Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-tf8b9 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-27T02:01:29.594Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Are All Things Created Equal? The Incidental in Archaeology

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  31 January 2020

Susan Pollock
Affiliation:
Freie Universität Berlin, Institut für Vorderasiatische Archäologie, Fabeckstraße 23–25, 14195Berlin, Germany Email: [email protected]
Reinhard Bernbeck
Affiliation:
Freie Universität Berlin, Institut für Vorderasiatische Archäologie, Fabeckstraße 23–25, 14195Berlin, Germany Email: [email protected]
Lena Appel
Affiliation:
Justus-Liebig-Universität Gießen, Institut für Angewandte Theaterwissenschaft, Gutenbergstr. 6, 35390Gießen, Germany Email: [email protected]
Anna K. Loy
Affiliation:
Excellence Cluster ROOTS, Christian-Albrechts-Universität zu Kiel, Leibnizstraße 3, 24118Kiel, Germany Email: [email protected]
Stefan Schreiber
Affiliation:
Römisch-Germanisches Zentralmuseum, Leibniz-Forschungsinstitut für Archäologie Mainz, Ernst-Ludwig-Platz 2, 55116Mainz, Germany Email: [email protected]
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Archaeologists evince a strong tendency to impute significance to the material traces they study, a propensity that has been especially marked since the post-processual emphasis on meaning and that has taken on renewed vigour with the turn to materiality. But are there not situations in which things are rather incidental or insignificant? This set of essays emerged from a workshop held in Berlin in April 2018, in which a group of scholars was invited to discuss the place of the incidental in social life in general and in archaeology in particular. Rather than lengthy formal papers, we offer an introduction that presents a general set of reflections on the issue of the incidentalness of things, followed by essays that pursue particular directions raised by that introduction as well as our discussions in Berlin. It is our hope that these brief forays into a complex topic will stimulate further work on this subject.

Type
Special Section
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
Copyright © McDonald Institute for Archaeological Research 2020

Introduction

‘If there was one blade of grass you know what would have happened, you would have eaten it’—this was the first thought of former Auschwitz prisoner Kitty Hart when she revisited the erstwhile concentration camp and saw the green grounds. Tourists, on the other hand, do not notice the grass as anything special: it is a green background typical for memorial sites and parks. This extreme example shows that the material world can evoke vastly different meanings and expectations, from considerations of existential importance to total obliviousness. Archaeology as ‘the discipline of things’ (Olsen et al. Reference Olsen, Shanks, Webmoor and Witmore2012) seems to be particularly well placed to investigate such questions. Reading recent contributions to the archaeological literature and philosophical works on which they draw could encourage us to view the material world of which we are part as one of enormous significance. However, traditional archaeologists have also acted as though even broken fragments of the most mundane artefacts are of major import.

The workshop from which this set of papers emerged had its genesis in discussions among several of the authors on positionality and shifting relations between things and identities within the framework of the ‘ontological turn’ and new materialisms in archaeology. These took place in the framework of informal discussions concerning the implications of an emerging archaeology of Nazi times in Germany as well as the problems of massive quantities of archaeological finds, especially but by no means exclusively from excavations of sites of modernity (e.g. Hofmann et al. Reference Hofmann, Meier, Mölders and Schreiber2016). In particular, it seemed to us that an issue of substantial importance that has been left aside in many of these discussions of otherwise fundamental principles is whether things—however exactly we define them—invariably have meaning or other kinds of significance for people. But are there not also situations in which they are incidental or insignificant? And, if so, what kinds of situations would call forth incidentalness? And for whom? We can best recognize incidentalness, often related to the quotidian, by reflecting on its opposite, such as the circumstances of extreme cruelty and inhumanity in which inmates of Nazi concentration camps found themselves. There, things take on very different qualities—as Kitty Hart remarks, they are almost never insignificant for those confined there. In other words, in our theoretical musings we must take into consideration those situations that contrast with more ‘normal’ ones, in which many things do indeed seem to fall into the realm of the incidental, inconsequential and casual.

Our intent with this introductory paper is not to offer a programmatic statement, but rather to open a discussion on the incidentalness of the thingly world. We raise a variety of issues and point in certain directions, suggesting potential avenues and posing questions, rather than providing definitive answers or charting a clear path forward.

Conceptualization and problems of translation

In looking for inspiration on how to conceptualize these issues, we turned in the first instance to the work of Martin Heidegger on Zeug as zuhanden (‘ready-to-hand’)Footnote 1 and to Hans Peter Hahn's writings on material culture and the Eigensinn of things (Hahn Reference Hahn and Bielfeldt2014; Reference Hahn and Hahn2015). It was in the latter that we found discussions about Beiläufigkeit that seemed to us to be on the mark.

