Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-dzt6s Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-22T08:53:22.360Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

STRONG COLORINGS OVER PARTITIONS

Part of: Set theory

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  22 February 2021

WILLIAM CHEN-MERTENS
Affiliation:
DEPARTMENT OF MATHEMATICS & STATISTICS YORK UNIVERSITY, 4700 KEELE STREET TORONTO, ON M3J 1P3, CANADAE-mail: [email protected]: [email protected]
MENACHEM KOJMAN
Affiliation:
DEPARTMENT OF MATHEMATICS BEN-GURION UNIVERSITY OF THE NEGEV P.O.B. 653, BE’ER SHEVA 84105, ISRAELE-mail: [email protected]
JURIS STEPRĀNS
Affiliation:
DEPARTMENT OF MATHEMATICS & STATISTICS YORK UNIVERSITY, 4700 KEELE STREET TORONTO, ON M3J 1P3, CANADAE-mail: [email protected]: [email protected]
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

A strong coloring on a cardinal $\kappa $ is a function $f:[\kappa ]^2\to \kappa $ such that for every $A\subseteq \kappa $ of full size $\kappa $ , every color $\unicode{x3b3} <\kappa $ is attained by $f\restriction [A]^2$ . The symbol

$$ \begin{align*} \kappa\nrightarrow[\kappa]^2_{\kappa} \end{align*} $$
asserts the existence of a strong coloring on $\kappa $ .

We introduce the symbol

$$ \begin{align*} \kappa\nrightarrow_p[\kappa]^2_{\kappa} \end{align*} $$
which asserts the existence of a coloring $f:[\kappa ]^2\to \kappa $ which is strong over a partition $p:[\kappa ]^2\to \theta $ . A coloring f is strong over p if for every $A\in [\kappa ]^{\kappa }$ there is $i<\theta $ so that for every color $\unicode{x3b3} <\kappa $ is attained by $f\restriction ([A]^2\cap p^{-1}(i))$ .

We prove that whenever $\kappa \nrightarrow [\kappa ]^2_{\kappa }$ holds, also $\kappa \nrightarrow _p[\kappa ]^2_{\kappa }$ holds for an arbitrary finite partition p. Similarly, arbitrary finite p-s can be added to stronger symbols which hold in any model of ZFC. If $\kappa ^{\theta }=\kappa $ , then $\kappa \nrightarrow _p[\kappa ]^2_{\kappa }$ and stronger symbols, like $\operatorname {Pr}_1(\kappa ,\kappa ,\kappa ,\chi )_p$ or $\operatorname {Pr}_0(\kappa ,\kappa ,\kappa ,\aleph _0)_p$ , also hold for an arbitrary partition p to $\theta $ parts.

The symbols

$$ \begin{gather*} \aleph_1\nrightarrow_p[\aleph_1]^2_{\aleph_1},\;\;\; \aleph_1\nrightarrow_p[\aleph_1\circledast \aleph_1]^2_{\aleph_1},\;\;\; \aleph_0\circledast\aleph_1\nrightarrow_p[1\circledast\aleph_1]^2_{\aleph_1}, \\ \operatorname{Pr}_1(\aleph_1,\aleph_1,\aleph_1,\aleph_0)_p,\;\;\;\text{ and } \;\;\; \operatorname{Pr}_0(\aleph_1,\aleph_1,\aleph_1,\aleph_0)_p \end{gather*} $$
hold for an arbitrary countable partition p under the Continuum Hypothesis and are independent over ZFC $+ \neg $ CH.

Type
Articles
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2021. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of Association for Symbolic Logic

1. Introduction

The theory of strong colorings branched off Ramsey theory in 1933 when Sierpinski constructed a coloring on $[\mathbb R]^2$ that contradicted the uncountable generalization of Ramsey’s theorem. For many years, pair-colorings which keep their range even after they are restricted to all unordered pairs from an arbitrary, sufficiently large set were called “bad”; now they are called “strong.”

Definition 1. Let $\lambda \le \kappa $ be cardinals. A strong $\lambda $ -coloring on $\kappa $ is a function $f:[\kappa ]^2\to \lambda $ such that $\lambda ={\operatorname {ran}}(f\restriction [A]^2)$ for every $A\in [\kappa ]^{\kappa }$ .

By Ramsey’s theorem there are no strong $\lambda $ -colorings on $\omega $ for $\lambda>1$ . Sierpinski constructed a strong two-coloring on the continuum and on $\aleph _1$ .

Assertions of existence of strong colorings with various cardinal parameters are conveniently phrased with partition-calculus symbols. The (negative) square-brackets symbol

$$ \begin{align*} \kappa\nrightarrow[\kappa]^2_{\lambda}, \end{align*} $$

asserts the existence of a strong $\lambda $ -coloring on $\kappa $ . Recall that the symbol for Ramsey’s theorem for pairs,

(1) $$ \begin{align} \omega\to(\omega)^2_n \end{align} $$

reads “for every $f:[\omega ]^2\to n$ there is an infinite subset $A\subseteq \omega $ such that $f\restriction [A]^2$ is constant (omits all colors but one).” The square brackets in place of the rounded ones stand for “omits at least one color”; with the negation on the arrow, the symbol $\kappa \nrightarrow [\kappa ]^2_{\lambda }$ means, then, “not for all colorings $f:[\kappa ]^2\to \lambda $ at least one color can be omitted on $[A]^2$ for some $A\subseteq \kappa $ of cardinality $|A|=\kappa $ .” That is, there exists a strong $\lambda $ -coloring on $\kappa $ .

When $2$ is replaced with some $d>0$ the symbol states the existence of an analogous coloring of unordered d-tuples. As Ramsey’s theorem holds for all finite $d>0$ , strong d-dimensional colorings can also exist only on uncountable cardinals. In what follows we shall address almost exclusively the case $d=2$ .

Definition 2. Given a coloring $f:[\kappa ]^2\to \lambda $ , a set $X\subseteq [\kappa ]^2$ is f -strong if ${\operatorname {ran}} (f\restriction X)={\operatorname {ran}} (f)$ .

The collection of f-strong subsets of $[\kappa ]^2$ is clearly upwards closed and not necessarily closed under intersections.

Different square-bracket symbols require that different families of sets are f-strong with respect to the coloring f whose existence each symbol asserts. The symbol above asserts the existence of f such that every $\kappa $ -square, that is, every $[A]^2$ for some $A\in [\kappa ]^{\kappa }$ , is f-strong. A $(\lambda ,\kappa )$ -rectangle in $[\kappa ]^2$ is a set of the form $A\circledast B= \{\{\alpha ,\beta \}: \alpha <\beta <\kappa , \; \alpha \in A \text { and } \beta \in B\}$ . Every $\kappa $ -square contains a $(\mu _1,\mu _2)$ -rectangle if $\mu _1\le \mu _2\le \kappa $ ; the symbol

$$ \begin{align*} \kappa\nrightarrow [\mu_1\circledast\mu_2]^2_{\lambda},\end{align*} $$

which asserts the existence of $f:[\kappa ]^2\to \lambda $ such that every $(\mu _1,\mu _2)$ -rectangle $A\circledast B\subseteq [\kappa ]^2$ is f-strong, is, then, stronger than $\kappa \nrightarrow [\kappa ]^2_{\lambda }$ .

The next two strong-coloring symbols go beyond specifying which sets ought to be f-strong. They require the existence of certain patterns in the preimage of each color.

Definition 3.

  1. (1) A coloring $f:[\kappa ]^2\to \lambda $ witnesses the symbol

    $$ \begin{align*} \operatorname{Pr}_1(\kappa,\mu,\lambda,\chi) \end{align*} $$
    if for every $\xi <\chi $ and a pairwise disjoint family $\mathcal A\subseteq [\kappa ]^{<\xi }$ of cardinality $|\mathcal A|=\mu $ and color $\unicode{x3b3} <\lambda $ there are $a,b\in \mathcal A$ with $\max a< \min b$ such that $f(\alpha ,\beta )=\unicode{x3b3} $ for all $\alpha \in a$ and $\beta \in b$ . The quantified $\xi $ above is needed only in the case that $\chi \ge {\operatorname {cf}}(\kappa )$ , which received attention very recently. When $\chi <{\operatorname {cf}}(\kappa )$ we omit $\xi $ from the definition and require only that $A\subseteq [\kappa ]^{<\chi }$ instead.
  2. (2) A coloring $f:[\kappa ]^2\to \lambda $ witnesses the symbol

    $$ \begin{align*} \operatorname{Pr}_0(\kappa,\mu,\lambda,\chi) \end{align*} $$
    if for every $\xi <\chi $ , a pairwise disjoint family $\mathcal A\subseteq [\kappa ]^{\xi }$ of cardinality $|\mathcal A|=\mu $ and a matrix $\{\unicode{x3b3} _{i,j}:i,j<\xi \}\subseteq \lambda $ there are $a,b\in \mathcal A$ with $\max a< \min b$ such that $f(\alpha (i),\beta (j))=\unicode{x3b3} _{i,j}$ for all $i,j<\xi $ , where $a(i),b(j)$ are the $i^{\text {th}}$ and $j^{\text {th}}$ elements of a and of b, respectively, in increasing order.

For $\chi>2$ and $\mu \ge \aleph _0$ , $\operatorname {Pr}_1(\kappa ,\mu ,\lambda ,\chi )$ implies $\kappa \nrightarrow [\mu ]^2_{\lambda }$ (see 8 below). If $\chi < {\operatorname {cf}}(\mu )$ then $\operatorname {Pr}_0(\kappa ,\mu ,\lambda ,\chi )$ implies $\operatorname {Pr}_1(\kappa ,\mu ,\lambda ,\chi )$ .

Let us conclude the introduction with the remark that some authors use the term “strong coloring” only for colorings which witness $\operatorname {Pr}_1$ or a stronger symbol.

2 A brief history of strong colorings

Strong $\kappa $ -colorings on various cardinals $\kappa $ were constructed by Erdős, Hajnál, Milner and Rado in the 1950s and 1960s from instances of the GCH. For every cardinal $\kappa $ they were able to construct from $2^{\kappa }=\kappa ^+$ colorings $f:[\kappa ^+]^2\to \kappa ^+$ which witnessed

$$ \begin{align*} \kappa^+\nrightarrow [\kappa\circledast \kappa^+]^2_{\kappa^+},\end{align*} $$

and even colorings which witnesses the stronger

whose meaning is that inside every $(\kappa ,\kappa ^+)$ -rectangle $A\circledast B\subseteq \kappa ^+$ there is a $(1,\kappa ^+)$ -rectangle $\{\alpha \}\circledast B\subseteq A\circledast B$ such that ${\operatorname {ran}} (f\restriction (\{\alpha \}\circledast B))=\kappa ^+$ (see Section 49 in [Reference Erdős, Hajnal, Máté and Rado5]). A coloring $f[\kappa ^+]^2\to \kappa ^+$ witnesses this symbol if and only if for every $B\in [\kappa ^+]^{\kappa ^+}$ , for all but fewer than $\kappa $ ordinals $\alpha <\kappa ^+$ the full range $\kappa ^+$ is attained by f on the set $\{\alpha \}\circledast B=\{\{\alpha ,\beta \}:\alpha <\beta \in B\}$ .

Galvin [Reference Galvin15], who was motivated by the problem of productivity of chain conditions and by earlier work of Laver, used $2^{\kappa }=\kappa ^+$ to obtain a new class of two-colorings, which in modern notation witness $\operatorname {Pr}_1(\kappa ^+,\kappa ^+,2,\aleph _0)$ , and used these colorings for constructing counter examples to the productivity of the $\kappa ^+$ -chain condition. A straightforward modification of Galvin’s proof actually gives $\operatorname {Pr}_1(\kappa ^+,\kappa ^+,\kappa ^+,\aleph _0)$ on all successor cardinals from $2^{\kappa }=\kappa ^+$ .

A remarkable breakthrough in the theory of strong colorings was the invention of the method of ordinal-walks by Todorčević [Reference Todorčević41] (or, as it was originally called, minimal walks). Todorčević applied his method to construct strong colorings on all successors of regulars in ZFC with no additional axioms. With the same method Todorčević [Reference Todorčević43] got in ZFC the square bracket symbol for triples $\omega _2\nrightarrow [\omega _1]^3_{\omega }$ and proved that $\omega _2\nrightarrow [\omega _1]^2_{\omega _1}$ is equivalent to the negation of the $(\aleph _2,\aleph _1)$ Chang conjecture. The rectangular symbol $\kappa ^+\nrightarrow [\kappa ^+\circledast \kappa ^+]^2_{\kappa ^+}$ has been obtained since in ZFC on all succesors of uncountable regular cardinals $\kappa $ by Shelah via further developments of ordinal-walks. Moore [Reference Moore20] developed ordinal-walks further and provided the missing $\kappa ^+=\aleph _1$ case. Rinot and Todorčević [Reference Rinot and Todorčević28] present a unified proof of the rectangle version for all successors of regulars with a completely arithmetic oscillation function.

