Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-2brh9 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-28T15:10:26.594Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Ankur Barua: Exploring Hindu Philosophy (Series in Global Philosophy.) Sheffield, UK and Bristol, CT: Equinox, 2023. ISBN 978 1 80050 269 7.

Review products

Ankur Barua: Exploring Hindu Philosophy (Series in Global Philosophy.) Sheffield, UK and Bristol, CT: Equinox, 2023. ISBN 978 1 80050 269 7.

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  13 December 2023

John Nemec*
Affiliation:
University of Virginia, Charlottesville, USA
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Type
Reviews
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of SOAS University of London

Hinduism is tremendously varied in its internal diversity, because the term refers to a host of traditions that developed and found practice across the Indian subcontinent and over the course of more than two millennia. To specify an array of materials to be studied under the broad title of “Hindu Philosophy”, and in a manner sufficiently narrow that it can fit into a short introductory book, is therefore no simple matter. Nevertheless, Ankur Barua, in this elegant volume of deceptively simple presentation, represents Hindu thought in a manner that sympathetically covers the subject with admirable range and yet is ideally suited for students.

Barua begins with a simple but significant proposition: to “… convey one key point to you [the reader]: while the patterns of arguments and counterarguments in Hindu styles of reasoning occasionally become quite rarefied, such patterns do ‘touch base’ with some of our basic experiences, ideas, and thoughts” (p. ix). This “key point” in turn suggests that Barua will engage fully his double experience, which was nurtured in two intellectual contexts: a department of philosophy and a faculty of divinity (p. x). He is interested in the analytical sophistication of Indian philosophy, but only while also remaining sensitive to its religious dimension, to the capacity for careful thought to further what Hindu thought can offer to a “philosophy of life” (p. 5). There can be no denying, as Barua himself indicates (pp. 3–7; passim), that such an approach will invite the view that “Hindu philosophy” is much the former at the cost of the rigour of the latter. So much is folly, however, as Barua rightly suggests, for Hindu thought demands a widened view of philosophy rather than a reflexive ghettoization of the same to a particular category of religion for its supposed lack of precision or objectivity. Thus this book, which “may initially seem to be a parochial inquiry into Hindu philosophy”, can be “repositioned as a critical contribution to contemporary conversations about the concept of philosophy across European and Indian intellectual landscapes” (p. 3).

Scholars who have read deeply in Indian philosophical traditions will find Barua’s “explorations” to be only slightly idiosyncratic, deeply coherent, and admirably ranging across many of the views of most of the major Brahminical traditions of analytic reflection of India's premodernity. A heavy dose of the realist Nyāya and Vaiśeṣika schools does much to shape the initial chapters of the book, with a slight emphasis on forms of Vedāntic speculation emerging more prominently in the later chapters. I was happy also to see mention in several places of some of the “sectarian” traditions, for example the Śaiva Siddhānta (pp. 70–71) and the non-dual Śaiva traditions occasionally referred to under the moniker of “Kashmiri Shaivism” (pp. 118–9), for these and similar philosophical schools have often been left out of published surveys of Indian thought.

Barua offers no comprehensive survey of Hindu Philosophy, however, and this is a strength of the book. For he instead endeavours substantially to explore a particular pattern of questions – human questions begging philosophical enquiry – which as I understand them are arranged as follows. First, chapter 1 (pp. 21–46) examines the nature of the world of phenomena (the prameyas) with a principal eye on the categories of existents (padārthas) primarily as articulated in Praśastapāda's Padārthadharmasaṃgraha, while chapter 2 (pp. 47–71) reflects on the means of knowing the same (the pramāṇas). Having thus examined what the world might be and how we might know it to be thus, Barua turns in chapter 3 (pp. 73–97) to “Therapies for liberation”, in other words to what it is that one can do given one's place in the world. Here, he explores Hindu views of the nature of the divine, ranging from a ubiquitous Brahman to a rather more monadic Īśvara. Chapter 4 (pp. 99–124) then considers how the world of finite entities may hook up with an infinite and transcendent divine, suggesting not only a host of philosophical problems in fashioning such a connection but paving the way too for an understanding of one's condition of living in the world given what can transcend it. Finally, chapter 5 (pp. 125–49) considers various models of morality in light of the theological and philosophical concerns established in the previous chapters. The conclusion (pp. 151–63) ties together these interlaced concerns by examining “… (1) the relation between descriptive accounts and revisionary accounts of what exists, (2) the role of cognition in revealing or constructing the world, and (3) the relation between philosophy and emancipation” (p. 154), though one feels Barua offers a slight repetition in the conclusion of his discussion of Hindu views of perception, examined already in chapter 2.

The strength of the book lies with Barua's deftness of philosophical analysis. He moves seamlessly between and across various philosophical concerns, representing accurately, clearly, and without oversimplification the subtly different positions of a host of schools as they address a range of related concerns such as the nature of language, the functioning of perception, the proper order of logic and inferential reasoning, the nature of objective reality, and questions of ethics and morality. That Hindu philosophers set these matters in relation to soteriological concerns is properly explained and justified, illustrating that subtle philosophical argument can emerge even in the context of thinking done by philosophers who simultaneously hold deep theological commitments. One does miss from these pages the presence of the philosophical positions of Hindu philosophy's principal opponents, the Buddhists with whom Hindu philosophers perennially argued, though given the scope and size of this book, Barua's focus on Hindu schools is readily justified. Another concern is that using this book for teaching will require one to help students historically to order the various thinkers and schools that Barua examines. So much may be managed without too much difficulty, however, and those who take this book to the classroom are likely to find that Barua's thoughtful engagement with Hindu philosophical ideas will enrich, deepen, and enliven their discussion – and both their students’ and their own appreciation – of Hindu philosophy.