With it, however, we encountered a first significant problem, that of translation: there is no single satisfactory English term that captures the meaning of Beiläufigkeit.Footnote 2 We have translated it for present purposes as ‘incidentalness’—not a very elegant word in English—but it encompasses a semantic field that includes not only notions of the incidental, but also casual(ness), inconsequentiality, that which is parenthetic, ‘by the way’, and apparently insignificant. The phrase ‘by the way’ incorporates an important element of the German term, where bei- implies a vague notion of ‘next to’ without any specific direction, distance, or quality of distance between two entities; laufen, to walk, suggests a spatial relation of unspecific distance and a sort of ‘moving non-target’. In daily language, Beiläufigkeit denotes something that barely makes it into our consciousness, if at all.

To plumb the depths of complex terminologies and concepts, it is often useful to think in pairs of oppositions and not just in synonyms. However, the search for an opposite of Beiläufigkeit also proves difficult. One can think of words denoting fullness or heaviness, conjuring up in the reverse a certain lightness and emptiness that surrounds the Beiläufige. Attentiveness, amazement, astonishment, caring, focusing, framing and spotlighting also capture elements of the opposite meaning. Beiläufigkeit not only denotes something vague, dynamic and barely perceived: the word itself avoids specificity.

This may be one of the reasons for Heidegger's choice of the term Zeug in Being and Time. Zeug is derived from the propensity of the German language to hang substantives onto each other in a substantivist way of thinking: Nähzeug, Fahrzeug, Spielzeug are all words that denote an unspecified and unordered set of material things: ‘things to sew with’, ‘things to move/drive’, ‘things to play with’. The latter could, for example, be anything from a game board to a teddy bear or a football or even a pen with which a person fiddles during a boring meeting.Footnote 3 In this sense, Hahn's use of Beiläufigkeit and Heidegger's more precise definition of Zeug are fairly similar. Faced with these translational issues, we fall back frequently on the German term, but also use the English words incidentalness, casualness, or inconsequential, depending on the context.

The varying fate of meaning in archaeology

Each of us has found her- or himself reflecting at various times and in various ways on the archaeological tendency to attribute meaning to all of the things we excavate, document and study. This (over)emphasis on meaning rears its head in many places. Post-processual archaeology of the 1980s and 1990s was concerned to counteract processual archaeology's propensity in the opposite direction—to functionalize everything and discount attempts to access meaning. The result was an obsessive attribution of deep significance to almost everything, often a complex symbolic one: white limestone cliffs are supposed by virtue of their colour to be a relevant factor in site locations (Boriç Reference Boriç, Jones and MacGregor2002); simple lines of pottery decorations point to specific underlying social structures and meanings (Hodder Reference Hodder and Hodder1982).

But do all things, regardless of how mundane, peripheral, banal, have a meaning (cf. Olsen Reference Olsen2010, 84–7)? More importantly, do all things embody similar levels or intensities of meaning? Or, rather, are not levels of meanings unstable, dynamic and context-dependent? Recent currents in archaeology, such as new realism and approaches based on object-oriented ontologies, once again realign discussions about the relation between humans and things (Edgeworth Reference Edgeworth2016; Olsen et al. Reference Olsen, Shanks, Webmoor and Witmore2012; Witmore Reference Witmore2014). The paradigm shift away from a discourse- and language-based philosophy, as promoted by Lacan, Foucault, and Barthes, has led to a renewed focus on materiality and a corresponding decline of interest in meaning as a relation between humans and other beings or things in general. New and speculative realism as well as object-oriented ontologies belong to a widespread discourse, one central tendency of which is the decentring of human beings. As a consequence, things and indeed the world are rendered flat; the split between human motivations and their outer appearance has been replaced by a way of thinking that fuses subjects and objects into actants and assemblages (Bennett Reference Bennett2010; DeLanda Reference DeLanda2006; Hamilakis & Jones Reference Hamilakis and Jones2017; Harman Reference Harman2009). Interest in ‘meaning’ as a relation of human symbolic and practical-manipulative power over objects fades (Boivin Reference Boivin2008). Perception and meaning transform into forces contributing to a coagulation or dismemberment of assemblages, released from human intentions or humans as actors. Interestingly, the outcome of this intellectual atmosphere in archaeology is a ‘democracy’ of objects where any and every object seems to be in need of fundamental ‘care’ (Olsen et al. Reference Olsen, Shanks, Webmoor and Witmore2012), where the thing world can be called a ‘parliament’ (Latour Reference Latour2004). In recent discussions, Ian Hodder has promoted the concept of ‘entanglement’, which emphasizes the relevance of almost everything to the constitution of our lived worlds, although in a reworking of his initial book on the subject he has pointed to the asymmetrical relations he sees as typifying entanglement (Hodder Reference Hodder2016).