Shelah, following Galvin [Reference Galvin15], phrased the strong coloring relations $\operatorname {Pr}_1(\kappa ,\mu ,\lambda ,\chi )$ and $\operatorname {Pr}_0(\kappa ,\mu ,\lambda ,\chi )$ (and a few more!) and proved $\operatorname {Pr}_1(\kappa ^{++},\kappa ^{++},\kappa ^{++},\kappa )$ for every regular $\kappa $ in ZFC [Reference Shelah34]. Shelah also proved a criterion for stepping up from $\operatorname {Pr}_1$ to $\operatorname {Pr}_0$ : if $\operatorname {Pr}_1(\kappa ,\kappa ,\lambda ,\chi )$ holds, $\lambda =\lambda ^{<\chi }$ and there is some “interpolant” cardinal $\rho $ such that $\rho ^{<\chi }\le \lambda $ , $2^{\rho }\ge \kappa $ and ${\operatorname {cf}}(\kappa )>\rho ^{<\chi }$ , then $\operatorname {Pr}_0(\kappa ,\kappa ,\lambda ,\chi )$ holds (Lemma 4.5(3), p. 170 of [Reference Shelah38]). In particular, chosing $\rho =\lambda $ as the interpolant, $\operatorname {Pr}_1(\lambda ^+,\lambda ^+,\lambda ^+,\aleph _0)\Rightarrow \operatorname {Pr}_0(\lambda ^+,\lambda ^+,\lambda ^+,\aleph _0)$ for every cardinal $\lambda $ ; so for all regular cardinals $\kappa $ , $\operatorname {Pr}_0(\kappa ^{++},\kappa ^{++},\kappa ^{++},\aleph _0)$ holds in ZFC ( $\operatorname {Pr}_1(\aleph _1,\aleph _1,3,\aleph _0)$ cannot hold in ZFC because under MA the product of two ccc spaces is ccc). See the survey in [Reference Rinot25] for more background on strong colorings and non-productivity of chain conditions.

On successors of singulars, Todorčević [Reference Todorčević41] proved that the pcf assumption $\operatorname {pp}(\mu )=\mu ^+$ for a singular $\mu $ implies $\mu ^+\nrightarrow [\mu ^+]^2_{\mu ^+}$ . Shelah proved $\operatorname {Pr}_1(\mu ^+,\mu ^+,{\operatorname {cf}}(\mu ),{\operatorname {cf}}(\mu ))$ for every singular $\mu $ (4.1 p. 67 of [Reference Shelah38]). Eisworth [Reference Eisworth9] proved $\operatorname {Pr}_1(\mu ^+\mu ^+,\mu ^+,{\operatorname {cf}}(\mu ))$ from $\operatorname {pp}(\mu )=\mu ^+$ . Then Rinot, building on Eisworth’s [Reference Eisworth9Reference Eisworth10], proved that for every singular $\mu $ , $\operatorname {Pr}_1(\mu ^+,\mu ^+,\mu ^+,{\operatorname {cf}}(\mu ))$ holds iff $\mu ^+\nrightarrow [\mu ^+]^2_{\mu ^+}$ holds. In particular, via Shelah’s criterion, $\operatorname {Pr}_0(\mu ^+,\mu ^+,\mu ^+,\aleph _0)\iff \mu ^+\nrightarrow [\mu ^+]^2_{\mu ^+}$ for all singular $\mu $ [Reference Rinot23]. Quite recently, Peng and Wu proved in [Reference Peng and Wu21] that $\operatorname {Pr}_0(\aleph _1,\aleph _1,\aleph _1,n)$ holds for all $n<\omega $ outright in ZFC.

The most recent progress on strong colorings is made in a series of papers by Rinot and his collaborators. The result in [Reference Rinot24], shown to be optimal in Theorem 3.4 in [Reference Lambie-Hanson and Rinot19], establishes the property $\operatorname {Pr}_1(\lambda ,\lambda ,\lambda ,\chi )$ for regular $\lambda>\chi ^+$ from a non-reflecting stationary subset of $\lambda $ composed of ordinals of cofinality $\ge \chi $ (using a new oscillation function called $\operatorname {P\ell }_6$ ). In [Reference Rinot25], Rinot gets the same result from $\square (\lambda )$ , thus establishing that if $\lambda ={\operatorname {cf}}(\lambda )>\aleph _1$ and the $\lambda $ -chain condition is productive, then $\lambda $ is weakly compact in L. Then Rinot and Zhang prove in [Reference Rinot and Zhang29] that for every regular cardinal $\kappa $ , $2^{\kappa }=\kappa ^+$ implies $\operatorname {Pr}_1(\kappa ^+,\kappa ^+,\kappa ^+,\kappa )$ and for every inaccessible $\lambda $ such that $\square (\lambda )$ and $\diamondsuit ^*(\lambda )$ both hold, $\operatorname {Pr}_1(\lambda ,\lambda ,\lambda ,\lambda )$ holds as well (this is the case in which our remark about $\xi $ at the end of (1) of Definition 3 is relevant). In the other direction it is proved in [Reference Rinot and Zhang29] that $\operatorname {Pr}_1(\kappa ^+,\kappa ^+,2,\kappa )$ fails for every singular cardinal $\kappa $ and that $\operatorname {Pr}_1(\kappa ^+,\kappa ^+,2,{\operatorname {cf}}(\kappa )^+)$ fails for a singular limit $\kappa $ of strongly compact cardinals.

Ramsey’s theorem prohibits the existence of strong colorings with more than one color on countable sets for which all infinite subsets are strong, but in topological partition theory, strong colorings may exist also on countable spaces. Baumgartner [Reference Baumgartner3], following some unpublished work by Galvin, constructed a coloring $c:[\mathbb Q]^2\to \omega $ which attains all colors on every homeomorphic copy of $\mathbb Q$ . Todorčević [Reference Todorčević44] obtained the rectangular version of Baumgartner’s result and very recently, Raghavan and Todorčević [Reference Raghavan and Todorčević22] proved that if a Woodin cardinal exists then for every natural number $k>2$ , for every coloring $c:[\mathbb R]^2\to k$ there is homeomorphic copy of $\mathbb Q$ in $\mathbb R$ on which at most two colors occur, confirming thus a conjecture of Galvin from the 1970s. They also proved that any regular topological space of cardinality $\aleph _n$ admits a coloring of $(n+2)$ -tuples which attains all $\omega $ colors on every subspace which is homeomorphic to $\mathbb Q$ .

3 Strong-coloring symbols over partitions

We introduce now the main new notion of symbols with an additional parameter p, where p is a partition of unordered pairs. Suppose $p:[\kappa ]^2\to \theta $ is a partition of unordered pairs from $\kappa $ . A preliminary definition of the square brackets symbol $\kappa \nrightarrow _p[\kappa ]^2_{\kappa }$ with parameter p has been mentioned in the abstract: there exists a coloring $f:[\kappa ]^2\to \kappa $ such that for every $A\in [\kappa ]^{\kappa }$ there is some p-cell $i<\theta $ such that for all $\unicode{x3b3} <\kappa $ there is $\{\alpha ,\beta \}\in [A]^2$ such that $p(\alpha ,\beta )=i$ and $f(\alpha ,\beta )=\unicode{x3b3} $ .

However, for $\operatorname {Pr}_1$ or for $\operatorname {Pr}_0$ it is not possible to require a prescribed pattern on $a\circledast b$ in both f and p when $a,b$ belong to an arbitrary $\mathcal A$ , as all such $a\circledast b$ might meet more than one p-cell. What we do, then, is replace this definition by a different one. The new definition is equivalent to the initial definition in all square-bracket symbols by Fact 5 below, and works for $\operatorname {Pr}_1$ and $\operatorname {Pr}_0$ .

Definition 4. Suppose $f:[\kappa ]^d\to \lambda $ is a coloring and $p:[\kappa ]^d\to \theta $ is a partition for a cardinal $\kappa $ and natural $d>0$ . Then:

  1. (1) For a function $\zeta :\theta \to \lambda $ and $\overline \alpha \in [\kappa ]^d$ we say that $f \text { hits } \zeta \text { over } p \text { at } \overline \alpha $ , if $f(\overline \alpha )=\zeta (p(\overline \alpha ))$ .

  2. (2) A set $X\subseteq [\kappa ]^d$ is $(f,p)$ -strong if for every $\zeta \in \lambda ^{\theta }$ there is $\overline \alpha \in X$ such that f hits $\zeta $ over p at $\overline \alpha $ .

Thus, the initial definition of an $(f,p)$ -strong $X\subseteq [\kappa ]^d$ — that $(X\cap p^{-1}(i))$ is f-strong for some fixed p-cell i—is replaced in (2) above with the requirement that every assignment of colors to p-cells $\zeta :\theta \to \lambda $ is hit by some $\overline d\in X$ . The advantage of the new definition is that an assignment $\zeta $ can be hit in any p-cell, so defining $\operatorname {Pr}_1$ and $\operatorname {Pr}_0$ over a partition will now make sense.

Topologically, a set $X\subseteq [\kappa ]^d$ is $(f,p)$ -strong iff the collection $\{u_{\langle p(\overline \alpha ),f(\overline \alpha )\rangle }:\overline \alpha \in X\}$ is an open cover of the space $\lambda ^{\theta }$ of all $\theta $ -sequences over $\lambda $ with the product topology, where $u_{\langle i,\unicode{x3b3} \rangle }$ is the basic open set $\{\zeta \in \lambda ^{\theta }: \zeta (i)=\unicode{x3b3} \}$ .

The definitions of the main symbols over partitions which we shall work with are in Definition 7 below; an impatient reader can proceed there directly. We precede this definition with two useful facts about $(f,p)$ -strong sets.

If $X\subseteq [\kappa ]^d$ is $(f,p)$ -strong then for every $\unicode{x3b3} <\lambda $ there is $\overline \alpha \in X$ such that $f(\overline \alpha )=\unicode{x3b3} $ since if $\zeta $ is the constant sequence with value $\unicode{x3b3} $ and $\overline \alpha \in X$ is such that $f(\overline \alpha )=\zeta (p(\overline \alpha ))$ then $f(\overline \alpha )=\unicode{x3b3} $ . This also follows from the next fact:

Fact 5. A set $X\subseteq [\kappa ]^d$ is $(f,p)$ -strong if and only if there is some $i<\theta $ such that $\lambda ={\operatorname {ran}} (f\restriction (X\cap p^{-1}(i)))$ .

Proof Suppose first that that $i<\theta $ is fixed so that $\lambda ={\operatorname {ran}} (f\restriction (X\cap p^{-1}(i)))$ . Let $\zeta \in \lambda ^{\theta }$ be arbitrary and let $\unicode{x3b3} =\zeta (i)$ . Fix some $\overline \alpha \in X$ such that $f(\overline \alpha )=\unicode{x3b3} $ and $p(\overline \alpha )=i$ . Now $f(\overline \alpha )=\zeta (p(\overline \alpha ))$ as required.

For the other direction suppose to the contrary that for every $i<\lambda $ there is some $\zeta (i)\in (\lambda \setminus {\operatorname {ran}}(f\restriction X))$ . Since X is $(f,p)$ -strong, find $\overline \alpha \in X$ such that f hits $\zeta $ over p at $\overline \alpha $ . Let $i=p(\overline \alpha )$ . Now $f(\overline \alpha )=\zeta (i)\notin {\operatorname {ran}} (f\restriction X)$ —a contradiction. ⊣

Suppose that $h:[\kappa ]^d\to \lambda ^{<\mu }$ is some function into sequences of length $<\mu $ . For every partition $p:[\kappa ]^d\to \theta $ for some $\theta <\mu $ , let $h_p:[\kappa ]^d\to \lambda \cup \{*\}$ be defined by

$$ \begin{align*} h_p(\overline \alpha)= \begin{cases} h(\overline\alpha)(p(\overline\alpha)) & \text{ if } p(\overline\alpha)\in {\operatorname {dom}\,}(h(\overline\alpha)),\\ * & \text{ otherwise.} \end{cases} \end{align*} $$

Then for every $\overline \alpha \in [\kappa ]^d$ , if $h_p(\overline \alpha )\neq *$ then $h_p$ hits $h(\overline \alpha )$ over p at $\overline \alpha $ . In particular, every $X\subseteq [\kappa ]^d$ which is h-strong is also $(h_p,p)$ -strong for every partition p of $[\kappa ]^d$ to $\theta <\mu $ cells. A simple book-keeping argument can waive the dependence of $h_p$ on p for a set of $\le \lambda ^{<\mu }$ partitions:

Lemma 6. Suppose $h:[\kappa ]^d\to \lambda ^{<\mu }$ is given and $\overline p=\langle p_{\delta }:\delta <\lambda ^{<\mu }\rangle $ is a sequence such that $p_{\delta }:[\kappa ]^d\to \theta _{\delta }$ and $\theta _{\delta }<\mu $ for all $\delta <\lambda ^{<\mu }$ . Then there is a single coloring $f:[\kappa ]^d\to \lambda $ such that for all $X\subseteq [\kappa ]^d$ , if X is h-strong then X is $(f,p_{\delta })$ -strong for all $\delta <\lambda ^{<\mu }$ .

Proof Suppose $h:[\kappa ]^d\to \lambda ^{<\mu }$ and $\overline p=\langle p_{\delta }:\delta <\lambda ^{<\mu }\rangle $ are given, where $p_{\delta }:[\kappa ]^d\to \theta _{\delta }$ and $\theta _{\delta }<\mu $ for every $\delta <\lambda ^{<\mu }$ .

Let $R=\bigcup \{\{\delta \}\times \lambda ^{\theta _{\delta }}:\delta <\lambda ^{<\mu }\}$ . As $|R|=\lambda ^{<\mu }$ , we may fix a bijection $t:\lambda ^{<\mu }\to R$ and let $g=t\circ h$ . So $g:[\kappa ]^d\to R$ and every $X\subseteq [\kappa ]^d$ is g-strong iff it is h-strong.

