Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-t7fkt Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-21T17:57:57.277Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Ethical frameworks of informed consent in the age of pediatric precision medicine

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 May 2024

David Chen*
Affiliation:
Temerty Faculty of Medicine, University of Toronto, Toronto, ON, Canada Department of Medical Oncology, Dana Farber Cancer Institute, Boston, MA, USA
*
Corresponding author: David Chen; Email: [email protected]
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Precision medicine is an emergent medical paradigm that uses information technology to inform the use of targeted therapies and treatments. One of the first steps of precision medicine involves acquiring the patient’s informed consent to protect their rights to autonomous medical decision-making. In pediatrics, there exists mixed recommendations and guidelines of consent-related practices designed to safeguard pediatric patient interests while protecting their autonomy. Here, we provide a high-level, clinical primer of (1) ethical informed consent frameworks widely used in clinical practice and (2) promising modern adaptations to improve informed consent practices in pediatric precision medicine. Given the rapid scientific advances and adoption of precision medicine, we highlight the dual need to both consider the clinical implementation of consent in pediatric precision medicine workflows as well as build rapport with pediatric patients and their substitute decision-makers working alongside interdisciplinary health teams.

Topics structure

Type
Perspective
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press

Impact statement

Precision medicine holds great promise to personalize medical therapies and treatments for each patient in order to improve clinical outcomes of disease. However, there remains hesitation among patients who may be unfamiliar with this promising technology. To engage pediatric patient participation in the use of clinical precision medicine, receiving patient consent is required. Given the variance in consent models in pediatric medicine due to regional contexts with no standardized international guidelines, we provide a clinical primer of existing informed consent workflows and promising modern adaptations to informed consent in pediatric precision medicine. This article serves as a call to action for renewed discussion toward standardized frameworks for informed consent in pediatric patient populations.

Introduction

Precision medicine is defined as a personalized medical approach to prevent, diagnose and treat disease using information from an individual’s genome, environment and lifestyle habits (Ginsburg and Phillips, Reference Ginsburg and Phillips2018). The provision of informed consent in precision medicine demands that the patient, or in some cases their substitute decision-maker for patients without the capacity to consent, is well-informed of the treatment options and can competently assess the treatment options to authorize an optimal decision for the patient (Oberg et al., Reference Oberg, Glade Bender, Cohn, Morris, Ruiz, Chung, Appelbaum, Kung and Levine2015).

The challenge of informed consent arises in pediatric care, where the authority for consent to make decisions in care should be considered alongside objective factors such as age and subjective factors such as the maturity of the patient, which must be determined on a case-by-case basis. Moreover, substitute decision-makers may not always make the best healthcare decisions for their child due to lack of health literacy; therefore, clinicians also play a role in protecting the child’s health from poor medical decision-making. In this perspectives article, we aim to outline modern ethical considerations and frameworks of consent-related practices in pediatric clinical precision medicine and relevant research applications.

Informed consent frameworks

Decision-making in pediatric precision medicine is a balance of priorities between respecting the pediatric patient’s self-determination and making the most optimal decisions to improve care from the healthcare provider and surrogate decision-maker perspectives. Informed consent is defined as the voluntary, autonomous authorization of medical intervention by a patient with the capacity to understand and appreciate disclosed information relevant to the intervention (Del Carmen and Joffe, Reference Del Carmen and Joffe2005). The clinical workflow of precision medicine starts with requesting informed consent from the pediatric patient or their substitute decision-makers when appropriate. Substitute decision-makers are individuals, such as parents, guardians, family members and individuals with power of attorney in pediatric medicine, with legal power to authorize healthcare-related decisions on another’s behalf if they cannot make the decisions for themselves, such as in the case of minors without knowledge and emotional understanding of the proposed intervention (Sellars et al., Reference Sellars, Tran, Nolte, White, Sinclair, Fetherstonhaugh and Detering2021). Decision-makers providing consent to precision medicine must assess the value of genetic screening while considering the current severity of the patient’s disease, the onset of future symptoms and the efficacy of follow-up treatment that follows from screening.

Age-based informed consent models have traditionally separated pediatric patients into two or more cohorts stratified by age, where patients below a pre-specified age threshold require joint consent to treatment from their surrogate decision-maker or assent to participate in the care plan, and patients above the threshold can provide informed consent independently (Coughlin, Reference Coughlin2018). Beyond using age as a threshold measure of capacity to consent, the interplay between subjective factors such as patient maturity and previous ability to make medical decisions based on absolute risk should also be considered along with objective factors such as patient age to determine the patient’s holistic capacity to give informed consent for genetic testing (Salibian et al., Reference Salibian, Frey, Choi and Karp2018).