The concept of Beiläufigkeit can contribute to a critique of this supposed equality of things by insisting that relations between humans and things have highly variable intensities and qualities. Our reflections represent an attempt to open a space to discuss the conditions and processes that are responsible for the variable status of things in a world of objects. Is there a possibility for things/people/other entities to have more or less ‘meaning’, rather than either none or an unspecified full one? Does a potential for variable importance and sense of specific things follow historical rhythms? On what or whom would such an ebb and flow of significances depend?

Mapping Beiläufigkeit

We suggest that the notion of Beiläufigkeit offers a way to address these issues, by shifting attention to that which is physically present but not necessarily a focus of perception or imbued with any particular significance. Beiläufig is that which in a specific context fades into the background. For Heidegger, this is the ready-to-hand that one does not notice because it is simply there and fulfils a task; it is the task that is the object of attention, what is hammered, not the hammer itself (Heidegger [1927] Reference Heidegger1962, 98). In more contemporary terminology, one might say that this kind of a beiläufige use of tools or gestures is part of embodied knowledge, a know-how that becomes sufficiently automatic as not to require conscious thought—until or unless it is disrupted by a broken limb or a broken hammer. This is a thing world upside down. The focus on single things, whether graffiti, taxi cab doors, or museum objects and their complex trajectories (e.g. Fuglerud & Wainwright Reference Fuglerud and Wainwright2015; Savoy Reference Savoy2017), creates an exceptional attention that does not correspond to daily routines in which the thing world drowns in a sea of incidentalness. Indeed, the incidental is the precondition for the ability to perceive and direct affect.

Incidentalness as a general phenomenon remains difficult to grasp and describe, elusive and ambiguous. Everything that we are not aware of belongs to this sphere. Our attention is focused first on one thing, then on another, constantly moving, so that only small attention-seeking islands appear and disappear in a sea of incidentalness. In archaeology, Beiläufigkeit is also related to the use of particular media to depict and represent objects. These are traditionally overwhelmingly visual. We do not pursue here an exploration of the role of other senses in producing incidentalness or its opposite, although this would be an intriguing direction for future research.

Basing on our common-sense understanding of Beiläufigkeit, as well as attempts to think theoretically through the concept and its implications, has led us to emphasize the dynamic aspects of Beiläufigkeit. Under what circumstances do things become (more or less) beiläufig; when and how do they move out of that status?

A cautiously formulated result of these reflections could be that a generalized, broad ‘Incidentalness’ with a capital ‘I’ should be distinguished from concrete, historically manifest incidentalnesses. On the level of generalized Beiläufigkeit, definitional issues can be discussed as well as the question of whether Incidentalness is characterized by a fundamental fluidity and ambiguity. On the other hand, there are concrete historical incidentalnesses, cases in specific and changing worlds that can be compared in terms of their patterns and dynamics. In order to broach these differences between the general Incidental and the specific multiple cases, we have tried to systematize conditions that influence the shaping and framing of Beiläufigkeiten. These are first and foremost the traditional ones of time and space.

Time and rhythm

Incidentalness is fluid, characterized by a process of constant re-focusing. It has a dynamic routine and its own history. The incidental is an unquestioned element of our life, but not an unquestionable sphere, and it should not be conflated with a traditional definition of ‘lifeworld’ as the unquestioned and unquestionable (Habermas Reference Habermas1984, 70). Any element in a beiläufige environment can be consciously ‘zeroed in upon’, fixed, and in the process changed to a very different state, one of impressiveness or attentiveness. However, the material world also exerts its own power over the potential of subjects to guide their attention towards specific elements in their surroundings. The dialectical relation between the ability to concentrate on some things and the possibility to let go have their counterpart in the orientational power of those very things. They embody their own patterns of change, which may be unique and directional or recursive and therefore to a certain extent foreseeable. We begin with several facets of directional change.

A first facet is growing up, which can be understood as a learning process during which more and more aspects of the world become incidental, or at least acquire the potential to be so. Children have much less of a need or a capacity for incidentalness and make distinctions between the incidental and the focused much less systematically and less often than adults. In this way, Beiläufigkeit seems to be a fundamental phenomenon of socialization, but the specific result—which elements of a world can be pushed aside as incidental—is the outcome both of growing up in a particular culture and of personal sensibilities (cf. Benjamin [1987] Reference Benjamin2006). These issues are of significance to an emerging archaeology of childhood and socialization (e.g. Baxter Reference Baxter2008; Coskunsu Reference Coskunsu2016).

