Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-gxg78 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-27T02:22:37.104Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Ethics of Price Gouging

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  23 January 2015

Abstract

Price gouging occurs when, in the wake of an emergency, sellers of a certain necessary goods sharply raise their prices beyond the level needed to cover increased costs. Most people think that price gouging is immoral, and most states have laws rendering the practice a civil or criminal offense. The purpose of this paper is to explore some of the philosophic issues surrounding price gouging, and to argue that the common moral condemnation of it is largely mistaken. I will make this argument in three steps, by rebutting three widely held beliefs about the ethics of price gouging: 1) that laws prohibiting price gouging are morally justified, 2) that price gouging is morally impermissible behavior, even if it ought not be illegal, and 3) that price gouging reflects poorly on the moral character of those who engage in it, even if the act itself is not morally impermissible.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Society for Business Ethics 2008

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Aquinas, T. 1918. Summa theologica. London: R. T. Washbourne.Google Scholar
Barry, B. 1986. Lady Chatterley’s lover and Doctor Fischer’s bomb party: Liberalism, Pareto-optimality, and the problem of objectionable preferences. In Elster, J. & Hylland, A. (Eds.), Foundations of social choice theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Bastiat, F. 1995. What is seen and what is not seen. In de Huszar, G. B. (Ed.), Selected essays on political economy. Irvington-on-Hudson, NY: Foundation for Economic Education.Google Scholar
Boston, Globe. 2004. City seeks to buy excess flu vaccine. October 15: B2. Available at http://www.boston.com/news/local/massachusetts/articles/2004/10/15/6_accused_of_rmv_permit_scheme/.Google Scholar
Bowie, N. E. 1988. Fair markets. Journal of Business Ethics, 7: 8998.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bowie, N. E., & Werhane, P. 2005. Management ethics. Malden, MA: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Buchanan, J. 1999. Cost and choice: An inquiry in economic theory. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.Google Scholar
Crist, C. 2004. Attorney general charges two Florida hotels with price gouging. Retrieved November 27, 2007, from http://myfloridalegal.com/__852562220065EE67.nsf/0/A15CA108ECBF1DDE85256EF30054D0FC?0pen&Highlight=0,gouging,palm,beach.Google Scholar
Cullity, G. 2006. The moral demands of affluence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Dressler, J. 2006. Understanding the criminal law, 4th ed. Newark: LexisNexis.Google Scholar
Farnsworth, E. A. 1982. Contracts. Boston: Little Brown and Company.Google Scholar
Federal Trade Commission. 2006. Investigation of gasoline price manipulation and post-Katrina gasoline price increases. Retrieved August 29, 2007, from http://www.ftc.gov/reports/060518PublicGasolinePricesInvestigationReportFinal.pdf.Google Scholar
Feinberg, J. 1983. Legal paternalism. In Sartorius, R. (Ed.), Paternalism. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Feinberg, J. 1986. Harm to self. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Frankfurt, H. 1973. Coercion and moral responsibility. In Honderich, T. (Ed.), Essays on freedom of action. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Fuller, L. 1964. The morality of law. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Gode, D. K., & Sunder, S. 1993. Allocative efficiency of markets with zero-intelligence traders: Markets as a partial substitute for individual rationality. Journal of Political Economy, 101: 119–37.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gorr, M. 1986. Toward a theory of coercion. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 16: 383406.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haidt, J. 2001. The emotional dog and its rational tail: A social intuitionist approach to moral judgment. Psychological Review, 108: 814–34.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Haidt, J., Koller, S. H., & Dias, M. G. 1993. Affect, culture, and morality, or is it wrong to eat your dog? Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 65: 613–28.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hayek, F. A. 1944. The road to serfdom. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Hayek, F. A.. 1968. Competition as a discovery procedure. In Hayek, F. A. (Ed.), New studies in philosophy, politics, economics, and the history of ideas. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Hayek, F. A.. 1980. The use of knowledge in society. In Hayek, F. (Ed.), Individualism and economic order: 7791. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. 1982. Judgment under uncertainty: Heuristics and biases. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kamm, F. 2006. Intricate ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kant, I. 1994. The metaphysics of morals, part II. In James, W. Ellington (Trans.), Ethical Philosophy, book 2, pp. 31161. Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