In the case of children incapable of providing informed consent, a common normative standard used to guide substitute decision-making is the best interests principle, where decisions are informed by the patient’s best interests (Hall et al., Reference Hall, Chowdhury, Pashayan, Hallowell, Pharoah and Burton2014). The best interests standard for informed consent has been challenged by proponents for an alternative framework that supposes parents have an ethical right to guide medical decisions for their children, even if they do not maximize their child’s well-being. Known as the zone of parental discretion, this ethical approach applies when parents may disagree with physicians over the recommendation for treatment and refuse to provide consent, so long as the child is not significantly harmed (Gillam, Reference Gillam2016).

Alternative frameworks of informed consent have focused on allowing parents to choose from reasonable options within an acceptable harm threshold or replacing substitute decision-making with supportive decision-making that establishes the patients as the primary decision-maker regardless of mental capacity (Diekema, Reference Diekema2004).

Pediatric patients who are not capable of consenting on their own behalf should provide assent, which allows for increased participation from pediatric participants with developing capacity to agree to proposed care. Assent is defined as the interactive process involving the disclosure of cognitively and emotionally appropriate information to the minor about the medical intervention and the voluntary agreement to choose to participate in the intervention free of undue influence (Tait and Geisser, Reference Tait and Geisser2017).

Assent empowers children to participate in the sharing decision-making process based on their developmental maturity and provides an opportunity for them to consider all of their options. To do so, children must be able to understand the details, benefits and risks of the procedure being performed, voluntarily decide to undergo the procedure, and communicate this choice (Rossi et al., Reference Rossi, Reynolds and Nelson2003). In shared decision-making frameworks involving pediatric assent, several ethical problems and burdens remain that require further research.

First, the age by which children should provide assent depends on a case-by-case evaluation of the patient’s developmental maturity, but previous research studies have required assent from patients ranging from 6 years old (Nunes et al., Reference Nunes, Ribeiro, Niewiadonski, Sabino, Yamamoto, Bertola, Gaburo and da Silva Filho2017), 12 years old (Hein et al., Reference Hein, De Vries, Troost, Meynen, Van Goudoever and Lindauer2015) and up to the age of majority based on regional legal guidelines (Coughlin, Reference Coughlin2018). The age of medical consent varies based on local contexts; for instance, the age of medical consent is 16 years in Spain and Scotland, 18 years in Italy and France, assessed based on maturity until the age of majority in the United Kingdom and assessed based on maturity even beyond the age of majority at 18 years in Finland and Sweden (Bolcato et al., Reference Bolcato, Franzetti, Fassina, Basile, Martinez and Tronconi2024). In Canada, provincial laws do not stipulate age of consent for treatment but generally deem minors (ranging from 14 to 16 years of age based on province) to have the capacity to make healthcare decisions (Coughlin, Reference Coughlin2018).

Using age as an indicator for patient capacity has previously been challenged by opponents who suggest that pediatric patients with more early lived experiences in healthcare, such as in the case of chronic disease, may have a more mature mindset when evaluating healthcare treatment options (Miller, Reference Miller2018). Second, there remains the need for education of both clinicians about the utility and application of assent as well as of patients and their substituted decision-makers about shared decision-making. Clinicians may have limited explicit knowledge of the concept of assent for medical treatment (Lee et al., Reference Lee, Havens, Sato, Hoffman and Leuthner2006), motivating the need for continuing clinical education about ethical concepts to remain up-to-date about modern consent practices. For patients, age-appropriate models may be needed to help minors and their substitute decision-makers understand the concept of assent and their roles in the process (Weisleder, Reference Weisleder2020). Maximizing the relevant, lay information necessary to understand the risk–benefit profiles of planned medical procedures coupled with novel communication mediums (Koonrungsesomboon et al., Reference Koonrungsesomboon, Charoenkwan, Natesirinilkul, Fanhchaksai, Sakuludomkan and Morakote2022), such as using age-appropriate multimedia assent documents (Wongthai et al., Reference Wongthai, Photia, Traivaree, Monsereenusorn, Lertvivatpong, Sudnawa and Rujkijyanont2022), are one step toward addressing this need for patient education. Third, there can exist exceptional scenarios where seeking assent from children with developing capacity may be overridden if there exists a significant benefit to the child and their wellbeing would be jeopardized otherwise (Moran et al., Reference Moran, Thornburg and Barfield2011). However, we note that critiques of assent due to its heterogeneous conceptual definition may lead to the potential for harm to specific groups, such as when a minor’s dissent is ignored due to parental insistence for treatment (Wongthai et al., Reference Wongthai, Photia, Traivaree, Monsereenusorn, Lertvivatpong, Sudnawa and Rujkijyanont2022). Loco-regional definitions of assent procedures should be consistently applied whenever possible in consultation with interdisciplinary care teams to standardize norms for assent.