In the process of socialization, we learn about incidentalness by getting used to inserting specific kinds of things in specific frameworks. We learn, for example, what a house looks like, or what things afford which contexts—e.g. forks in a kitchen—but also what is socially acceptable and expected of us in particular locations. These frameworks have their own complex multitemporal structure: some elements reach far back in time and have a strong power to anchor perceptions and experience over the long term, influencing generations if not whole epochs in their understanding of the world, e.g. architectural traditions; others are only short in duration and decay quickly, for example, the use of public telephones and phone booths to call people when away from home.

Change comes through small alterations of practices. We can de-incidentalize things by focusing on them and their surroundings, something which often requires an initial call for attention. Consequently, incidentalness is neither inherent in objects or living beings, nor is it purely a matter of individual perception or a broadly generalizable relation between the two. Rather, incidentalness needs to be understood as a culture-specific potential that underlies the contingency of relations.

Second, the more we involve ourselves in a particular environment, the easier it is to focus attention on highly specific individual phenomena and by implication to ignore everything else. Travel and the accompanying experience of being a foreigner lead to a rapid lowering of incidentalness. Where language, culture, food, clothing and rituals are foreign, full attention is required to make sense of one's impressions and the relationships between them. Non-incidentalness and the active, intensified search for meaning are closely related. Conversely, the most basic elements necessary for survival will, after a short time, tend toward the casual even in foreign environments. They will be primarily situated in the material world rather than in linguistic and intellectual spheres and are therefore relevant for any material studies.

Third, rites of passage produce an abrupt change in the well-rehearsed world of the incidental, set in motion through ritually structured processes. Since these are stages in life through which other subjects also go, such deep-running changes are predictable from an external perspective and in their objective consequences; they lead to a shift in perceived identity. The required negotiation between the new role and one's surroundings entails a re-socialization which is not in essence distinct from travel, as parts of the changing environment have to be mastered and condensed into a routine.

Fourth, certain historical circumstances can lead to an expansion or narrowing of relations of incidentalness. A secure, little-changing environment might tend towards a fast spread of incidentalness at the expense of attentiveness, as dangers are minimized and awareness of contexts is not required. Situations of threat, on the other hand, lead to greater attention and therefore to a diminution of the beiläufige world. One can consider conditions in prisons, in war or participation in a hunt as examples. Reports about battlefields by former soldiers suggest that in violence-prone situations the world of inattentive routine almost completely disappears and even the smallest everyday objects, every movement or sound, take on extraordinary relevance. Not without grave consequences. Walter Benjamin noted that the experience of extreme violence in the First World War ended with a society-wide loss of the capacity for experience (Jay Reference Jay1999/2000).

Such non-recursive temporal frames of Beiläufigkeit include varying degrees of unforeseeability. In contrast, repetitive events have their own position in incidental worlds. In this realm, it is useful to distinguish quotidian from exceptional recursivity.

Quotidian recursive temporalities and incidentalness reinforce each other. Cyclical occurrences mesh with daily, weekly, or seasonal habits. They bring with them sets of experiences that spur expectations, often including expectations about the framing of specific events (Koselleck Reference Koselleck2004, 255–75). Time and space fuse, making a crowding-out and forgetting of the spatio-temporal backstage world relatively easy.

In contrast to such quotidian recursiveness are exceptional occurrences such as rituals (for definition, see Kertzer Reference Kertzer1988 and Bell Reference Bell1992). Often set into transcendentally anchored complex religious dogma or political staging, they capture our full attention when they are able to mobilize a host of elements that frame our lives, from movements (processions) to smells, tastes, the audible, or gift giving. One could even propose that successful rituals are those that temporally abrogate a maximum amount of incidentalness.

Both quotidian and ritual temporalities are part of experienced and remembered time (Rosa Reference Rosa2010). Time filled with special or exciting encounters passes very quickly. Conversely, the same amount of time spent with everyday, repetitive activities feels as though it goes by very slowly. This perception of experienced time is often inversely proportional to remembered time. Extraordinary moments remain in one's memory long after, while the boring ones are perceived as beiläufig, unimportant, and coalesce into an undifferentiated mass in one's memory. This multitemporal aspect of Beiläufigkeit could, in Rosa's sense, be an effect of the relationship between experience and memory and also an expression of feelings of social acceleration and slowing down.

Space

Incidentalness is supported by spatial conditions. We distinguish two fundamentally different approaches to the relation between space and the incidental. Some authors start from a subjectivist notion of incidentalness and describe it as driven by perception, while others analyse the incidental as a mise-en-scène or framing.