Define $f:[\kappa ]^d\to \lambda $ by

$$ \begin{align*} f(\overline\alpha)= \zeta(i) \text{ if } g(\overline\alpha)=\langle \delta,\zeta\rangle \text{ and } p_{\delta}(\overline\alpha)=i. \end{align*} $$

Let $X\subseteq [\kappa ]^d$ be given and assume that X is h-strong. Let $\delta <\lambda ^{<\mu }$ and some desirable $\zeta \in \lambda ^{\theta _{\delta }}$ be given. As X is h-strong, it is also g-strong, so fix ${\overline \alpha }\in X$ such that $g(\overline \alpha )=\langle \delta ,\zeta \rangle $ . Now it holds by the definition of f that $f(\overline \alpha )=\zeta (p_{\delta }(\overline \alpha ))$ , that is f hits $\zeta $ over $p_{\delta }$ at $\overline \alpha \in X$ .⊣

We define now the main symbols over a partition. We state only the case for pairs. The definitions of the square-bracket symbols for $d\neq 2$ are similar.

Definition 7. Suppose $p:[\kappa ]^2\to \theta $ is a partition of all unordered pairs from a cardinal $\kappa $ .

  1. (1) The symbol

    $$ \begin{align*} \kappa\nrightarrow_p[\mu]^2_{\lambda} \end{align*} $$
    asserts the existence of a coloring $f:[\kappa ]^2\to \lambda $ such that for all $A\in [\kappa ]^{\mu }$ , for every $\zeta \in \lambda ^{\theta }$ there is $\{ \alpha ,\beta \}\in [A]^2$ such that $f(\alpha , \beta )=\zeta (p(\alpha ,\beta ))$ .
  2. (2) The symbol

    $$ \begin{align*} \kappa\nrightarrow_p[\mu_1\circledast\mu_2]^2_{\lambda} \end{align*} $$
    asserts the existence of a coloring $f:[\kappa ]^2\to \lambda $ such that for all $A\in [\kappa ]^{\mu _1}$ and $B\in [\kappa ]^{\mu _2}$ , for every $\zeta \in \lambda ^{\theta }$ there is $\{\alpha ,\beta \}\in A\circledast B$ such that $f( \alpha ,\beta )=\zeta (p(\alpha ,\beta ))$ .
  3. (3) The symbol

    $$ \begin{align*}\operatorname{Pr}_1(\kappa,\mu,\lambda,\chi)_p\end{align*} $$
    asserts the existence of a coloring $f:[\kappa ]^2\to \lambda $ such that for every $\xi <\chi $ and a family $\mathcal A\subseteq [\kappa ]^{<\xi }$ of pairwise disjoint nonempty subsets of $\kappa $ such that $|\mathcal A|=\mu $ , for every $\zeta \in \lambda ^{\theta }$ there are $a,b\in \mathcal A$ such that $\max a<\min b$ and $f(\alpha ,\beta )=\zeta (p(\alpha ,\beta ))$ for all $\{\alpha ,\beta \}\in a\circledast b$ .
  4. (4) The symbol

    $$ \begin{align*} \operatorname{Pr}_0(\kappa,\mu,\lambda,\chi)_p\end{align*} $$
    asserts the existence of a coloring $f:[\kappa ]^2\to \lambda $ such that for every $\xi <\chi $ , a pairwise disjoint family $\mathcal A\subseteq [\kappa ]^{\xi }$ of cardinality $|\mathcal A|=\mu $ and a matrix $\{\zeta _{i,j}:i,j<\xi \}\subseteq \lambda ^{\theta }$ there are $a,b\in \mathcal A$ with $\max a< \min b$ such that $f(a(i),b(j))=\zeta _{i,j}(p(a(i),b(j))$ for all $i,j<\xi $ , where $a(i),b(j)$ are the $i^{\text {th}}$ and $j^{\text {th}}$ elements of a and of b, respectively, in increasing order. If $\chi < {\operatorname {cf}}(\mu )$ then $\operatorname {Pr}_0(\kappa ,\mu ,\lambda ,\chi )_p$ implies $\operatorname {Pr}_1(\kappa ,\mu ,\lambda ,\chi )_p$ .
  5. (5) Suppose $\overline p=\langle p_{\delta }:\delta <\delta (*)\rangle $ is a sequence of partitions $p_{\delta }:[\kappa ]^2\to \theta _{\delta }$ . In each of the four symbols above, writing $\overline p$ instead of p means there exists a single coloring which witnesses simultaneously the relation with $p_{\delta }$ in place of p for each $\delta <\delta (*)$ .

By Fact 5, the first two symbols are equivalently defined by requiring that for every $X\subseteq [\kappa ]^2$ which is a $\mu $ -square or is a $(\mu _1,\mu _2)$ -rectangle there is a single cell $i<\theta $ (which depends on X) such that $X\cap p^{-1}(i)$ is f-strong.

Fact 8. Suppose $\kappa \ge \mu \ge \lambda $ are cardinals. Then every coloring f which witnesses $\operatorname {Pr}_1(\kappa ,\mu ,\lambda ,3)_p$ witnesses also $\kappa \nrightarrow _p[\mu \circledast \mu ]^2_{\lambda }$ . In particular,

$$ \begin{align*} \operatorname{Pr}_1(\kappa,\mu,\lambda,3)_p \,\,\, \Rightarrow \,\,\, \kappa\nrightarrow_p[\mu\circledast \mu]^2_{\lambda}\end{align*} $$

for every partition $p:[\kappa ]^2\to \theta $ .

Proof Fix $f:[\kappa ]^2\to \lambda $ which witnesses $\operatorname {Pr}_1(\kappa ,\mu ,\lambda ,3)_p$ . Let $A\circledast B\subseteq [\kappa ]^2$ be an arbitrary $(\mu ,\mu )$ -rectangle. Find inductively a pair-wise disjoint $\mathcal A=\{a_i:i<\mu \}\subseteq A\circledast B$ . Given some $\zeta \in \lambda ^{\theta }$ , fix $a=\{\alpha, \beta \}$ and $b=\{\unicode{x3b3},\, \delta \}$ from $\mathcal A$ such that $\alpha <\beta <\unicode{x3b3} <\delta $ and such that f hits $\zeta $ over p at all (four) elements $\{x,y\}\in a\circledast b$ . In particular, f hits $\zeta $ over p at $\{\alpha,\,\delta \}$ which belongs to $A\circledast B$ . ⊣

The next lemma is the main tool for adding a partition parameter to a strong-coloring symbol.

Lemma 9. Suppose $\kappa \ge \mu \ge \lambda \ge \rho $ are cardinals. Then for every sequence of partitions $\overline p=\langle p_{\delta }:\delta <\lambda ^{<\rho }\rangle $ in which $p_{\delta }:[\kappa ]^2\to \theta _{\delta }$ and $\theta _{\delta }<\rho $ for $\delta <\lambda ^{<\rho }$ :

  1. (1)

    $$ \begin{align*} \\[-40pt] \kappa\nrightarrow [\mu]^2_{\lambda^{<\rho}} \;\;\;\Rightarrow\;\;\; \kappa\nrightarrow_{\overline p}[\mu]^2_{\lambda}.\end{align*} $$
  2. (2) For all $\mu '\le \mu $ ,

    $$ \begin{align*}\kappa\nrightarrow [\mu'\circledast \mu]^2_{\lambda^{<\rho}}\;\;\;\Rightarrow\;\;\; \kappa\nrightarrow_{\overline p} [\mu'\circledast \mu]^2_{\lambda}.\end{align*} $$
  3. (3)

  4. (4) For all $\chi>0$ ,

    $$ \begin{align*}\operatorname{Pr}_0(\kappa,\mu,\lambda^{<\rho},\chi)\;\;\;\Rightarrow\;\;\; \operatorname{Pr}_0(\kappa,\mu,\lambda,\chi)_{\overline p}.\end{align*} $$
  5. (5) For all $\chi>0$ ,

    $$ \begin{align*}\operatorname{Pr}_1(\kappa,\mu,\lambda^{<\rho},\chi)\;\;\;\Rightarrow\;\;\; \operatorname{Pr}_1(\kappa,\mu,\lambda,\chi)_{\overline p}.\end{align*} $$

Proof Given any of the first three symbols in the hypotheses above, fix a coloring $h:[\kappa ]^2\to \lambda ^{<\rho }$ which witnesses it. Suppose $\overline p=\langle p_{\delta }:\delta <\lambda ^{<\rho }\rangle $ is given, where $p_{\delta }:[\kappa ]^2\to \theta _{\delta }$ and $\theta _{\delta }<\rho $ for every $\delta <\lambda ^{<\rho }$ .

By Lemma 6 fix $f:[\kappa ]^2\to \lambda $ such that every $X\subseteq [\kappa ]^2$ which is h-strong is also $(f,p_{\delta })$ -strong for all $\delta <\lambda ^{<\rho }$ . Let $\delta <\lambda ^{<\rho }$ be arbitrary. Suppose that $X\subseteq [\kappa ]^2$ is some $\mu $ -square $[A]^2$ or X is some $(\mu ',\mu )$ -rectangle $A\circledast B$ . Then X is $(f,p_{\delta })$ -strong. This proves the first two implications. For the third, let $A\circledast B$ be some $(\kappa ,\kappa ^+)$ -rectangle. By the hypothesis, there is some $\alpha \in A$ such that $\{\alpha \}\circledast B$ is h-strong, hence it is also $(f,p_{\delta })$ -strong.

To prove the fourth implication, let, as in the proof of Lemma 6, $R=\bigcup \bigl \{\{\delta \}\times \lambda ^{\theta _{\delta }}:\delta <\lambda ^{<\rho }\bigr \}$ , let $g:[\kappa ]^2\to R$ witness $\operatorname {Pr}_0(\kappa ,\mu ,\lambda ^{<\rho },\chi )$ and let $f(\alpha ,\beta )=\zeta (p_{\delta }(\alpha ,\beta ))$ when $g(\alpha ,\beta )=\langle \delta ,\zeta \rangle $ . Suppose $\xi <\chi $ and $\mathcal A\subseteq [\kappa ]^{\xi }$ is pair-wise disjoint and $|\mathcal A|=\mu $ . Given any $\delta <\lambda ^{<\rho }$ and $\{\zeta _{i,j}:i,j<\xi \}\subseteq \lambda ^{\theta _{\delta }}$ , use the fact g witnesses $\operatorname {Pr}_0(\kappa ,\mu ,\lambda ^{<\rho },\chi )$ to fix $a,b\in \mathcal A$ such that $\max a<\min b$ and $f(\alpha (i),\beta (j))=\langle \delta ,\zeta _{i,j}\rangle $ for all $i,j<\xi $ , where $a(i)$ and $b(j)$ are the $i^{\text {th}}$ and $j^{\text {th}}$ members of a and of b respectively. Now $f(a(i),b(j))=\zeta _{i,j}(p_{\delta }(a(i),b(j))$ as required.

The proof of the last implication is gotten from the fourth by using constant $\zeta _{i,j}=\zeta $ . ⊣

4 Valid symbols over partitions in ZFC and in ZFC with additional axioms

Question 10. Suppose $\kappa \ge \rho $ are cardinals. Which strong-coloring symbols in $\kappa $ hold over all $<\rho $ partitions?

Clearly, every coloring which witnesses a strong-coloring symbol $\Phi $ over some partition p, witnesses the symbol gotten by deleting p from $\Phi $ . The question of existence of strong colorings over partition therefore refines the question of existence of strong colorings in the classical sense.

Let us mention two obvious constraints on obtaining strong-coloring symbols over partitions. Given any coloring $f:[\kappa ]^2\to \lambda $ with $\lambda \ge 2$ , let us define, for $\alpha <\beta <\kappa $ , $p(\alpha ,\beta )=0\iff f(\alpha ,\beta )=0$ and $p(\alpha ,\beta )=1$ otherwise. Then f does not witness $\kappa \nrightarrow _p [\kappa ]^2_{\lambda }$ . Hence:

Fact 11. No single coloring witnesses $\kappa \nrightarrow _p [\kappa ]^2_{\lambda }$ for all two-partitions p if $\lambda>1$ .

If $\theta \ge {\operatorname {cf}}(\kappa )$ then there is a partition $p:[\kappa ]^2\to \theta $ with $|p^{-1}(i)|<\kappa $ for every $i<\theta $ , so $\kappa \nrightarrow _p[\kappa ]^2_{\kappa }$ cannot hold. This narrows down the discussion of $\kappa \nrightarrow _p[\kappa ]^2_{\kappa }$ to partitions $p:[\kappa ^2]\to \theta $ with $\theta <{\operatorname {cf}}(\kappa )$ .

4.1 Symbols which are valid in ZFC

Every infinite cardinal $\lambda $ satisfies $\lambda ^{<\aleph _0}=\lambda $ . Therefore, by Lemma 9, every symbol with $\lambda \ge \aleph _0$ colors which holds in ZFC continues to hold in ZFC over any sequence of length $\lambda $ of finite partitions.

Let us state ZFC symbols over partitions whose classical counterparts were mentioned in §2 above:

Theorem 12. For every regular cardinal $\kappa $ and a sequence of length $\kappa ^+$ of finite partitions of $[\kappa ^+]^2$ ,

$$ \begin{align*} \kappa^+\nrightarrow_{\overline p}[\kappa^+\circledast \kappa^+]^2_{\kappa^+}. \end{align*} $$

Proof The symbol without $\overline p$ holds by the results of Todorčević, Moore and Shelah. Now apply Lemma 9(1). ⊣

In particular,

Corollary 13. For every finite partition $p:[\omega _1]^2\to n$ ,

$$ \begin{align*} \omega_1\nrightarrow_p [\omega_1\circledast \omega_1]^2_{\omega_1} \;\;\; \text{ and } \;\;\; \omega_1\nrightarrow_p[\omega_1]^2_{\omega_1}. \end{align*} $$

Theorem 14. For every sequence of length $\omega _2$ of finite partitions of $[\omega _2]^3$ ,

$$ \begin{align*} \omega_2\nrightarrow_{\overline p}[\omega_1]^3_{\omega}, \end{align*} $$

and $\omega _2\nrightarrow _{\overline p}[\omega _1]^3_{\omega _1}$ is equivalent to the negation of the $(\aleph _2,\aleph _1)$ Chang conjecture.