Given that patient participation in precision medicine can be associated with their voluntary enrollment in related clinical trials, oversight of clinical studies by local ethics review boards remains a necessary stakeholder in the supervision of precision medicine research. The ethics review board is in the position to define the components of the informed consent processes and should ensure that such processes can be readily understood by a lay audience, such as minors and their substitute decision-makers (Matrana and Campbell, Reference Matrana and Campbell2020). In addition, review boards play an integral role in the long-term oversight of precision medicine trial-related data governance and privacy, as defined in the terms of consent (Chen, Reference Chen2020). Taken together, ethics review boards also play an emergent role in precision medicine due to the marked overlap between medical therapy and clinical research studies in precision medicine.

Modern adaptations to improve informed consent practices

Modern consent workflows have recently been proposed to address the practical challenges to informed consent due to the unclear expectations of the benefits of precision medicine, the change in development capacity when patients reach the age of majority, and the overwhelming demands from repeated consent requests. First, having a two-step consent process where consent to genetic screening occurs one to two months following the initial consent for a diagnostic biopsy may increase the ability for parents of children to provide meaningful informed consent (Oberg et al., Reference Oberg, Glade Bender, Cohn, Morris, Ruiz, Chung, Appelbaum, Kung and Levine2015). This two-step approach gives parents and children time and space to fully process the implications of genetic screening. Second, providing options for pediatric patients to exercise their right to re-consent for continued use of genomic data at the age of majority aligns with the patient’s right to autonomy when full informed decision-making capacity has developed (Edwards et al., Reference Edwards, Korngiebel, Pfeifer, Goodman, Renz, Wenzel, Bowen and Condit2016). Third, broad consent has previously been proposed as one way for pediatric patients and their parents to provide a one-time informed consent for the reuse of genomic data and/or health information in future research as deemed appropriate by a regulatory oversight body (Smith et al., Reference Smith, Sanderson, Brothers, Myers, McCormick, Aufox, Shrubsole, Garrison, Mercaldo, Schildcrout and Clayton2016). When the mature child and parents are ready to make a decision about genetic testing for adult-onset conditions, factors such as the disease, the stage of development of the child, family dynamics and values should be considered. The conceptual development of dynamic consent frameworks in precision medicine to support both specific and broad, blanket consent is one step toward personalizing consent processes to the unique preferences of minors and their substitute decision-makers (Goncharov et al., Reference Goncharov, Suominen and Cook2022).

The age-appropriate information provided to pediatric patients and their legal representatives should, at a minimum, explain the purpose of the proposed precision medicine approach, who will have access to the genomic data, and provide clear written forms for providing informed consent (Naito et al., Reference Naito, Aburatani, Amano, Baba, Furukawa, Hayashida, Hiyama, Ikeda, Kanai, Kato and Kinoshita2021). Genetic counseling should be provided to both the substitute decision-maker and the child about primary, clinically actionable findings and the potential for incidental findings with unknown impact to protect the patient’s right to know and not know (Naito et al., Reference Naito, Aburatani, Amano, Baba, Furukawa, Hayashida, Hiyama, Ikeda, Kanai, Kato and Kinoshita2021). We highlight the distinction between genomic testing for evidence-based, clinically actionable findings with proven therapeutic implications compared to incidental findings, such as variants of unknown significance identified in exploratory, whole genome-scale research. Incidental findings remain commonplace in precision medicine fields such as clinical genomics, with an ongoing debate about the duty to report incidental findings based on perceived risks of disease threat (AlFayyad et al., Reference AlFayyad, Al-Tannir, Abu-Shaheen and AlGhamdi2021). Incidental findings may harbor unexpected results that require further high clinical suspicion for their relevance and applicability to clinical treatment, given their potential to cause patient anxiety over lack of actionability. To do so, engagement in genetic counseling, verification of results with the molecular genetics laboratory, and exploring patient perspectives over their right to know and not know remain ethical priorities (Maani et al., Reference Maani, Panabaker, JM, Buckley, Semotiuk, Farncombe, Ainsworth, Panchal, Sadikovic, Armel and Lin2021). Despite the need for genetic counselors to navigate the complex medical and ethical considerations of pediatric precision medicine, there remains a shortage of genetic counselors and related clinicians necessary to meet the demands for precision medicine testing (Dragojlovic et al., Reference Dragojlovic, Borle, Kopac, Ellis, Birch, Adam, Friedman, Nisselle, Elliott and Lynd2020). Revisions aimed at developing more efficient contemporary genetic service models, including education to improve the competency of healthcare learners and providers in precision medicine-related tasks (Chen and Gorla, Reference Chen and Gorla2023), such as risk assessments and taking family histories, as well as automation of tasks through tools such as electronic decision aids and artificial intelligence, remain an ongoing area of research (Dragojlovic et al., Reference Dragojlovic, Borle, Kopac, Ellis, Birch, Adam, Friedman, Nisselle, Elliott and Lynd2020).

