings Center Report 1996;26, forthcoming.Google Scholar
12. Thomasma, DC, Kushner, T. A dialogue on compassion and supererogation in medicine. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 1995;4(4):415–25.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
13. Thomasma, DC. Human Life in the Balance. Louisville, Ky.: Westminster Press, 1990.Google Scholar
14. Johnson, PE, The ACLU philosophy and right to abuse the unborn. Criminal Justice Ethics 1990;9(1):48–51.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
15. Swenson, VJ, Crabbe, C. Pregnant substance abusers: a problem that won't go away. St. Mary's Law Journal 1994;25:623–73.Google Scholar
16. American Medical Association, Report of the Board of Trustees. Treatment Versus Criminalization: Physician Role in Drug Addiction During Pregnancy. Resolution 131. Chicago: American Medical Association, 1990.Google Scholar
17. Campbell, AGM, McHaffie, HE. Prolonging life and allowing death: infants. Journal of Medical Ethics 1995;21(6):339–44.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
- 2
- Cited by