Proof The symbol $\omega _2\nrightarrow [\omega _1]^3_{\omega }$ holds by Todorevic’s [Reference Todorčević43], and now apply Lemma 6 as in the proof of Lemma 9. ⊣

Theorem 15. For every cardinal $\kappa $ and a list $\overline p$ of length $\kappa ^{++}$ of finite partitions of $[\kappa ^{++}]^2$ ,

$$ \begin{align*} \operatorname{Pr}_1(\kappa^{++},\kappa^{++},\kappa^{++},\kappa)_{\overline p}. \end{align*} $$

Proof By Shelah’s [Reference Shelah34] and Lemma 9(4). ⊣

Theorem 16. For every cardinal $\kappa $ and a list $\overline p$ of length $\kappa ^{++}$ of finite partitions of $[\kappa ^{++}]^2$ ,

$$ \begin{align*} \operatorname{Pr}_0(\kappa^{++},\kappa^{++},\kappa^{++},\aleph_0)_{\overline p}. \end{align*} $$

Proof By Shelah’s [Reference Shelah34], 4.5(3) p. 170 in [Reference Shelah38] and Lemma 9(5). ⊣

Theorem 17. For every singular cardinal $\mu $ and a sequence of length ${\operatorname {cf}}(\mu )$ of finite partitions of $[\mu ^+]^2$ ,

$$ \begin{align*} \operatorname{Pr}_1(\mu^+,\mu^+,{\operatorname {cf}}(\mu),{\operatorname {cf}}(\mu))_{\overline p}.\end{align*} $$

Proof By Shelah’s 4.1 p. 67 of [Reference Shelah38] and Lemma 9(4). ⊣

Theorem 18. For every singular $\mu $ and a sequence $\overline p$ of length $\mu ^+$ of finite partitions of $[\mu ^+]^2$ ,

$$ \begin{align*} \mu^+\nrightarrow[\mu^+]^2_{\mu^+}\Rightarrow \operatorname{Pr}_1(\mu^+,\mu^+,\mu^+,{\operatorname {cf}}(\mu))_{\overline p} \wedge \operatorname{Pr}_0(\mu^+,\mu^+,\mu^+,\aleph_0)_{\overline p}. \end{align*} $$

Proof Suppose $\mu ^+\nrightarrow [\mu ^+]^2_{\mu ^+}$ . By Rinot’s [Reference Rinot23], also $\operatorname {Pr}_1(\mu ^+,\mu ^+,\mu ^+,{\operatorname {cf}}(\mu ))$ holds. The first conjuct now follows by Lemma 9(4). To get the second conjunct observes that by the first conjunct we have in particular $\operatorname {Pr}_1(\mu ^+,\mu ^+,\mu ^+,\aleph _0)$ . The second conjunct follows now by 4.5(3) in [Reference Shelah38] and Lemma 9(5). ⊣

4.2 Symbols from instances of the GCH or of the SCH

If the GCH holds then every regular cardinal $\lambda $ satisfies $\lambda ^{<\lambda }=\lambda $ . Thus,

Theorem 19 GCH

In Theorems (12)-(18) above, “finite partitions” may be replaced by $<\lambda $ -partitions.

The GCH also makes Shelah’s implication 4.5(3) from [Reference Shelah38] valid in additional cases. For example,

Theorem 20 GCH

For every regular cardinal $\kappa $ and a sequence $\overline p$ of length $\kappa ^{++}$ of $\kappa ^+$ -partitions,

$$ \begin{align*} \operatorname{Pr}_0(\kappa^{++},\kappa^{++},\kappa^{++},\kappa)_{\overline p}. \end{align*} $$

Proof By Shelah’s [Reference Shelah34] we have $\operatorname {Pr}_1(\kappa ^{++},\kappa ^{++},\kappa ^{++},\kappa )$ in ZFC. Let $\rho =\kappa ^+$ . By the GCH, $\rho ^{<\kappa }=\rho $ and $(\kappa ^{++})^{<\kappa }=\kappa ^{++}$ , so $\rho $ qualifies as an interpolant in 4.5(3) p. 170 in [Reference Shelah38] and $\operatorname {Pr}_0(\kappa ^{++},\kappa ^{++},\kappa ^{++},\kappa )$ follows. Now use GCH again with Lemma 9(5). ⊣

Theorem 21. For every cardinal $\kappa $ , if $2^{\kappa }=\kappa ^+$ then for every sequence p of length $\kappa ^+$ of $\kappa $ -partitions of $[\kappa ]^2$ ,

Proof The symbol follows from $2^{\kappa }=\kappa ^+$ by the and Erdoős–Hajnal–Milner theorem (see Section 49 in [Reference Erdős, Hajnal, Máté and Rado5]). Use now Lemma 9(2). ⊣

Theorem 22. For every singular cardinal $\mu $ , if $\operatorname {pp}(\mu )=\mu ^+$ then for every sequence $\overline p$ of length $\mu ^+$ of finite partitions of $[\mu ^+]^2$ ,

$$ \begin{align*} \operatorname{Pr}_1(\mu^+,\mu^+,\mu^+,{\operatorname {cf}}(\mu))_{\overline p}. \end{align*} $$

Proof By $\operatorname {pp}(\mu )=\mu ^+$ and Eisworth’s theorem [Reference Eisworth10], $\operatorname {Pr}_1(\mu ^+,\mu ^+,\mu ^+,{\operatorname {cf}}(\mu ))$ holds. Now use Lemma 9(4). ⊣

Theorem 23 GCH

For every singular cardinal $\mu $ and a sequence $\overline p$ of length $\mu ^+$ of $\mu $ -partitions of $[\mu ^+]^2$ ,

$$ \begin{align*} \operatorname{Pr}_0(\mu^+,\mu^+,\mu^+,{\operatorname {cf}}(\mu))_{\overline p}. \end{align*} $$

Proof By Eisworth’s theorem it holds that $\operatorname {Pr}_1(\mu ^+,\mu ^+,\mu ^+,{\operatorname {cf}}(\mu ))$ . By the GCH and Shelah’s 4.5(3) in [Reference Shelah38], also $\operatorname {Pr}_0(\mu ^+,\mu ^+,\mu ^+,{\operatorname {cf}}(\mu ))$ holds. Finally, as $(\mu ^+)^{\mu }=\mu ^+$ , by Lemma 9(5), for every sequence $\overline p$ of length $\mu ^+$ of $\mu $ -partitions of $[\mu ]^+$ it holds that $\operatorname {Pr}_0(\mu ^+,\mu ^+,\mu ^+,{\operatorname {cf}}(\mu ))_{\overline p}$ . ⊣

In the next theorem a different cardinal arithmetic assumption appears:

Theorem 24. If $\mu $ is a singular cardinal and $2^{{\operatorname {cf}}(\mu )}>\mu $ then for every sequence $\overline p$ of length $\mu ^+$ of finite partitions of $[\mu ^+]^2$ ,

$$ \begin{align*} \operatorname{Pr}_0(\mu^+,\mu^+,{\operatorname {cf}}(\mu),\aleph_0)_{\overline p}. \end{align*} $$

Proof By Shelah’s 4.1 p. 67 the symbol $\operatorname {Pr}_1(\mu ^+,\mu ^+,{\operatorname {cf}}(\mu ),{\operatorname {cf}}(\mu ))$ holds in ZFC. Choose $\rho ={\operatorname {cf}}(\mu )$ . So $2^{\rho }\ge \mu ^+$ , $\rho ^{<\aleph _0}=\rho $ and ${\operatorname {cf}}(\mu ^+)>\rho ^{<\aleph _0}$ , so $\rho $ qualifies as an interpolant cardinal in 4.5(3) p. 170 in [Reference Shelah38] and $\operatorname {Pr}_0(\mu ^+,\mu ^+,{\operatorname {cf}}(\mu ),\aleph _0)$ follows. Now use Lemma 9(5). ⊣

Lastly in this section, we show that , an axiom (stated in the proof below), which does not imply $2^{\kappa }=\kappa ^+$ , implies the following rectangular square-brackets symbol.

Theorem 25. If $\kappa $ is a cardinal and

holds then for every sequence of partitions $\overline p=\langle p_{\unicode{x3b3} }:\unicode{x3b3} <\kappa ^+\rangle $ , where $p_{\unicode{x3b3} }:[\kappa ^+]^2\to \lambda _{\unicode{x3b3} }$ and $\lambda _{\unicode{x3b3} }<{\operatorname {cf}}(\kappa )$ for each $\unicode{x3b3} <\kappa ^+$ , it holds that

That is, there exists a coloring $f:[\kappa ^+]^2\to \kappa ^+$ such that for every $(\kappa ^+,\kappa ^+)$ -rectangle $A\circledast B$ and $\unicode{x3b3} <\omega _1$ there is $j<\lambda _{\unicode{x3b3} }$ and $X\in [A]^{\kappa }$ such that

$$ \begin{align*} \kappa^+={\operatorname {ran}} \bigl( f\restriction [(X\circledast B)\cap p_{\unicode{x3b3}}^{-1}(j)] \bigr). \end{align*} $$

Proof Suppose a sequence of partitions $\overline p =\langle p_{\unicode{x3b3} }:\unicode{x3b3} <\kappa ^+\rangle $ is given as above and we shall define the required f assuming . Fix a sequence $\langle X_i:i<\kappa ^+\rangle $ which witnesses , that is: $X_i\subseteq \kappa ^+$ , ${\operatorname {otp}} (X_i)=\kappa $ for each $i<\kappa ^+$ and for every $A\in [\kappa ^+]^{\kappa ^+}$ there exists some $i<\kappa ^+$ such that $X_i\subseteq A$ .

Let $\beta <\kappa ^+$ be arbitrary. Towards defining $f(\alpha ,\beta )$ for $\alpha <\beta $ , let us define, for every triple $\langle \unicode{x3b3} ,i,j\rangle $ such that $\unicode{x3b3} ,i<\beta $ and $j<\lambda _{\unicode{x3b3} }$ ,

(2) $$ \begin{align} A^{\beta}_{\langle \unicode{x3b3},i,j\rangle} = \{\alpha<\beta: \alpha\in X_i \wedge p_{\unicode{x3b3}}(\alpha,\beta)=j\}. \end{align} $$

Let

(3) $$ \begin{align} \mathcal A_{\beta}= \left\{A^{\beta}_{\langle \unicode{x3b3},i,j\rangle}: \unicode{x3b3},i<\beta\wedge j<\lambda_{\unicode{x3b3}} \wedge |A^{\beta}_{\langle \unicode{x3b3},i,j\rangle}|=\kappa\right\}. \end{align} $$

As $\mathcal A_{\beta }$ is a family of at most $\kappa $ subsets of $\beta $ , each of cardinality $\kappa $ , we may fix a disjoint refinement $\mathcal D_{\beta }=\{D^{\beta }_{\langle \unicode{x3b3} ,i,j\rangle }: A^{\beta }_{\langle \unicode{x3b3} ,i,j\rangle }\in \mathcal A_{\beta }\}$ , that is, each $D^{\beta }_{\langle \unicode{x3b3} ,i,j\rangle }\subseteq A^{\beta }_{\langle \unicode{x3b3} ,i,j\rangle }$ has cardinality $\kappa $ and $\langle \unicode{x3b3} ,i,j\rangle \neq\langle \unicode{x3b3} ',i',j'\rangle \Rightarrow D^{\beta }_{\langle \unicode{x3b3} ,i,j \rangle }\cap D^{\beta }_{\langle \unicode{x3b3} ',i',j'\rangle }=\emptyset $ for any $A^{\beta }_{\langle \unicode{x3b3} ,i,j\rangle }, A^{\beta }_{\langle \unicode{x3b3} ',i',j'\rangle }\in \mathcal A_{\beta }$ .

Let us define now $f(\alpha ,\beta )$ for all $\alpha $ below our fixed $\beta $ by cases. For each $D^{\beta }_{\langle \unicode{x3b3} ,i,j\rangle }\in \mathcal D_{\beta }$ define $f\restriction (D^{\beta }_{\langle \unicode{x3b3} ,i,j\rangle }\circledast \{\beta \})$ to be some function onto $\beta $ . This is possible since $| D^{\beta }_{\langle \unicode{x3b3} ,i,j\rangle }|=\kappa $ and $\beta <\kappa ^+$ (so $| D^{\beta }_{\langle \unicode{x3b3} ,i,j\rangle }|=|\beta |$ ) and because the $D^{\beta }_{\langle \unicode{x3b3} ,i,j\rangle }$ are pairwise disjoint, hence $(D^{\beta }_{\langle \unicode{x3b3} ,i,j\rangle } \circledast \{\beta \})\cap (D^{\beta }_{\langle \unicode{x3b3} ',i',j'\rangle }\circledast \{\beta \}) =\emptyset $ when $\langle \unicode{x3b3} ,i,j\rangle \neq\langle \unicode{x3b3} ',i',j'\rangle $ .