Notably, a review of patient perspectives related to ethical issues in precision medicine by Ahmed et al. (Reference Ahmed, Constantinidou and Chatzittofis2023) identified several emergent themes, including data governance, patient costs, risks for discrimination, issues with the diagnostic accuracy and psychosocial implications of the findings. Future research is needed to evaluate how these ethical issues can be addressed in part through revised informed consent processes, with a particular emphasis on the need to consider pediatric patients as a growing patient population involved in precision medicine. Upon reviewing the contemporary literature on ethics in consent-related practices of pediatric precision medicine, we synthesized a list of themes that can be included as topics of discussion at the time of consent in Table 1.

Table 1. Discussion themes during pediatric precision medicine consent

Conclusion

Taken together, the development of a meaningful consent process should be individualized to local contexts while seeking input from ethics review boards to ensure that legal and ethical boundaries are respected among healthcare providers, substitute decision-makers, and pediatric patients. Recent advances in consent frameworks derived from the traditional age-based consent model have proposed assessing pediatric patient’s development maturity and lived experiences in healthcare decision-making when deciding who, between the patient and their substitute decision-maker, should provide informed consent. When the substitute decision-maker is providing informed consent on behalf of a pediatric patient with developing maturity, ethical standards such as the best interests standard, harm threshold, and pediatric assent can help guide a principled, informed consent process.

Due to the complexity of pediatric precision medicine, providing ample space and counseling to make informed decisions with consideration of future medical, social and ethical implications can build rapport with patients. As the prevalence of pediatric precision medicine grows, we must develop modern ethical frameworks of informed consent involving patients, substitute decision-makers, healthcare providers and genetic counselors as part of an interdisciplinary team that collectively acts to improve the pediatric patient’s decision-making process while respecting their autonomy.

Open peer review

To view the open peer review materials for this article, please visit http://doi.org/10.1017/pcm.2024.3.

Author contribution

D.C. was involved in study conceptualization, investigation and writing.

Competing interest

The author declares none.

