Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-vdxz6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-20T11:33:54.415Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Music and mathematics: Theophrastus against the number-theorists

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 February 2013

Andrew Barker
Affiliation:
Selwyn College, Cambridge

Extract

A long and important fragment of the Περὶ μοψσικῆς of Theophrastus is preserved in Porphyry's commentary on Ptolemy's Harmonics. Both Porphyry and Ptolemy were reedited earlier in this century by Düring, in works which have rightly been taken to supersede the texts of Wallis: and so far as the Theophrastus passage is concerned, we should expect to be able to abandon in Düring's favour the text published by Wimmer, who in effect reprints Wallis, though adopting a few variant readings and emendations from Schneider. But it seems to me that Düring's text is not in all respects an improvement, and that the comments made on it in a subsequent publication by Alexanderson have muddied the waters still further. It is not only a matter of the text: Alexanderson prints also a (partial) translation and an interpretative commentary, and both are open to serious objections. I intend in this paper to deal only with a portion of the fragment, but it is that portion whose argument is the most intricate, and one which ought to shed a good deal of light on central controversies among the musical theoreticians who follow Aristotle. I am not in a position to dispute any of Düring's findings in the manuscripts, but where emendation has in any event proved necessary or where the manuscripts differ among themselves, I hope to show through a study of the content of the argument that the case in favour of Düring is not always closed.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s). Published online by Cambridge University Press 1977

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

NOTES

1. Porphyrios' Kommentar zur Harmonielehre des Ptolemaios, ed. Düring, I., Göteborg 1932Google Scholar.

2. Die Harmonielehre des Klaudios Ptolemaios, ed. Düring, I., Göteborg 1930Google Scholar.

3. Operum Mathematicorum vol. 3, Oxford 1699Google Scholar.

4. Theophrasti Eresii Opera, ed. Wimmer, F., Leipzig 1862, frag. LXXXIXGoogle Scholar.

5. Theophrasti Eresii quae supersunt opera, ed. Schneider, J. G., Leipzig 1821Google Scholar.

6. Textual remarks on Ptolemy's Harmonica and Porphyry's Commentary, Göteborg 1969Google Scholar.

7. The most complete example which remains of a work designed on the basis of the theory here attacked is of course the Euclidean Sectio Canonis. Ptolemy and Porphyry both refer us to the earlier work of Archytas. It appears from their remarks that whereas his predecessors among the Pythagoreans had restricted themselves to the discovery of ratios involved in concords, Archytas sought . See the passages quoted at Diels, / Kranz, , Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker (1952 and later editions) 47Google Scholar, A16 and A17.

8. In Aristoxenus the term may sometimes be construed as referring to other musical theorists quite generally (perhaps El. Harm. 2, 5): but more commonly it is used, as by Theophrastus here, to pick out a particular school. Their reliance on is implied (e.g. 40) though not emphasised by Aristoxenus – he is after all more concerned to attack those who rely on things other than . His criticisms of them seem to turn largely on their ignorance of, and failure to seek, any principles governing the nature of : they are ‘mere’ empiricists, seeking to distinguish intervals accurately, to develop an accurate notation to represent them, and to tabulate their sequences in the simplest schematic ways – ways which, according to Aristoxenus, wholly ignore their specifically musical interrelations. They are presumably close relatives of the of Republic 531 a-b, where the description of them as may be seen as providing a link with the procedure of which Aristoxenus characteristically associates with the . See El. Harm. 2, 5, 7, 28, 37, 40.

9. It has been pointed out to me that in fr. 1, lines 37ff and 76 (Wimmer), Theophrastus seems to use the two words interchangeably. This obviously weakens my case, but I do not think that it destroys it.

10. The notion of a ‘shade’ may require a little explanation. Within the scale, as understood by writers of this period, certain notes are ‘fixed’ – i.e. stand always at the same intervals from one another. Others are not, and by moving these up or down a small amount we can shift the scale from one to another, the three being diatonic, chromatic, enharmonic. (Besides the passages from Aristoxenus cited below, see e.g. D.K. 47 A16 on Archytas.) But even then these moveable notes are not completely determined. By moving them up or down within a very small range () we can generate subtly different effects; and while these changes are not reckoned to constitute shifts of , they are sufficient to be recognised, and are designated as differences of shade, . within a No doubt these distinctions originated in the preferences of performances for particular styles of tuning (cf. El. Harm. 23), but however haphazard their origins, Aristoxenus is able to present a formal account of them, recognising three shades of the chromatic and two of the diatonic. The enharmonic does not, in his scheme, admit of such variations. See especially El. Harm. 47–52.

11. Cf. El. Harm. 21, 47 ad init., with 25-6, 46, 50-2.

12. It has been suggested to me that the before is a genuine connective. This would mean that the protasis which begins at (line 12) continues as far as line 14), and then subdivides into the of line 14 and the of line 21.1 find the suggestion quite attractive: it would affect the sense only marginally.

13. Cf. Porphyry 29.27 – 31.21 (Düring).