For $\alpha \in \beta \setminus \bigcup \mathcal D_{\beta }$ define $f(\alpha ,\beta )$ arbitrarily (say, as $0$ ). As $\beta $ was arbitrary, we have defined $f(\alpha ,\beta )$ for all $\alpha <\beta <\kappa ^+$ . By this definition, for all $\beta <\kappa ^+ $ and $D^{\beta }_{\langle \unicode{x3b3} ,i,j\rangle }\in \mathcal D_{\beta }$ ,

(4) $$ \begin{align} \beta={\operatorname {ran}} (f\restriction (D^{\beta}_{\langle \unicode{x3b3},i,j\rangle}\circledast \{\beta\}). \end{align} $$

To see that f satisfies what Theorem 25 states, let $A,B\subseteq \kappa ^+$ be arbitrary with $|A|=|B|=\kappa ^+$ and let $\unicode{x3b3} <\kappa ^+$ be given. Using the properties of the -sequence, fix some $i<\kappa ^+$ such that

(5) $$ \begin{align} X_i\subseteq A. \end{align} $$

As $X_i\subseteq \kappa ^+$ and ${\operatorname {otp}}(X_i)=\kappa $ , $\mathrm{sup} (X_i)<\kappa ^+$ , hence $\beta _0:=\max \{\unicode{x3b3} ,i,\mathrm{sup} X_i\}<\kappa ^+$ .

If $\beta \in B$ is any ordinal such that $\beta>\beta _0$ then $X_i\subseteq \beta $ and as $|X_i|=\kappa $ while $\lambda _{\unicode{x3b3} }<{\operatorname {cf}}\kappa $ , there exists some $j(\beta )<\lambda _{\unicode{x3b3} }$ such that

$$ \begin{align*} |\{\alpha\in X_i: p_{\unicode{x3b3}}(\alpha,\beta)=j \}|=\kappa,\end{align*} $$

that is, by (2) and (3),

$$ \begin{align*} A^{\beta}_{\langle \unicode{x3b3},i,j(\beta)\rangle}\in \mathcal A_{\beta}. \end{align*} $$

By the regularity of $\kappa ^+$ and the assumption that $\lambda _{\unicode{x3b3} }<{\operatorname {cf}}\kappa <\kappa ^+$ , we can fix some $B'\subseteq B\setminus (\beta _0+1)$ and $j(*)<\lambda _{\unicode{x3b3} }$ such that $j(\beta )=j(*)$ for all $\beta \in B$ .

For each $\beta \in B'$ it holds, then, that $A^{\beta }_{\langle \unicode{x3b3} ,i,j(*)\rangle }$ belongs to $\mathcal A_{\beta }$ , and therefore also

(6) $$ \begin{align} D^{\beta}_{\langle \unicode{x3b3},i,j(*)\rangle}\in \mathcal D_{\beta}. \end{align} $$

Now, for each $\beta \in B'$ we have by (6) and (4) that

$$ \begin{align*} \beta={\operatorname {ran}}(c\restriction D^{\beta}_{\langle \unicode{x3b3},i,j(*)\rangle}\circledast \{\beta\}),\end{align*} $$

and as $D^{\beta }_{\langle \unicode{x3b3} ,i,j(*)\rangle }\subseteq X_i\cap p_{\unicode{x3b3} }^{-1}(j(*))$ by (2),

$$ \begin{align*} \beta={\operatorname{ran}}(f\restriction [(X_i\circledast \{\beta\})\cap p_{\unicode{x3b3}}^{-1}(j(*))]). \end{align*} $$

As $B'\subseteq B$ is unbounded in $\kappa ^+$ it follows, after setting $X=X_i$ and $j=j(*)$ , that

$$ \begin{align*} \kappa^+= f\restriction [(X\circledast B)\cap p_{\unicode{x3b3}}^{-1}(j)]. \end{align*} $$

5 Independence results on $\aleph _1$

In this section we shall show that the existence of strong colorings over countable partitions of $[\omega _1]^2$ is independent over ZFC and over ZFC + $2^{\aleph _0}>\aleph _1$ .

Theorem 26. If the CH holds, then the following five symbols are valid for every sequence of partitions $\overline p=\langle p_{\delta }:\delta <\omega _1\rangle $ where $p_{\delta }:[\omega _1]^2\to \omega $ :

  • $\displaystyle \aleph _1\nrightarrow _{\overline p}[\aleph _1]^2_{\aleph _1},$

  • $\displaystyle \aleph _1\nrightarrow _{\overline p}[\aleph _1\circledast \aleph _1]^2_{\aleph _1},$

  • $\displaystyle \operatorname {Pr}_1(\aleph _1,\aleph _1,\aleph _1,\aleph _0)_{\overline p},$

  • $\displaystyle \operatorname {Pr}_0(\aleph _1,\aleph _1,\aleph _1,\aleph _0)_{\overline p}.$

Proof Assume CH, that is, $2^{\aleph _0}=\aleph _1$ . Then $\operatorname {Pr}_1(\aleph _1,\aleph _1,\aleph _1,\aleph _0)$ holds by (a slight strengthening of) Galvin’s theorem. By Shelah’s 4.5(3) from [Reference Shelah38], also $\operatorname {Pr}_0(\aleph _1,\aleph _1,\aleph _1,\aleph _0)$ holds. The CH also implies that $(\aleph _1)^{\aleph _0}=(2^{\aleph _0})^{\aleph _0}=2^{\aleph _0}=\aleph _1$ . By Lemma 9(5), then, for every $\omega _1$ -sequence $\overline p$ of countable partitions of $[\omega _1]^2$ it holds that

$$ \begin{align*} \operatorname{Pr}_0(\aleph_1,\aleph_1,\aleph_1,\aleph_0)_{\overline p} \end{align*} $$

and therefore by Lemma 8 also

$$ \begin{align*} \operatorname{Pr}_1(\aleph_1,\aleph_1,\aleph_1,\aleph_0)_{\overline p}, \;\;\;\omega_1\nrightarrow_{\overline p}[\omega_1]^2_{\omega_1} \;\;\; \text{ and } \;\;\; \omega_1\nrightarrow_{\overline p}[\omega_1\circledast\omega_1]^2_{\omega_1}.\end{align*} $$

Similarly, by the CH and Theorem 21 in the previous section,

We prove next that these five symbols are valid in all models of ZFC obtained by adding $\aleph _2$ Cohen reals over an arbitrary model V of ZFC, and, more generally, by forcing with a finite-support $\omega _2$ -iteration of $\sigma $ -linked posets over an arbitrary model V of ZFC.

Before proving yet another combinatorial property in a Cohen extension let us recall Roitman’s [Reference Roitman30] proof that the addition of a single Cohen real introduces an S-space, Todorčević’s presentation in [Reference Todorčević42], p. 26 and Rinot’s blog-post [Reference Rinot26] in which it is shown that a single Cohen real introduces $\operatorname {Pr}_0(\aleph _1,\aleph _1,\aleph _0,\aleph _0)$ . For a short proof of Shelah’s theorem that a single Cohen real introduces a Suslin line see [Reference Steprāns40]. Fleissner [Reference Fleissner14] proved that adding $\lambda $ Cohen reals introduces two ccc spaces whose product is not $\lambda $ -cc. Hajnal and Komjath [Reference Hajnal and Komjath17] proved that adding one Cohen subset to a cardinal $\kappa =\kappa ^{<\kappa }$ forces the statement $Q(\kappa ^+)$ they defined, following [Reference Erdős, Galvin and Hajnal4]: for every graph $G=\langle \kappa ^+,E\rangle $ with $\chi (G)=\kappa ^+$ there is a coloring $f:E\to \kappa ^+$ such that for every partition of $\kappa ^+$ to $\kappa $ parts, all colors are gotten by f on edges from a single part. It is still open if $Q(\aleph _1)$ holds in ZFC.

Theorem 27. If $\mathbb C_{\aleph _2}$ is the partial order for adding $\aleph _2$ Cohen reals then for every sequence $\overline p =\langle p_{\delta }:\delta <\omega _1\rangle $ of partitions $p_{\delta }:[\omega _1]^2\to \omega $ in the forcing extension by $\mathbb C_{\aleph _2}$ ,

Proof Let $\mathbb {C}_{\alpha }$ be the partial order of finite partial functions from $[\alpha ]^2$ to $\omega $ . Let V be a model of set theory and let $G\subseteq \mathbb C_{\omega _2}$ be generic over V. Then $\bigcup G:[\omega _2]^2\to \omega $ .

Now suppose that $\overline p=\langle p_{\delta }:\delta <\omega _1\rangle $ is an arbitrary sequence of partitions $p_{\delta }:[\omega _1]^2\to \omega $ in $V[G]$ . As there is some $\alpha \in \omega _2$ such that $\overline p\in V[G\cap \mathbb C_{\alpha }]$ , it may be assumed that $\overline p\in V$ . Let $c= \bigcup G\restriction [\omega _1]^2$ . So $c:[\omega _1]^2\to \omega $ . In V, fix a sequence $\langle e_{\alpha }:\omega \le \alpha <\omega _1\rangle $ , where $e_{\alpha }: \omega \to \alpha $ is a bijection. In the generic extension, define a coloring $f:[\omega _1]^2\to \omega _1$ by

$$ \begin{align*} f(\alpha,\beta)=e_{\beta}(c(\alpha,\beta)),\end{align*} $$

for $\beta \ge \omega $ and as $0$ otherwise.

To see that f witnesses $\displaystyle \aleph _1\nrightarrow _{\overline p}[\aleph _1]^2_{\aleph _1}$ suppose that there is some $\delta<\omega_1$ for which f fails to witness $\displaystyle \aleph _1\nrightarrow _{\overline p}[\aleph _1]^2_{\aleph _1}$ . This means that in $V^G$ there are $A\in [\omega _1]^{\omega }$ and $B\in [\omega _1]^{\omega _1}$ such that for all $\alpha \in A$ there is some $W(\alpha )\in \omega _1^{\omega }$ such that for all $\beta \in B\setminus (\alpha +1)$ it holds that $f(\alpha ,\beta )\neq W(\alpha )(p_{\delta }(\alpha ,\beta ))$ . Let $\dot A$ and $\dot W$ be countable names for A and W and let $\dot B$ be a name for B. Let $r\in G$ decide $\delta $ and force

$$ \begin{align*} r\Vdash_{} ``(\forall \alpha\in \dot A)(\forall \beta\in \dot B\setminus (\alpha+1))\,(f(\alpha,\beta))\neq \dot W(\alpha)(p_{\delta}(\alpha,\beta)).\text{''} \end{align*} $$

Let $\mathfrak M$ be a countable elementary submodel of $H(\omega _2,\dot A, \dot B, \dot {W}, r) $ .

Fix an extension $r'\in G$ of r and an ordinal $\beta \in \omega _1\setminus \mathrm{sup} (\mathfrak M\cap \omega _1)$ such that $r'\Vdash \beta \in \dot B$ . Let $r_0=r'\cap \mathfrak M$ . Inside $\mathfrak M$ extend $r_0$ to $r_1$ such that $r_1\Vdash _{} ``\alpha \in \dot A\text{''}$ for an ordinal $\alpha $ which is not in $\bigcup {\operatorname {dom}\,}(r')$ and $r_1$ decides $W(\alpha )(p_{\delta }(\alpha ,\beta ))$ . Thus, $\{\alpha ,\beta \}\notin {\operatorname {dom}\,}(r'\cup r_1)$ . Let

$$ \begin{align*}r^*=r'\cup r_1\cup \bigl\{\langle \{\alpha,\beta\},e^{-1}_{\beta}(W(\alpha)(p_{\delta}(\alpha,\beta))\rangle\bigr\}. \end{align*} $$

Since $r^*$ extends r and $f(\alpha ,\beta )=e_{\beta }(c(\alpha ,\beta ))=W(\alpha )(p_{\delta }(\alpha ,\beta ))$ , this is a contradiction to the choice of r.⊣

The forcing for adding a single Cohen real is obviously $\sigma $ -linked. Thus, the next theorem applies to a broader class of posets than Cohen forcing. The previous theorem holds also in this generality.

Theorem 28. If $\mathbb P$ is an $\omega _2$ -length finite support iteration of $\sigma $ -linked partial orders then

$$ \begin{align*} 1\Vdash_{\mathbb P}``\operatorname{Pr}_{0}(\aleph_{1},\aleph_{1},\aleph_{1},\aleph_0)_{\bar{p}}\mathrm{''} \end{align*} $$

for any $\omega _1$ sequence of partitions $\bar {p} = \langle p_{\delta }:\delta <\omega _1\rangle $ such that $p_{\delta }:[\omega _1]^2\to \omega $ for all $\delta <\omega _1$ .

Proof Let $\mathbb {P}_{\alpha }$ be the finite support iteration of the first $\alpha $ partial orders and suppose that

(7) $$ \begin{align} 1\Vdash_{{\mathbb P}_{\alpha}} ``\mathbb Q_{\alpha} = \bigcup_{n\in\omega} \mathbb Q_{\alpha,n} \text{ and each } \mathbb Q_{\alpha,n} \text{ is linked,''} \end{align} $$
(8) $$ \begin{align} 1\Vdash_{{\mathbb P}_{\alpha}} ``\{\dot{q}_{\alpha,n}\}_{n\in\omega} \text{ is a maximal antichain in } \mathbb Q_{\alpha}.\text{''} \end{align} $$

Let $B: [\omega _2]^2\to \omega _2$ be a bijection and let $e_{\xi }:\omega \to \xi $ be a bijection for each infinite $\xi \in \omega _1$ . Let V be a model of set theory, let $G\subseteq \mathbb P$ be generic over V and let $G_{\alpha }$ be the generic filter induced on $\mathbb Q_{\alpha }$ by G.