Heidegger's attempt to describe a room and its perception in his chapter on Zeug and Zuhandenheit in Being and Time highlights the complexity of incidentalness from the perspective of a subject. The ready-to-hand is by definition ‘in its place’ and includes—according to Heidegger—a specific nearness and directionality (Verweisung).Footnote 4 One might formulate this, following Mary Douglas, by saying that the incidental is matter in place (Douglas Reference Douglas1984, 36–41). Still, in Heidegger's philosophy, things do not only passively hold a place, but act, since he describes them as ‘retreating’, stepping away into a ‘veiled underworld’ (see also Harman's Reference Harman2002 rereading). The consequence is that a particular spatial or relational distribution of objects can be experienced as unproblematic, unperceived, we might say ‘normal’.

Miller expresses the specific actions of things as their ‘humility’ (Miller Reference Miller1987, 85–108) and mentions monumentality as (one of) the opposites of such a quality. Engagements with thing worlds often start from this opposing end and question why and how people perceive particular things as possessing an enhanced rather than an unobtrusive and low-key position. Another good example is Walter Benjamin's engagement with aura. Benjamin (Reference Benjamin and Arendt1968) takes a person as the starting point, and the focus is placed squarely on that which attracts and enchants, that which is not incidental. Underlying these approaches is the conviction that incidentalness and attentiveness are an antagonistic pair. Typical for this paradigmatic choice is Miller's (Reference Miller1987) term objectification: the world is understood as a configuration of entities exterior to a subject.

This point leads us to a brief aside: Does this mean that a world where things consist of a mix of what we traditionally consider lifeless objects and living beings would not differentiate between the incidental and the attention-commanding? The question has regained renewed attraction with the ontological turn and questioning of the affective qualities of relations between things, rather than just between people and things. A non-anthropocentric view may help us to think more generally through questions concerning the quality and quantity of relationships.Footnote 5 Rather than being an epistemological mode of human perception and evaluation of relations, Beiläufigkeit might be understood as an ontological relation. Is Beiläufigkeit then a quality or mode of interaction between entities, one that is undirected, random and unrepeatable? With what other humans and non-humans do things come into contact? Or is it rather the externalized result of a process of territorialization of an assemblage (DeLanda Reference DeLanda2006, 12–13), an unstable, boundary-drawing process of a ‘subject-less self-referring entity that captures different actions into the same flow’ (Normark Reference Normark2010, 168; see also Schreiber Reference Schreiber2018, 113–14)? These questions would not be answered in the same way by each of the authors of this paper.

Let us return to the previous argument and turn the logic around to consider the spatialities of incidentalness as a matter of subjectivation. Here, incidentalness is not in the eye of the beholder or the potentially changeable interest of a person, but is rather determined to a certain extent by spatial conditions. Erving Goffman's (Reference Goffman1986) concept of frame analysis is a useful starting point, although his approach is situated in intersubjective and discursive realms, whereas our concern is with material framing. Goffman's ideas of social life as framed make reference to theatre as an underlying metaphor: actions are carried out on a stage that has scenery and a setting.

Such framing is, we propose, an organizer of incidentalness. A specific material setting draws attention to particular things while deflecting from others (Butler Reference Butler2009). It dissects an endless attention-seeking world into entities that gravitate towards specific relations and practices. Umberto Eco takes from Goffman the example of a personFootnote 6 and a mirror (Eco Reference Eco1994, 105). At a hairdresser's a person inspects the mirror for its decorated frame rather than to adjust their hair. The same mirror is sold in an antique shop, and a person stands in front of it adjusting their hair rather than examining the frame. The point is the mirror's context, which emphasizes some of its qualities and pushes others into a stage-like background. When these culturally fixed expectations are not followed, the scene is perceived as inappropriate. Put differently, Beiläufigkeit, attentiveness and specific rules that relate them need to be considered as a set of connections that is constantly reproduced through material practices in daily life. On a broader level, frame theory could lead to an investigation of the relation between material frames and expectations for practices. Both can to some extent be materially manifest, and in such cases, the diversion from these expectations could give us a sense of how people in the past dealt with the incidental. In our workshop discussions, Shannon Dawdy referred to the concept of facilitators, things that were made to be incidental; we may think of a computer mouse or paper coffee cups. Other things may become that way, despite different original intentions.

How does Beiläufigkeit challenge archaeological practice?

Archaeologists often study pre-modern worlds. These are frequently reconstructed as emptier than ours, bare of the thousands of human-made things we surround ourselves with and are surrounded by. Varying abundances of things in specific locations and times may accord them a more or less meaningful position, specifically in archaeological discourse. If we follow the idea of material framing as a stage set that leads to specific forms of subjectivation and understandings of incidentalness, what does this imply for pre-industrial times? Answers to this question are not straightforward. Should we imagine that the whole issue of incidentalness is a truly modern one, the outcome of a world that drowns in things,Footnote 7 so that a generalized Incidentalness (with a capital ‘I’) cannot be posited at all? Do material framings subjectivize people into fundamentally different selves whose constitution defies comparability? Or does incidentalness lend itself to cross-cultural comparisons? No matter how we approach thingly quantities and their effects on framing, a basic issue for dealing with Beiläufigkeit in the deeper past surely must be a sort of hermeneutic withdrawal from one's own overflowing thing-world.