References

Ahmed, L, Constantinidou, A and Chatzittofis, A (2023) Patients’ perspectives related to ethical issues and risks in precision medicine: A systematic review. Frontiers in Medicine 10, 1215663.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
AlFayyad, I, Al-Tannir, M, Abu-Shaheen, A and AlGhamdi, S (2021) To disclose, or not to disclose? Perspectives of clinical genomics professionals toward returning incidental findings from genomic research. BMC Medical Ethics 22, 18.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bolcato, V, Franzetti, C, Fassina, G, Basile, G, Martinez, RM and Tronconi, LP (2024) Comparative study on informed consent regulation in health care among Italy, France, United Kingdom, Nordic countries, Germany, and Spain. Journal of Forensic and Legal Medicine 14, 102674.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chen, D (2020) Open data: Implications on privacy in healthcare research. Blockchain in Healthcare Today 3.Google ScholarPubMed
Chen, D and Gorla, J (2023) The need to develop digital health competencies for medical learners. Medical Teacher 45(7), 790791.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Coughlin, KW (2018) Medical decision-making in paediatrics: Infancy to adolescence. Paediatrics & Child Health 23(2), 138146.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Del Carmen, MG and Joffe, S (2005) Informed consent for medical treatment and research: A review. The Oncologist 10(8), 636641.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Diekema, D (2004) Parental refusals of medical treatment: The harm principle as threshold for state intervention. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 25, 243264.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Dragojlovic, N, Borle, K, Kopac, N, Ellis, U, Birch, P, Adam, S, Friedman, JM, Nisselle, A, Study G, Elliott, AM and Lynd, LD (2020) The composition and capacity of the clinical genetics workforce in high-income countries: A scoping review. Genetics in Medicine 22(9), 14371449.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Edwards, KL, Korngiebel, DM, Pfeifer, L, Goodman, D, Renz, A, Wenzel, L, Bowen, DJ and Condit, CM (2016) Participant views on consent in cancer genetics research: Preparing for the precision medicine era. Journal of Community Genetics 7, 133143.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gillam, L (2016) The zone of parental discretion: An ethical tool for dealing with disagreement between parents and doctors about medical treatment for a child. Clinical Ethics 11(1), 18.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ginsburg, GS and Phillips, KA (2018) Precision medicine: From science to value. Health Affairs 37(5), 694701.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Goncharov, L, Suominen, H and Cook, M (2022) Dynamic consent and personalised medicine. The Medical Journal of Australia 216(11), 547.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hall, AE, Chowdhury, S, Pashayan, N, Hallowell, N, Pharoah, P and Burton, H (2014) What ethical and legal principles should guide the genotyping of children as part of a personalised screening programme for common cancer?. Journal of Medical Ethics 40(3), 163167.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hein, IM, De Vries, MC, Troost, PW, Meynen, G, Van Goudoever, JB and Lindauer, RJ (2015) Informed consent instead of assent is appropriate in children from the age of twelve: Policy implications of new findings on children’s competence to consent to clinical research. BMC Medical Ethics 16, 17.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Koonrungsesomboon, N, Charoenkwan, P, Natesirinilkul, R, Fanhchaksai, K, Sakuludomkan, W and Morakote, N (2022) What information and the extent of information to be provided in an informed assent/consent form of pediatric drug trials. BMC Medical Ethics 23(1), 113.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lee, KJ, Havens, PL, Sato, TT, Hoffman, GM and Leuthner, SR (2006) Assent for treatment: Clinician knowledge, attitudes, and practice. Pediatrics 118(2), 723730.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Maani, N, Panabaker, K, JM, McCuaig, Buckley, K, Semotiuk, K, Farncombe, KM, Ainsworth, P, Panchal, S, Sadikovic, B, Armel, SR and Lin, H (2021) Incidental findings from cancer next generation sequencing panels. NPJ Genomic Medicine 6(1), 63.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Matrana, MR and Campbell, B (2020) Precision medicine and the institutional review board: Ethics and the genome. Ochsner Journal 20(1), 98103.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Miller, VA (2018) Involving youth with a chronic illness in decision-making: Highlighting the role of providers. Pediatrics 142(Supplement_3), S142S148.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Moran, C, Thornburg, CD and Barfield, RC (2011) Ethical considerations for pharmacogenomic testing in pediatric clinical care and research. Pharmacogenomics 12(6), 889895.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Naito, Y, Aburatani, H, Amano, T, Baba, E, Furukawa, T, Hayashida, T, Hiyama, E, Ikeda, S, Kanai, M, Kato, M and Kinoshita, I (2021) Clinical practice guidance for next-generation sequencing in cancer diagnosis and treatment (edition 2.1). International Journal of Clinical Oncology 26, 233283.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Nunes, LM, Ribeiro, R, Niewiadonski, VD, Sabino, E, Yamamoto, GL, Bertola, DR, Gaburo, N and da Silva Filho, LV (2017) A new insight into CFTR allele frequency in Brazil through next generation sequencing. Pediatric Pulmonology 52(10):13001305.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Oberg, JA, Glade Bender, JL, Cohn, EG, Morris, M, Ruiz, J, Chung, WK, Appelbaum, PS, Kung, AL and Levine, JM (2015) Overcoming challenges to meaningful informed consent for whole genome sequencing in pediatric cancer research. Pediatric Blood & Cancer 62(8), 13741380.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Rossi, WC, Reynolds, W and Nelson, RM (2003) Child assent and parental permission in pediatric research. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 24, 131148.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Salibian, AA, Frey, JD, Choi, M and Karp, NS (2018) BRCA mutations in the young, high-risk female population: Genetic testing, management of prophylactic therapies, and implications for plastic surgeons. Plastic and Reconstructive Surgery 141(6), 13411350.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sellars, M, Tran, J, Nolte, L, White, B, Sinclair, C, Fetherstonhaugh, D and Detering, K (2021) Public knowledge, preferences and experiences about medical substitute decision-making: A national cross-sectional survey. BMJ Supportive & Palliative Care 14, e893e902.Google Scholar
Smith, ME, Sanderson, SC, Brothers, KB, Myers, MF, McCormick, J, Aufox, S, Shrubsole, MJ, Garrison, NA, Mercaldo, ND, Schildcrout, JS and Clayton, EW (2016) Conducting a large, multi-site survey about patients’ views on broad consent: Challenges and solutions. BMC Medical Research Methodology 16, 162.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Tait, AR and Geisser, ME (2017) Development of a consensus operational definition of child assent for research. BMC Medical Ethics 18, 18.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Weisleder, P (2020) Helping them decide: A scoping review of interventions used to help minors understand the concept and process of assent. Frontiers in Pediatrics 8, 25.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wongthai, P, Photia, A, Traivaree, C, Monsereenusorn, C, Lertvivatpong, N, Sudnawa, KK and Rujkijyanont, P (2022) Improving comprehension, recall and attention using multimedia‐informed assent among pediatric oncology patients: A comparative randomized controlled trial. Pediatric Blood & Cancer 69(8), e29785.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Figure 0