Now suppose that a sequence of partitions $\bar {p} = \langle p_{\delta }:\delta <\omega _1\rangle $ such that $p_{\delta }:[\omega _1]^2\to \omega $ belongs to $V[G]$ . As there is some $\alpha \in \omega _2$ such that $\bar {p}\in V[G\cap \mathbb P_{\alpha }]$ , it may be assumed that $\bar {p}\in V$ . There is no harm in assuming that B maps $ [\omega _1]^2$ to $\omega _1$ so let $c: [\omega _1]^2\to \omega _1$ be defined by $c(\alpha ,\beta ) = \xi $ if and only if $q_{B(\alpha ,\beta ),k}\in G_{B(\alpha ,\beta )}$ and $\xi = e_{B(\alpha ,\beta )}(k)$ .

To see that c witnesses $\operatorname {Pr}_0(\aleph _1,\aleph _1,\aleph _1,\aleph _0)_{\bar {p}}$ suppose that:

  • $\delta \in \omega _1.$

  • $k>0.$

  • $\dot \alpha _{\xi ,i}<\omega _1$ are $\mathbb P$ -names for $\xi <\omega _1$ and $1\le i\le k$ of distinct ordinals such that for every $\xi <\omega _1$ the sequence $\langle \dot \alpha _{\xi ,i}:1\le i\le \kappa \rangle $ is increasing with i.

  • $\left (\dot {N}_{i,j}\right )$ is a $\mathbb P$ -name for a $k\times k$ matrix with entries in ${\omega _1}^{\omega }$ .

We may fix $q_{\xi }\in G$ such that:

  1. (1) $q_{\xi }\Vdash _{\mathbb P} ``\dot {\alpha }_{\xi ,i} = \alpha _{\xi ,i}\;\text{''}$ for all $1\le i\le k,$

  2. (2) $\{\alpha _{\xi ,1},\alpha _{\xi , 2}, \ldots , \alpha _{\xi , k}\}\subseteq d_{\xi } = \bigcup B^{-1}({\operatorname {dom}\,}(q_{\xi })),$

  3. (3) for all $\mu \in {\operatorname {dom}\,}(q_{\xi })$ there is $n_{\mu ,\xi }$ such that $q_{\xi }\restriction \mu \Vdash _{{\mathbb P}_{\mu }} ``q_{\xi }(\mu )\in \mathbb Q_{\mu , n_{\mu ,\xi }}.\text{''}$

Let $\{\mathfrak M_{\eta }\}_{\eta \in \omega +1}$ be countable elementary submodels of

$$ \begin{align*}H(\omega_2,\{q_{\xi}, \{\alpha_{\xi,1},\alpha_{\xi, 2}, \ldots , \alpha_{\xi, k}\}\}_{\xi\in\omega_1},B, \dot{N}, G)\end{align*} $$

such that $\mathfrak M_j\prec \mathfrak M_{j+1}\prec \mathfrak M_{\omega }$ and $\omega _1\cap \mathfrak M_j \in \mathfrak M_{j+1}$ for each $j\in \omega $ . Let $\xi _{\omega } \in \omega _1\setminus \mathfrak M_{\omega }$ . By elementarity there are $\xi _j\in \omega _1\cap \mathfrak M_j$ such that:

  1. (1) ${\operatorname {dom}\,}(q_{\xi _{\omega }})\cap \mathfrak M_j\subseteq {\operatorname {dom}\,}(q_{\xi _j}).$

  2. (2) $ n_{\mu ,\xi _j} = n_{\mu ,\xi _{\omega }}$ for each $\mu \in {\operatorname {dom}\,}(q_{\xi _{\omega }})\cap \mathfrak M_j$ .

Note that $\{\alpha _{\xi _{\omega },1},\alpha _{\xi _{\omega }, 2}, \ldots , \alpha _{\xi _{\omega }, k}\}\cap \mathfrak M_{\omega }=\varnothing $ and hence

(9) $$ \begin{align} (\forall j\in \omega)(\forall u\in k)(\forall v\in k) \ B(\alpha_{\xi_j,u},\alpha_{\xi_{\omega},v})\notin \mathfrak M_{\omega} . \end{align} $$

Furthermore, note that $\bigcup B^{-1}({\operatorname {dom}\,}(q_{\xi _{\omega }}))$ is finite and so there is J such that

$$ \begin{align*}\bigcup B^{-1}({\operatorname {dom}\,}(q_{\xi_{\omega}}))\cap \mathfrak M_{\omega}\subseteq \mathfrak M_J .\end{align*} $$

From (9) it follows that

(10) $$ \begin{align}B(\alpha_{\xi_J,u},\alpha_{\xi_{\omega},v})\notin {\operatorname {dom}\,}(q_{\xi_J})\cup {\operatorname {dom}\,}(q_{\xi_{\omega}}) .\end{align} $$

From condition (19) in the choice of $q_{\xi }$ and condition (1) in the choice of $\xi _j$ , it follows that there is $q^*$ such that $q^*\leq q_{\xi _J}$ and $q^*\leq q_{\xi _{\omega }}$ and ${\operatorname {dom}\,}(q^*)= {\operatorname {dom}\,}(q_{\xi _J}) \cup {\operatorname {dom}\,}(q_{\xi _{\omega }})$ .

Let $\mathcal {A}\in \mathfrak {M_{\omega }}$ be a maximal antichain such that for every conditions $r\in \mathcal A$ ,

$$ \begin{align*}r\Vdash_{\mathbb P} ``M_{u,v} = \dot{N}_{u,v}(p_{\delta}(a_{\xi_J,u}, a_{\xi_{\omega},v}))\text{''}\end{align*} $$

for some $k\times k$ matrix $\left (M_{i,j}\right )$ with entries in $\omega _1$ .

By the countable chain condition, $\mathcal {A}$ is countable and hence $\mathcal {A}\subseteq \mathfrak {M_{\omega }}$ . Let $r\in \mathcal {A}$ be such that r is compatible with $q^*$ and let $\left (M_{i,j}\right )$ be the $k\times k$ matrix which witnesses that $r\in \mathcal {A}$ . Let $q^{**}\le q^*, r$ .

Note that $B(\alpha _{\xi _J,u},\alpha _{\xi _{\omega },v})\notin {\operatorname {dom}\,}(q^{**})$ because ${\operatorname {dom}\,}(q^{**})\setminus ({\operatorname {dom}\,}(q_{\xi _J})\cup {\operatorname {dom}\,}(q_{\xi _{\omega }}))\subseteq \mathfrak M_{\omega }$ and (9) and (10) hold. Let

$$ \begin{align*}\hat{q}(\theta)= \begin{cases} q^{**}(\theta) & \text{ if } \theta \notin \{B(a_{\xi_J,u}, a_{\xi_{\omega},v})\}_{u,v\in k},\\ q_{\theta , e^{-1}_{B(a_{\xi_J,u}, a_{\xi_{\omega},v})}(M_{u,v})} & \text{ if } \theta = B(a_{\xi_J,u}, a_{\xi_{\omega},v}). \end{cases}\end{align*} $$

Then by the definition of c

$$ \begin{align*}\hat{q}\Vdash_{\mathbb P} ``c(\alpha_{\xi_J, u}, \alpha_{\xi_{\omega}, v}) = M_{u,v} = \dot{N}_{u,v}((p_{\delta}(a_{\xi_J,u}, a_{\xi_{\omega},v}))\text{''}\end{align*} $$

for each u and v as required. ⊣

Corollary 29. It is consistent with ${MA}_{\aleph _1}(\sigma \text {-linked})$ that $\operatorname {Pr}_{0}(\aleph _1,\aleph _1,\aleph _1,\aleph _0)_{\bar p}$ holds for any $\omega _1$ sequence of partitions $\bar {p} = \{p_{\xi }\}_{\xi \in \omega _1}$ such that $p_{\xi }:[\omega _1]^2\to \omega $ .

Now we prove that the symbol

$$ \begin{align*} \omega_1\nrightarrow_p [\omega_1]^2_{\omega_1} \end{align*} $$

can consistently fail for some $p:[\omega _1]^2\to \omega $ .

We actually prove more. The failure of the symbol above over a partition $p:[\omega _1]^2\to \omega $ , symbolically written as

$$ \begin{align*} \omega_1\rightarrow_p[\omega_1]^2_{\omega_1}, \end{align*} $$

means that for every coloring $f:[\omega _1]^2\to \omega _1$ there is a set $A\in [\omega _1]^{\aleph _1}$ such that $f\restriction ([A]^2\cap p^{-1}(i))$ omits at least one color for every $i<\omega $ . Let us introduce the following symbol:

$$ \begin{align*} \omega_1\rightarrow_p[\omega_1]^2_{\omega_1\setminus \omega_1}, \end{align*} $$

to say that for every coloring $f:[\omega _1]^2\to \omega _1$ there is a set $A\in [\omega _1]^{\aleph _1}$ such that for every $i<\omega $ a set of size $\aleph _1$ of colors is omitted by $f\restriction ([A]^2\cap p^{-1}(i))$ . An even stronger failure (via breaking $\omega _1$ to two disjoint equinumerous sets and identifying all colors in each part) is

$$ \begin{align*} \omega_1\rightarrow_p[\omega_1]^2_2.\end{align*} $$

It is the consistency of the latter symbol which we prove. Note that with the rounded-brackets symbol in (1) from the introduction we may write this failure as:

$$ \begin{align*} \omega_1\rightarrow_p(\omega_1)^2_2,\end{align*} $$

whose meaning is that for every coloring $f:[\omega _1]^2\to 2$ there is $A\in [\omega _1]^{\aleph _1}$ such that for every $i<\omega $ the set $[A]^2\cap p^{-1}(i)$ is f-monochromatic. Thus, while $\omega _1\nrightarrow [\omega _1]^2_{\omega _1}$ holds in ZFC, it is consistent that for a suitable countable partition p the symbol $\omega _1\nrightarrow _p[\omega _1]^2_{\omega _1}$ fails pretty badly.

Theorem 30. It is consistent that $2^{\aleph _0}=\aleph _2$ and there is a partition $p:[\omega _1]^2 \to \omega $ such that

$$ \begin{align*} \omega_1\rightarrow_p [\omega_1]^2_2. \end{align*} $$

Corollary 31. It is consistent that $2^{\aleph _0}=\aleph _2$ and there is some $p:[\omega _1]^2\to \omega $ such that

$$ \begin{align*} \omega_1\rightarrow_p[\omega_1]^2_{\omega_1\setminus \omega_1} \;\;\;\text{ and hence }\;\;\; \omega_1\rightarrow_p[\omega_1]^2_{\omega_1}. \end{align*} $$

Proof of the Theorem

Let $\mathbb P$ be the partial order of finite partial functions from $[\omega _1]^2 \to \omega $ ordered by inclusion. More precisely, each condition $q\in \mathbb P$ has associated to it a finite subset of $\omega _1$ which, abusing notation, will be called ${\operatorname {dom}\,}(q)$ . Then q is a function $[{\operatorname {dom}\,}(q)]^2\rightarrow \omega $ .

Given any partition $p:[\omega _1]^2 \to \omega $ and a colouring $c:[\omega _1]^2 \to 2$ define the partial order $\mathbb Q(p,c)$ to be the set of all pairs $(h,w)$ such that

  • $w\in [\omega _1]^{<\aleph _0},$

  • $h:m\to 2$ for some $m\in \omega $ so that $m\supseteq p([w]^2),$

  • $c(\{\alpha ,\beta \}) \neq h(p(\{\alpha ,\beta \}))$ for each $\{\alpha ,\beta \}\in [w]^2$

and order $\mathbb Q(p,c)$ by coordinatewise extension. Let V be a model of set theory in which $2^{\aleph _1} = \aleph _2$ and let $\{c_{\xi }\}_{\xi \in \omega _2}$ enumerate cofinally often the subsets of hereditary cardinality less than $\aleph _2$ . If $G\subseteq \mathbb P$ is generic over V, in $V[G]$ define $p_G=\bigcup G$ . Then define a finite support iteration $\{\mathbb Q_{\zeta }\}_{\zeta \in \omega _2}$ such that $\mathbb Q_1=\mathbb P$ and if $c_{\zeta }$ is a $\mathbb Q_{\zeta }$ -name such that $1\Vdash _{{\mathbb Q}_{\zeta }} ``c_{\zeta }:[\omega _1]^2 \to 2\text{''}$ then $\mathbb Q_{\zeta +1} = \mathbb Q_{\zeta }\ast \mathbb Q(p_G,c_{\zeta })$ .

It suffices to establish the following two claims.

Claim 32. For each $\zeta \in \omega _2$ greater than $1$ and $\eta \in \omega _1$ the set of $q\in \mathbb Q_{\zeta +1}$ such that

$$ \begin{align*}q\restriction \zeta\Vdash_{{\mathbb Q}_{\zeta}} ``q(\zeta ) = (h,w)\text{ and } w\setminus \eta\neq \varnothing\mathrm{''}\end{align*} $$

is dense in $\mathbb Q_{\zeta +1}$ .

Proof Given q it may be assumed that there are h and w such that

$$ \begin{align*}q\restriction \zeta\Vdash_{{\mathbb Q}_{\zeta}} ``q(\zeta ) = (\check{h},\check{w}).\text{''}\end{align*} $$

Let $\theta \in \omega _1$ be so large that $\theta>\max ({\operatorname {dom}\,}(q(0))),\max (w),\eta $ . Let $f:w\to \omega $ be any one-to-one function so that ${\operatorname {ran}}(f)\cap {\operatorname {dom}\,}(h)=\emptyset $ and let $f_{\theta }:\{\{\theta ,\rho \}\}_{\rho \in w}\to \omega $ be defined by $f_{\theta }(\{\theta ,\rho \}) = f(\rho )$ . Note that since $q(0)\cup f_{\theta }\in \mathbb P$ it is possible to find $\bar {q}\leq q\restriction \zeta $ such that:

  • $f_{\theta }\subseteq \bar {q}(0)$ and

  • $\bar {q}\Vdash _{{\mathbb Q}_{\zeta }} ``c_{\zeta }(\{\theta ,\rho \}) = \check {k}_{\rho }\text{''}$ for some family of integers $\{k_{\rho }\}_{\rho \in w}$ equal to $0$ or $1$ .