The issues of framing and staging also raise again the question of whether all things have similar potentials to be beiläufig. Are specific kinds of things inherently more or less likely to become or to remain beiläufig? Or—and we argue that this is more likely—is Beiläufigkeit always a relation dependent on a staging of an object world, an emergent property of the relationships between people and things, rather than being somehow inherent in things? Fundamentally, it seems to us that Beiläufigkeit is much more easily produced in a highly specialized world such as ours, one that is filled with stuff and in which the object world is at least in part separated from personal culture, than in a materially frugal, less specialized realm. This rests more on the recognition (or lack thereof) of the work that goes into making things than on a simple issue of quantity (cf. Fowles Reference Fowles, Bille, Hastrup and Sorensen2010). Incidentalness is related to knowledge and/or visibility of labour, drudgery and skill in the making of a material world, even if indirectly. When we are not confronted with or do not make the effort to see the labour entailed in making the clothing we wear, the computers on which we write our papers and through which much of our communication takes place, or the ‘cleansing’ of internet content performed by workers in the Philippines, this inattention contributes to the making of incidentalness.

How research changes the object of study

Archaeology is a discipline that is quintessentially opposed to Beiläufigkeit, as we search almost by definition for meaning in all material that captures our attention, even when that meaning amounts to little more than functions of things. But this is not a democratic process—we sort things out according to our (often implicit) interests and questions, paying attention, for example, to chipped stone artefacts when they are found in Palaeolithic or Neolithic contexts, but not when they occur in Bronze Age occupations. Our search for meaning takes place in two registers. On the one hand, much effort goes into (more or less explicit) reconstructions of the meanings of concrete things. On the other hand, archaeology and its often frustratingly unimaginative attempts at historiography are part of a whole apparatus of Sinnproduktion, ‘making sense of the past’ as an orientation, however imprecise, for the future (e.g. Rüsen Reference Rüsen1990). An archaeological field project, article or book that does not want to make sense of an issue, a site, or a research problem is doomed to failure.

We note that the role of incidentalness is much more easily grasped and analysed in a diachronic study, whereas a synchronic search for the incidental in other (past) cultures faces many more obstacles. It is a symptom for the state of archaeology, a discipline that cannot relinquish things and let them return to their ‘humble’ past contexts where they perhaps did not have an overly important place, where they were just the casual object next door. We are left with the question of how we can extract from our evidential record hints at the varying potential for incidentalization of past things or enchainments of things.

We are not the first to note one of the paradoxes of research on Beiläufigkeit: when training the spotlight on a concrete incidental thing, we automatically—per definition—take this very thing on which we focus out of the realm of the Beiläufige. We archaeologists deal best with incidentalness when we are off duty. While we are used to destroying that which we investigate materially through excavation, in this case the effect is located in the conceptual world. A study of Beiläufigkeit is thereby invariably part of the history of knowledge at its most complex—as a developing diachronic relation.

What do we do with this paradox of automatically destroying the very core of our interest? It has no real solution, but we see three possible ways of coping with it. The first is to abandon wholesale the issue of Beiläufigkeit as outside of academic investigation. Clearly, this is not a direction we advocate. A second option is to study incidentalness not as it shapes up, but as a matter of memory. In this case, we are confronted with personal anecdotes, a way of thinking that is often the starting point of philosophical treatises. We consider this insufficient for an anthropologically and politically engaged archaeology. A third alternative is to attempt to objectivize the issue: to study the things that were made to be incidental. In the realm of material (or other) production, that means investigating tools and their position in social life, since they are material means that were used for other ends. In terms of consumption, incidental things would be the opposite of Latour's (Reference Latour1999, 186) ‘sleeping policeman’, e.g. man-hole covers, to stay with the example of the street. These are things that hide, that do not disrupt, but that still keep their agency. From that perspective, present and past material elements for the production of incidentalness might best be conceived as large-scale systems of concealment.

One final characteristic needs to be added to these reflections on the incidental: its political import. The world of Beiläufigkeiten is political in complex and indirect ways, first, because that world appears to be the opposite of anything political: the unperceived, irrelevant, casual, peripheral. This very location below the radar renders incidentalness so powerful. The unnoticed is unquestioned and does not run the danger of being opposed.