Kirzner, I. 1979. The Perils of Regulation: A market process approach. Coral Gables, FL: University of Miami School of Law, Law and Economics Center.Google Scholar
Kirzner, I.. 1996. The meaning of market process: Essays in the development of modern Austrian economics. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Leff, A. A. 1967. Unconscionability and the code: The emperor’s new clause. University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 115.Google Scholar
Mas-Colell, A., Whinston, M., & Green, J. 1995. Microeconomic theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Mayer, R. 2007. What’s wrong with exploitation? Journal of Applied Philosophy, 24: 137–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Meyers, C. 2004. Wrongful beneficence: Exploitation and third world sweatshops. Journal of Social Philosophy, 35: 319–33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miller, R. 2004. Beneficence, duty and distance. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 32: 357–83.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Munger, M. 2007. They clapped: Can price gouging laws prohibit scarcity? Retrieved June 12, 2007, from http://www.econlib.org/LIBRARY/Columns/y2007/Mungergouging.html.Google Scholar
Murphy, L. 2003. Moral demands in nonideal theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Nozick, R. 1969. Coercion. In Morgenbesser, S. (Ed.), Philosophy, science and method. New York: St. Martin’s Press.Google Scholar
Nozick, R.. 1974. Anarchy, state, and utopia. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
O’Driscoll, G., & Rizzo, M. 1996. The economics of time and ignorance. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Rapp, G. 2005–2006. Gouging: Terrorist attacks, hurricanes, and the legal and economic aspects of post-disaster price regulation. Kentucky Law Journal, 94.Google Scholar
Rawls, J. 1971. A theory of justice, 1st ed. Cambridge: Belknap Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Raz, J. 1982. Liberalism, autonomy, and the politics of neutral concern. In French, P. (Ed.), Midwest Studies in Philosophy, vol. 8. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Raz, J.. 1986. The morality of freedom. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sample, R. 2003. Exploitation: What it is and why it’s wrong. New York: Rowman and Littlefield.Google Scholar
Samuelson, P., & Nordhaus, W. 1998. Economics. Boston: Irwin McGraw-Hill.Google Scholar
Schmidtz, D. 2000. Islands in a sea of obligation: Limits of the duty to rescue. Law and Philosophy, 19: 683705.Google Scholar
Schmidtz, D.. 2006. Elements of justice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Simmons, A. J. 1993. On the edge of anarchy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Singer, P. 1972. Famine, affluence, and morality. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 1: 229–43.Google Scholar
Skarbek, D. Forthcoming. Market failure and natural disaster: A reexamination of anti-gouging laws. Public Contract Law Journal.Google Scholar
Skarbek, D., & Skarbek, B. 2008. The price is right!: How price gouging laws delay post-disaster recovery. Unpublished manuscript. Santa Clara University.Google Scholar
Smith, V. 1982. Market as economizers of information: Experimental examination of the “Hayek hypothesis.” Economic Inquiry, 20(2): 165–79.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sollars, G. G., & Englander, F. 2007. Sweatshops: Kant and consequences. Business Ethics Quarterly, 17: 115–33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sowell, T. 2004. “Price gouging” in Florida. Jewish World Review, September 28. Retrieved November 15, 2007, from http://www.jewishworldreview.com/cols/sowell091404.asp.Google Scholar
Wertheimer, A. 1996. Exploitation. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wertheimer, A.. 2006. Coercion. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Zimmerman, D. 1981. Coercive wage offers. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 10: 121–45.Google Scholar
Zwolinski, M. 2007. Sweatshops, choice, and exploitation. Business Ethics Quarterly, 17: 689727.CrossRefGoogle Scholar