Table 1. Discussion themes during pediatric precision medicine consent

Author comment: Ethical frameworks of informed consent in the age of pediatric precision medicine — R0/PR1

Comments

December 20, 2023

Editor-in-Chief

Dr. Dame Anna Dominiczak

Dear Dr. Dominiczak,

We kindly request that you consider our article “Ethical Frameworks of Informed Consent in the Age of Pediatric Precision Medicine” for publication in Cambridge Prisms: Precision Medicine as a Perspectives Article.

Precision medicine holds great promise to inform personalized medical approaches designed to diagnose, manage, and treat patients based on a patient’s omics profile, environment, and lifestyle habits. The first step in the clinical precision medicine workflow is to acquire informed consent from a patient to initiate a treatment intervention in accord with principles of autonomous decision-making. The ethical dilemma arises in pediatric precision medicine, where the applicability, utility, and acceptability of diverse ethical frameworks of informed consent varies based on sociocultural, legal, and institutional contexts.

Given the heterogeneity in context-specific informed consent frameworks and practices in pediatric precision medicine, this Perspectives article aims to outline emergent ethical considerations and modern frameworks of consent-related practices to motivate future directions for pediatric consent-related ethics research. To achieve this aim, we provide an overview of 1) ethical informed consent frameworks widely used in clinical practice and 2) promising modern adaptations to improve informed consent practices. In parallel with modern advances in precision medicine research and clinical applications, we uniquely highlight the dual need to consider the clinical implementation of consent in pediatric precision medicine workflows and build rapport with pediatric patients and their substitute decision-makers as part of an interdisciplinary health team.

Our article comprises original content that has not been published previously and is not under consideration elsewhere. The work was undertaken by the authors with no writing assistance. The authors have no conflicts of interest, and the review does not convey a perception of financial bias.

Please do not hesitate to contact us if you have any questions.

Sincerely,

David Chen

Temerty Faculty of Medicine, University of Toronto, Toronto, Ontario, Canada

Dana Farber Cancer Institute, Boston, Massachusetts, USA

Tel: 1-416-803-0124

Email: [email protected]

Recommendation: Ethical frameworks of informed consent in the age of pediatric precision medicine — R0/PR2

Comments

Please specifically address the comments of Reviewers 2 and 3 only. On this occasion and with agreement of the Publisher I include Reviewer 1’s comments for full and transparent records for all, but as handling editor advise response to comments are not required.

Decision: Ethical frameworks of informed consent in the age of pediatric precision medicine — R0/PR3

Comments

No accompanying comment.

Author comment: Ethical frameworks of informed consent in the age of pediatric precision medicine — R1/PR4

Comments

No accompanying comment.

Recommendation: Ethical frameworks of informed consent in the age of pediatric precision medicine — R1/PR5

Comments

No accompanying comment.

Decision: Ethical frameworks of informed consent in the age of pediatric precision medicine — R1/PR6

Comments

No accompanying comment.