The threshold that separates the non-incidental from the casual, unperceived reality is deeply ideological. It determines what we can capture with our senses, whether through language, sight, acoustics, or otherwise. We follow Rancière's (Reference Rancière2004) insight that perception is a cultural-political process that cuts the world into specific parts that for us come into existence through the senses. These parts are continuously reproduced, modified, and sometimes abruptly changed.

The world of incidentalness has its own inner structure. In archaeology, this structure has developed historically. We attempt to democratize the Beiläufigkeit potential of the thingly world by claiming to take everything as important, although we, too, sort (out), classify, and attribute meaning or withhold it. Some things can be closer, others further away from the threshold of imperceptibility. The papers that follow provide important insights into the complex field of relations between people and things, divisions, processes and emergent dynamics that remind us how much of the world in which we live remains barely noticed, if not completely overlooked, yet deeply influential.

Acknowledgements

This article is based on the introduction to the workshop ‘Do Things Have Meaning. Beiläufigkeit in Archaeology’, held in April 2018 in Berlin, as part of the Cluster of Excellence ‘Topoi. The Formation and Transformation of Space and Knowledge’, financed by the Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft. We thank all of the participants for their engagement and enthusiasm. The current manuscript has benefited from the comments of two anonymous reviewers.

Footnotes

1. Heidegger ([1927] Reference Heidegger1962, 95–122). We did so with many reservations. Not all of us were willing to fully engage with Heidegger's work, as the influence on his philosophy of his Nazi political leanings—which he neither denied nor renounced during his lifetime—remains intensely disputed (see Scheit Reference Scheit2001).

2. The German noun is Beiläufigkeit [incidentalness, inconsequentialness]; the adjective is beiläufig.

3. In the English translation of Heidegger's Sein und Zeit, Zeug is generally rendered as ‘equipment’; only in a few places is the somewhat pejorative ‘stuff’ used (Heidegger [1927] Reference Heidegger1962, 97). Julian Thomas has suggested the term ‘kit’.

4. Our understanding of Beiläufigkeit differs in a fundamental way from Heidegger's. His whole vocabulary consists of substantives, such as das Hingehören or das Zuhandene, dividing the world into static building blocks that are set into relation to each other. We consider incidentalness to occur mainly in the becoming, rather than as static being.

5. One may note that the ontological turn has led to a wave of anthropomorphization of the material world, with the proclaimed refusal of anthropocentrism in many cases turned on its head.

6. A woman in the original.

7. A recent conference on the ‘massive accumulation of things’ discussed these issues (Hofmann et al. Reference Hofmann, Meier, Mölders and Schreiber2016).