Then let $\bar {h}\supseteq h$ be any finite function such that $\bar {h}(f(\rho ))=1- k_{\rho }$ and let $\bar {w} = w\cup \{\theta \}$ . Then $\bar {q}\ast (\bar {h},\bar {w})$ is the desired condition. ⊣

Claim 33. The partial order $\mathbb Q_{\omega _2}$ satisfies the ccc.

Proof By a standard argument, there is a dense subset of $\mathbb Q_{\omega _2}$ of conditions q such that for each $\zeta \in {\operatorname {dom}\,}(q)$ with $\zeta>0$ , there are h and w so that $q\restriction \zeta \Vdash _{{\mathbb Q}_{\omega _2}} ``q(\zeta ) = (\check {h},\check {w}).\text{''}$ We will assume that all conditions that we work with are members of this dense subset.

Let $\{ q_{\xi }:\xi <\omega _1\}$ be conditions in $\mathbb Q_{\omega _2}$ . By thinning out, we can assume that their domains form a $\Delta $ -system with root $\{0,\zeta _0,\zeta _1,\ldots ,\zeta _k\}$ . We can further assume that:

  • each of the sets $\{{\operatorname {dom}\,}(q_{\xi }(0)):\xi <\omega _1\}$ , and $\{w_{\xi ,\zeta _i}:\xi <\omega _1\}$ for each $i\le k$ form a $\Delta $ -system,

  • the functions $q_{\xi }(0)$ agree on the root of the $\Delta $ -system of their domains, and

  • there are $h_i$ , $i\le k$ , so that for all $\xi <\omega $ we have $h_i=h_{\xi ,\zeta _i}$ ,

where $q_{\xi }\restriction \zeta \Vdash _{{\mathbb Q}_{\omega _2}} ``q_{\xi }(\zeta ) = (\check {h}_{\xi ,\zeta },\check {w}_{\xi ,\zeta }).\text{''}$

Let $\delta =\max \{{\operatorname {dom}\,}(q_0(0)),w_{0,\zeta _i}:i\le k\}$ . Pick $\unicode{x3b3} <\omega _1$ so that each of the values

$$ \begin{align*}\min({\operatorname {dom}\,}(q_{\unicode{x3b3}}(0))\setminus {\operatorname {dom}\,}(q_0(0))),\min(w_{\unicode{x3b3},\zeta_i}\setminus w_{0,\zeta_i}) \text{ for } i\le k,\end{align*} $$

are above $\delta $ (if defined).

Arguing as in Claim 32, we see that $q_0$ and $q_{\unicode{x3b3} }$ are compatible conditions. ⊣

This completes the proof of the theorem.⊣

Definition 34. The symbol

$$ \begin{align*}\kappa\to_p [\kappa]^2_{\lambda,<\mu} \end{align*} $$

for a partition $p:[\kappa ]^2\to \theta $ means that for every coloring $f:[\kappa ]^2\to \lambda $ there is a set $A\in [\kappa ]^{\kappa }$ such that $|{\operatorname {ran}} (f\restriction ( [A]^2\cap p^{-1}(i)))|<\mu $ for all $i<\theta $ .

Note that for $\mu \le \lambda $ this symbol is stronger than $\kappa \to _p [\kappa ]^2_{\lambda \setminus \lambda }$ . Thus the next theorem, which uses ideas from [Reference Shelah and Steprāns39], gives a stronger consistency than the previous one.

Theorem 35. Given any regular $\kappa>\aleph _1$ it is consistent that:

  • $ \operatorname {\mathrm {\textbf {non}}}(\mathcal L)= \aleph _1$ ,

  • $\mathfrak b = \aleph _2 = 2^{\aleph _0}$ ,

  • $2^{\aleph _1} = \kappa $ , and

  • there is a $p:[\omega _1]^2\to \omega $ such that $\omega _1\rightarrow _p [\omega _1]^2_{\omega ,<\omega }$ .

Theorem 36. Given any regular $\kappa>\aleph _1$ it is consistent that:

  • $ \operatorname {\mathrm {\textbf {non}}}(\mathcal M)= \aleph _1$ ,

  • $\mathfrak b = \aleph _1 $ ,

  • $\mathfrak d = \aleph _2 = 2^{\aleph _0}$ ,

  • $2^{\aleph _1} = \kappa $ , and

  • there is a $p:[\omega _1]^2\to \omega $ such that $\omega _1\rightarrow _p [\omega _1]^2_{\omega ,<\omega }$ .

The proofs of both theorems are similar, using ideas from [Reference Shelah and Steprāns39]; only the proof of Theorem 35 will be given in detail. Both rely on the following definition:

Definition 37. Let $\mu $ be some probability measure on $\omega $ under which each singleton has positive measure, for example $\mu (\{n\}) = 2^{-n}$ . A sequence of functions $\mathcal P = \{p_{\eta }\}_{\eta \in \omega _1}$ will be said to have full outer measure if:

  • $p_{\eta }:\eta \to \omega $ and

  • for each $\eta \in \omega _1$ the set $\{p_{\beta }\restriction \eta \}_{\beta> \eta }$ has measure one in the measure space $(\omega ^{\eta },\mu ^{\eta })$ .

The sequence $\mathcal P$ is defined to be nowhere meagre similarly, by requiring that for each $\eta \in \omega _1$ the set $\{p_{\beta }\restriction \eta \}_{\beta> \eta }$ is nowhere meagre in $(\omega ^{\eta },\mu ^{\eta })$ with the usual product topology. In both cases define $p = p(\mathcal P)$ by $p(\alpha , \beta ) = p_{\beta }(\alpha )$ if $\alpha < \beta $ .

By enumerating all functions from a countable ordinal into $\omega $ , we have:

Proposition 38. Assuming the Continuum Hypothesis there is a sequence $\mathcal P = \{p_{\eta }\}_{\eta \in \omega _1}$ such that $\{p_{\beta }\restriction \eta \}_{\beta> \eta } = \omega ^{\eta }$ for each $\eta \in \omega _1$ . Hence $\mathcal P$ has full outer measure as in Definition 37 .

While it is, of course, impossible to preserve the property that $\{p_{\beta }\restriction \eta \}_{\beta> \eta } = \omega ^{\eta }$ when adding reals, the goal of the following arguments is to show that the properties of Definition 37 can be preserved in certain circumstances. The following definition is from [Reference Shelah and Steprāns39] and will play a key role in this context.

Definition 39. A function $\psi : {\omega }^{<\omega } \to [\omega _1]^{<\aleph _0}$ satisfying that $\psi (s)\cap \psi (t)=\varnothing $ unless $s=t$ will be said to have disjoint range. If for each $t\in {\omega }^{<\omega }$ there is k such that $|\psi (t^{\frown } j)|<k$ for all $j\in \omega $ then $\psi $ will be called bounded with disjoint range. If G is a filter of subtrees of $ {\omega }^{<\omega }$ and $\psi $ has disjoint range define

$$ \begin{align*}S(G,\psi) = \bigcup_{t\in\bigcap G} \psi(t) .\end{align*} $$

If G is a generic filter of trees over a model V define

$$ \begin{align*} \mathcal S_b(G) = \{S(G,\psi) \ | \ \psi\in V\text{ and } \psi \text{ is bounded with disjoint range}\}. \end{align*} $$

It is shown in [Reference Shelah and Steprāns39] that Lemmas 40 and 42 hold.

Lemma 40. If $G\subseteq \mathbb L$ is generic over V then $\mathcal S_b(G)$ is a P-ideal in $V[G]$ .

Lemma 41 is the content of Section 3 of [Reference Abraham and Todorčević1]. Recall that if $\mathcal I$ is an ideal then X is said to be orthogonal to $\mathcal I$ if $X\cap A$ is finite for each $A\in \mathcal I$ .

Lemma 41 Abraham and Todorčević

Let $\mathcal I$ be a P-ideal on $\omega _1$ that is generated by a family of $\aleph _1$ countable sets and such that $\omega _1$ is not the union of countably many sets orthogonal to $\mathcal I$ . Then there is a proper partial order ${\mathbb P}_{\mathcal I}$ , that adds no reals, even when iterated with countable support, such that there is a ${\mathbb P}_{\mathcal I}$ -name $\dot {Z}$ for an uncountable subset of $\omega _1$ such that $ 1\Vdash _{{\mathbb P}_{\mathcal I}} ``(\forall \eta \in \omega _1) \ \dot {Z}\cap \eta \in \mathcal I.\mathrm{''} $

Lemma 42. If $G\subseteq \mathbb L$ is generic over V and ${\mathbb P}_{{\mathcal S}_b(G)}$ is the partial order of Lemma 41 using Lemma 40 and $H\subseteq {\mathbb P}_{{\mathcal S}_b(G)}$ is generic over $V[G]$ then in $V[G][H]$ there is an uncountable $R\subseteq \omega _1$ such that $R\cap Y\neq \varnothing $ for each uncountable $Y\in V[G]$ and such that $[R]^{\aleph _0}\subseteq {\mathcal S}_b(G)$ .

Lemma 43. Let $\mathcal P$ be a sequence with full outer measure and suppose that $p = p(\mathcal P)$ . Suppose further that

  • $c:[\omega _1]^2 \to \omega $ ,

  • $G\subseteq \mathbb L$ is generic over V, and

  • $H\subseteq \mathbb P_{{\mathcal S}_b(\dot {G})}$ is generic over $V[G]$ .

Then there is an uncountable $X\subseteq \omega _1$ in $V[G][H]$ and $L:\omega \to \omega $ such that $L(p(\alpha ,\beta ))>c(\alpha ,\beta )$ for all $\{\alpha ,\beta \}\in [X]^2$ .

Proof In $V[G]$ let $L = \bigcap {G}$ be the Laver real. In $V[G][H]$ let R be the uncountable set given by Lemma 42. Construct by induction distinct $\rho _{\xi }\in R$ such that if $\eta \in \xi $ then $L(p(\rho _{\xi },\rho _{\eta }))>c(\rho _{\xi },\rho _{\eta }) $ . To carry out the induction assume that $R_{\eta }= \{\rho _{\xi }\}_{\xi \in \eta }$ have been chosen and satisfy the inductive hypothesis.

By the choice of R it follows that $R_{\eta }\in {\mathcal S}_b(G)$ . Since $\mathbb P_{{\mathcal S}_b(\dot {G})}$ adds no new reals it follows that $R_{\eta } \in V[G]$ and so there is $T\in G$ and $\psi \in V$ with bounded, disjoint range such that $T\Vdash _{\mathbb L} ``\dot {R}_{\eta } = S(\dot {G},\psi ).\text{''}$ Let $\mu $ be so large that $T\Vdash _{\mathbb L} ``\dot {R}_{\eta } \subseteq \mu \text{''}$ and let r be the root of T. For $t\in T$ define $\mathcal W_t=\left \{x\in 2^{\mu } \ \left | \ x\restriction \psi (t)\text { has constant value } |t| \right .\right \} $ and then define

$$ \begin{align*}\mathcal W_t^+ = \left\{x\in 2^{\mu} \ \left| \ (\exists^{\infty} s\in \textstyle{\textbf{succ}_T(t)}) \ x\in {\mathcal W}_s \right.\right\} .\end{align*} $$

Note that ${\mathcal W}_t^+$ has measure one in $2^{\mu }$ for each $t\supseteq r$ . To see this note that for a random $h\in 2^{\mu }$ the probability that $h(\zeta ) = |t| + 1$ is $2^{-(|t|+1)}$ . Also, note that since $\psi $ is bounded—see Definition 39—there is some k such that $|\psi (s)|\leq k$ for each $s\in \textbf {succ}_T(t)$ . Hence, the probability of h belonging to ${\mathcal W}_{s}$ is bounded below by $2^{-(|t|+1)k}$ for all $s\in \textbf {succ}_T(t)$ and these events are independent because the $\psi (s)$ are pairwise disjoint for $s\in \textbf {succ}_T(t)$ .

Define f on $\bigcup _{j\leq |r|}\psi (r\restriction j)$ to have constant value $|r|$ and note that the domain of f is disjoint from each $\psi (s)$ where $s\supsetneq r$ . Hence the probability that $f\subseteq h$ is non-zero and independent from belonging to each ${\mathcal W}^+$ . Since p has full outer measure it follows that

$$ \begin{align*}\Bigg\{\beta\in \omega_1 \ \Bigg| \ f\subseteq p_{\beta}\restriction \mu\in\bigcap_{r\subseteq t\in T}{\mathcal W}_{t}^+ \Bigg\}\end{align*} $$

is uncountable and belongs to $V[G]$ . Therefore by Lemma 42 there is some $\beta \in R\setminus R_{\eta }$ such that $f\subseteq p_{\beta }\restriction \mu $ and such that for all $t\in T$ containing r there are infinitely many $s\in \textstyle {\textbf {succ}_T(t)}$ such that $p(\alpha ,\beta ) = |s|$ for all $\alpha \in \psi (s)$ .