References

Baxter, J.E., 2008. The archaeology of childhood. Annual Review of Anthropology 37, 159–75.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bell, C., 1992. Ritual Theory, Ritual Practice. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Bennett, J., 2010. Vibrant Matter. A political ecology of things. Durham (NC): Duke University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Benjamin, W., 1968. The work of art in the age of mechanical reproduction, in Illuminations, ed. Arendt, H.. New York (NY): Schocken, 217–52.Google Scholar
Benjamin, W., [1987] 2006. Berliner Kindheit um neunzehnhundert [Berlin childhood around 1900]. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.Google Scholar
Boivin, N., 2008. Material Cultures, Material Minds. The impact of things on human thought, society, and evolution. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Boriç, D., 2002. Apotropaism and the temporality of colours: colourful Mesolithic-Neolithic seasons in the Danube Gorges, in Colouring the Past: The significance of colour in archaeological research, eds Jones, A. & MacGregor, G.. Oxford: Berg, 2343.Google Scholar
Butler, J., 2009. Frames of War. When is life grievable? London/New York: Verso.Google Scholar
Coskunsu, G. (ed.), 2016. The Archaeology of Childhood. Interdisciplinary perspectives on an archaeological enigma. Albany (NY): SUNY Press.Google Scholar
DeLanda, M., 2006. A New Philosophy of Society. Assemblage theory and social complexity. London/New York: Continuum.Google Scholar
Douglas, M., 1984. Purity and Danger. An analysis of the concepts of pollution and taboo. London/New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Eco, U., 1994. The Limits of Interpretation. Bloomington (IN): Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
Edgeworth, M., 2016. Grounded objects. Archaeology and speculative realism. Archaeological Dialogues 23, 93113.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fowles, S., 2010. People without things, in An Anthropology of Absence. Materializations of transcendence and loss, ed. Bille, M., Hastrup, F. & Sorensen, T.F.. New York (NY): Springer, 2341.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fuglerud, Ø. & Wainwright, L. (eds), 2015. Objects and Imagination. Perspectives on materialization and meaning. New York (NY): Berghahn.Google Scholar
Goffman, E., 1986. Frame Analysis. An essay on the organization of experience. Boston (MA): Northeastern University Press.Google Scholar
Habermas, J., 1984. Theory of Communicative Action, Vol. 1: Reason and the rationalization of society. Boston (MA): Beacon Press.Google Scholar
Hahn, H.P., 2014. Widerständigkeit und Eigensinn des Materiellen. Modelle der Wahrnehmung der dinglichen Welt [Resistance and self-will of the material. Models of perception of the object world], in Ding und Mensch in der Antike. Gegenwart und Vergegenwärtigung [Thing and person in antiquity. Present and making present], ed. Bielfeldt, R.. (Akademie-Konferenzen 16.) Heidelberg: Winter, 6788.Google Scholar
Hahn, H.P., 2015. Der Eigensinn der Dinge. Einleitung [The obstinacy of things. An introduction], in Vom Eigensinn der Dinge. Für eine neue Perspektive auf die Welt des Materiellen [Of the obstinacy of things. Toward a new perspective on the world of the material], ed. Hahn, H.P.. Berlin: Neofelis, 1056.Google Scholar
Hamilakis, H. & Jones, A.M. (eds), 2017. Archaeology and assemblage, Cambridge Archaeological Journal 27(1), 77193.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harman, G., 2002. Tool-Being. Heidegger and the metaphysics of objects. Chicago/La Salle: Open Court.Google Scholar
Harman, G., 2009. Prince of Networks. Bruno Latour and metaphysics. Melbourne: re.press.Google Scholar
Heidegger, M., [1927] 1962. Being and Time. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Hodder, I., 1982. Sequences of structural change in the Dutch Neolithic, in Symbolic and Structural Archaeology, ed. Hodder, I.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 162–78.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hodder, I., 2016. Studies in Human-Thing Entanglement. Online at: https://www.ian-hodder.com/books/studies-human-thing-entanglementGoogle Scholar
Hofmann, K.P., Meier, T., Mölders, D. & Schreiber, S. (eds), 2016. Massendinghaltung in der Archäologie: Der material turn und die Ur- und Frühgeschichte [Mass accumulation of things in archaeology: the material turn and prehistory]. Leiden: Sidestone Press.Google Scholar
Jay, M. 1999/2000. Walter Benjamin, remembrance, and the First World War. Review of Japanese Culture and Society 11/12, 1831.Google Scholar
Kertzer, D.I., 1988. Ritual, Politics, and Power. New Haven/London: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Koselleck, R., 2004. Futures Past. On the semantics of historical time. New York (NY): Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Latour, B., 1999. Pandora's Hope. Essays on the reality of science studies. Cambridge/London: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Latour, B., 2004. Politics of Nature. How to bring the sciences into democracy. Cambridge (MA): Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Miller, D., 1987. Material Culture and Mass Consumption. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Normark, J., 2010. Involutions of materiality. Operationalizing a neo-materialist perspective through the causeways at Ichmul and Yo'okop. Journal of Archaeological Method and Theory 17, 132–73.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Olsen, B., 2010. In Defense of Things. Archaeology and the ontology of objects. Lanham/Boulder/New York/Toronto/Oxford: AltaMira.Google Scholar
Olsen, B., Shanks, M., Webmoor, T. & Witmore, C., 2012. Archaeology. The discipline of things. Berkeley/Los Angeles/London: University of California Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rancière, J., 2004. The Politics of Aesthetics: The distribution of the sensible. London/New Delhi/New York/Sydney: Bloomsbury.Google Scholar
Rosa, H., 2010. Alienation and Acceleration. Towards a critical theory of late-modern temporality. Malmö: NSU Press.Google Scholar
Rüsen, J., 1990. Zeit und Sinn. Strategien historischen Denkens [Time and meaning. Strategies of historical thought]. Frankfurt am Main: Fischer.Google Scholar
Savoy, B., 2017. Objets du désir, désir d'objects [Objects of desire, desire of objects]. Paris: Fayard.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scheit, G., 2001. Das Sein ohne Juden: Über Martin Heidegger [Existence without Jews: About Martin Heidegger]. Zwischenwelt 18(1), 117.Google Scholar
Schreiber, S., 2018. Wandernde Dinge als Assemblagen. Neo-materialistische Perspektiven zum ‘römischen Import’ im ‘mitteldeutschen Barbaricum’ [Wandering things as assemblages. Neo-materialist perspectives on ‘Roman imports’ in the central German ‘Barbaricum’]. Berlin: Edition Topoi.Google Scholar
Witmore, C., 2014. Archaeology and the new materialisms. Journal of Contemporary Archaeology 1(2), 203–24.CrossRefGoogle Scholar