Using this and the definition of f, it is possible to start with r and successively thin out the successors of each $t\in T$ to find a tree $T^*\subseteq T$ with root r such that $p(\alpha ,\beta ) = |t| $ for all $t\in T^*$ and for all $\alpha \in \psi (t)$ . Once again starting with r and removing only finitely many elements of $\textbf {succ}_{T^*}(t)$ for each $t\in T^*$ it is possible to find $T^{**}\subseteq T^*$ with root r such that

$$ \begin{align*} (\forall t\in T^{**})(\forall s\in {\textbf{succ}_{T^{**}}(t)})(\forall \alpha \in \psi(t)) \ s(|t|) = s(p(\alpha,\beta))>c(\alpha,\beta)\end{align*} $$

and this implies that

$$ \begin{align*} T^{**}\, {\Vdash}_{\mathbb L} ``(\forall \alpha\in {\dot{R}}_{\eta}) \ \dot{L}(p(\alpha,\beta))>c(\alpha,\beta).\text{''} \end{align*} $$

Since this holds for any T, genericity yields that in $V[G][H]$ there is some $\beta \in R\setminus R_{\eta }$ such that $L(p(\rho _{\xi },\beta ))>c(\rho _{\xi },\beta )$ for each $\xi \in \eta $ . Define $\rho _{\eta } = \beta $ to continue the induction. Since limit stages are immediate, this completes the proof. ⊣

Proof of Theorem 35

The required model is the one obtained by starting with a model of the Continuum Hypothesis in which $2^{\aleph _1}=\kappa $ . Then iterate with countable support the partial order ${\mathbb L}\ast {\mathbb P}_{{\mathcal S}_b\dot {G})}$ . In the initial model there is, by Proposition 38, a sequence with full outer measure. To see this, begin by observing that it is shown in Theorem 7.3.39 of [Reference Bartoszyński and Judah2] that $\mathbb L$ preserves $\sqsubseteq ^{\textbf {Random}}$ . Since ${\mathbb P}_{{\mathcal S}(\dot {G})}$ is proper and adds no new reals it is immediate that it also preserves $ \sqsubseteq ^{\textbf {Random}}$ . It follows by Theorem 6.1.13 of [Reference Bartoszyński and Judah2] that the entire countable support iteration preserves outer measure sets and, hence, any sequence with full outer measure in the initial model maintains this property throughout the iteration.

To see that for every function $c:[\omega _1]^2\to \omega $ there is an uncountable set witnessing $\aleph _1{\rightarrow }_p[\aleph _{1}]_{\aleph _0,<\aleph _0}$ use Lemma 3.4 and Lemma 3.6 of [Reference Abraham and Todorčević1] to conclude that each partial order in the $\omega _2$ length iteration is proper and has the $\aleph _2$ -pic of Definition 2.1 on page 409 of [Reference Shelah35]. By Lemma 2.4 on page 410 of [Reference Shelah35] it follows that the iteration has the $\aleph _2$ chain condition and, hence, that c appears at some stage. It is then routine to apply Lemma 43.

That $\mathfrak b=\aleph _2$ is a standard argument using that Laver forcing adds a dominating real. ⊣

Remark 44. The proof of Theorem 36 is similar but uses Miller reals instead of Laver reals. This requires that nowhere meagreness play the role of full outer measure.

Remark 45. Note that there is no partition p such that

$$ \begin{align*} \omega_1{\rightarrow}_p [\omega_1]^2_{\omega_1,<\omega_1} \end{align*} $$

because a colouring $c:[\omega _1]^2\to \omega _1$ that is a bijection will provide a counterexample.

6 Concluding Remarks and Open Questions

It turns out, via Lemma 9, that getting strong coloring symbols over finite partitions is not harder than getting them without partitions; so one immediately gets many strong coloring symbols over partitions outright in ZFC. If the number of colors $\lambda $ raised to the number of cells in a partition is not too large, Lemma 9 applies again, and consequently all GCH symbols gotten by Erdoős, Hajnal and Milner on $\kappa ^+$ hold under the GCH over arbitrary $\kappa $ -partitions. Even without instances of the GCH, strong colorings symbols over countable partitions are valid in Cohen-type forcing extenstions, by Theorems 27 and 28.

Yet, it is not the case that every time a strong-coloring symbol holds at a successor of a regular, it also holds over countable partitions: by Theorems 30 and 35 the ZFC symbol $\aleph _1\nrightarrow [\aleph _1]^2_{\aleph _1}$ , and hence all stronger ones, consistently fail quite badly over sufficiently generic countable partitions. Thus, strong coloring symbols over partitions are a subject of their own, in which the independence phenomenon is manifested prominently.

Many natural questions about the combinatorial and set-theoretic connections between coloring and partition arise. We hope that this subject will get attention in the near future both in the infinite combinatorics and in the forcing communities. For example, by Fact 11, there is always a set of $2$ -partitions of $[\kappa ^+]^2$ such that no coloring is strong over all of them. What is the least cardinality of such a set? In the case of $\theta =\kappa =\aleph _0$ , the results in Section 5 show that this cardinal may be as small as 1 or at least as large as $\aleph _2=\kappa ^{++}$ . Can this number ever be $\kappa $ or, say, $\kappa ^+<2^{\kappa }$ ?

We conclude with a short selection of open questions.

Question 46. If $\operatorname {Pr}_1(\aleph _1,\aleph _1,\aleph _1,\aleph _0)_p$ holds for all countable p, does also $\operatorname {Pr}_0(\aleph _1,\aleph _1,\aleph _1,\aleph _0)_p$ hold for all countable p?

Question 47. Suppose $\operatorname {Pr}_0(\aleph _1,\aleph _1,\aleph _0,\aleph _0)_p$ holds for some countable partition p. Does $\operatorname {Pr}_0(\aleph _1,\aleph _1,\aleph _1,\aleph _0)_p$ hold as well?

Without partitions, both implications above hold.

Question 48. Does $MA_{\sigma \text {-linked}}$ or $\mathfrak p = \mathfrak c$ or even full $MA_{\aleph _1}$ imply that $\operatorname {Pr}_{0}(\aleph _1,\aleph _1,\aleph _1,\aleph _0)_{\bar p}$ holds for every $\omega _1$ sequence of partitions $\bar {p} = \langle p_{\delta }:\delta <\omega _1\rangle $ such that $p_{\delta }:[\omega _1]^2\to \omega $ ?

Question 49. Is it consistent that there is a partition p such that

$$ \begin{align*}\aleph_1\rightarrow_p [\aleph_1]^2_{\aleph_0,<k}\end{align*} $$

for some integer k?

Question 50. Is

consistent for all $\aleph _0$ - or $\aleph _1$ -partitions p? That is, can there be a coloring $f:[\omega _2]^2\to \omega _2$ such that for every (one, or sequence of $\omega _2$ many) $\omega _1$ -partition(s) of $[\omega _2]^2$ , for every $B\in [\omega _2]^{\omega _2}$ , for all but finitely many $\alpha <\omega _2$ there is $i<\omega _1$ such that for every color $\zeta <\omega _2$ there is $\beta \in B$ such that $p(\alpha ,\beta )=i$ and $f(\alpha ,\beta )=\zeta $ .

The consistency of this symbol is open even without the p. A negative answer may be easier to get with p.

Added in proof: Problems 46–49 above are solved in [Reference Kojman, Rinot and Steprans18].

Acknowledgments

The first author’s research for this paper was partially supported by an Israeli Science Foundation grant number 665/20. The third author’s research for this paper was partially supported by NSERC of Canada.

References

REFERENCES

Abraham, U. and Todorčević, S., Partition properties of ${\omega}_1$ compatible with CH . Fundamenta Mathematicae, vol. 152 (1997), no. 2, pp. 165181.10.4064/fm-152-2-165-181CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bartoszyński, T. and Judah, H., Set Theory: On the Structure of the Real Line, A. K. Peters, Boca Raton, 1995.10.1201/9781439863466CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baumgartner, J. E., Partition relations for countable topological spaces. The Journal of Combinatorial Theory, Series A, vol. 43 (1986), no. 2, pp. 178195.10.1016/0097-3165(86)90059-2CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Erdős, P., Galvin, F. and Hajnal, A., On set-systems having large chromatic number and not containing prescribed subsystems , Infinite and Finite Sets (Colloq. Keszthely 1973; dedicated to P. Erdős on his 60th birthday,) Vol. I. Colloq. Math. Soc. J. Bolyai, Vol. 10, North Holland, Amsterdam, 1975, pp. 425513.Google Scholar
Erdős, P., Hajnal, A., Máté, A., and Rado, R., Combinatorial Set Theory Partition Relations for Cardinals , Vol. 106, Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, North Holland, Amsterdam, 1984 . Google Scholar
Eisworth, T, A note on strong negative partition relations . Fundamenta Mathematicae , vol. 202 (2009), pp. 97123.10.4064/fm202-2-1CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eisworth, T, Club guessing, stationary reflection, and coloring theorems . Annals of Pure and Applied Logic , vol. 161 (2010), pp. 12161243.10.1016/j.apal.2010.02.004CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eisworth, T, Successors of singular cardinals , Handbook of Set Theory (Foreman, M and Kanamori, A, editors), Springer, Dordrecht, 2010, pp. 12291350.10.1007/978-1-4020-5764-9_16CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eisworth, T, Getting more colors I . Journal of Symbolic Logic , vol. 78 (2013), no. 1, pp. 116.10.2178/jsl.7801010CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eisworth, T, Getting more colors II . Journal of Symbolic Logic , vol. 78 (2013), no. 1, pp. 1738.10.2178/jsl.7801020CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eisworth, T, On idealized versions of ${Pr}_1(\mu {,}^{+},{\mu}^{+},{\mu}^{+}, cf(\mu ))$ . Archive for Mathematical Logic , vol. 53 (2014), pp. 809824.10.1007/s00153-014-0389-4CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eisworth, T. and Shelah, S., Successors of singular cardinals and coloring theorems I . Archive for Mathematical Logic , vol. 44 (2005), no. 5, pp. 597618.10.1007/s00153-004-0258-7CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eisworth, T. and Shelah, S., Successors of singular cardinals and coloring theorems II . Journal of Symbolic Logic , vol. 74 (2009), no. 4, pp. 12871309.10.2178/jsl/1254748692CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fleissner, W. G., Some spaces related to topological inequalities proven by the Erdős-Rado theorem . Proceedings of the American Mathematical Society, vol. 71 (1978), no. 2, pp. 313320.Google Scholar
Galvin, F., Chain conditions and products. Fundamenta Mathematicae, vol. 108 (1980), no. 1, pp. 3348.10.4064/fm-108-1-33-48CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Guzman, O., On $(1,{\omega}_1)$ -weakly universal functions. Fundamenta Mathematicae, vol. 247 (2019), no. 1, pp. 8798.10.4064/fm630-9-2018CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hajnal, A. and Komjath, P., Some remarks on the simultaneous chromatic number . Combinatorica, vol. 23 (2003), no. 1, pp. 89104.10.1007/s00493-003-0015-2CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kojman, M., Rinot, A. and Steprans, J., Advances on strong colorings over partitions, Preprint February 2021. Available at http://assafrinot.com/paper/49, 2021.Google Scholar
Lambie-Hanson, C. and Rinot, A., Knaster and friends II: The C-sequence number. Journal of Mathematical Logic, vol. 21 (2021), no. 1, p. 2150002, 54.Google Scholar
Moore, J. T., A solution to the L space problem. Journal of the American Mathematical Society, vol. 19 (2006), pp. 717736.10.1090/S0894-0347-05-00517-5CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Peng, Y. and Wu, L., A Lindelöf group with non-Lindelöf square. Advances in Mathematics, vol. 325 (2018), pp. 215242.10.1016/j.aim.2017.11.021CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Raghavan, D. and Todorčević, S., Proof of a conjecture of Galvin. Forum of Mathematics, vol. Pi 8 (2020), p. e15.10.1017/fmp.2020.12CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rinot, A., Transforming rectangles into squares, with applications to strong colorings. Advances in Mathematics, vol. 231 (2012), no. 2, pp. 10851099.10.1016/j.aim.2012.06.013CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rinot, A., Complicated colorings. Mathematical Research Letters, vol. 21 (2014), no. 6, pp. 13671388.10.4310/MRL.2014.v21.n6.a9CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rinot, A., Chain conditions of products, and weakly compact cardinals, this Journal, vol. 20 (2014), no. 3, pp. 293314.Google Scholar
Rinot, A., An $S$ -space from a Cohen real. Blog post Available at http://blog.assafrinot.com/?p=2707.Google Scholar
Rinot, A., Personal communication. 2019.Google Scholar
Rinot, A. and Todorčević, S., Rectangular square-bracket operation for successor of regular cardinals. Fundamenta Mathematicae, vol. 220 (2013), no. 2, pp. 119128.10.4064/fm220-2-2CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rinot, A. and Zhang, J., Strongest transformations, Preprint February 2021. Available at http://assafrinot.com/paper/45, 2021.Google Scholar
Roitman, J., Adding a random or a Cohen real: Topological consequences and the effect on Martin’s axiom. Fundamenta Mathematicae , vol. 103 (1979), no. 1, pp. 4760.10.4064/fm-103-1-47-60CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shelah, S., Was Sierpiński right? I. Israel Journal of Mathematics, vol. 62 (1988), pp. 355380.10.1007/BF02783304CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shelah, S., Strong partition relations below the power set: Consistency, was Sierpiński right, II? Proceedings of the Conference on Set Theory and its Applications in Honor of Hajnal, A. and Sos., V. T., Budapest, 1/91, 1991, pp. 637668.Google Scholar
Shelah, S., Was Sierpiński right? III. Can continuum–c.c. times c.c.c. be continuum–c.c.? Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, vol. 78 (1996), pp. 259269.10.1016/0168-0072(95)00036-4CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shelah, S., Colouring and non-productivity of ${\aleph}_2$ -cc. Annals Pure and Applied Logic, vol. 84 (1997), pp. 153174.10.1016/S0168-0072(96)00020-6CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shelah, S., Proper and Improper Forcing, second ed., Perspectives in Mathematical Logic, Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 1998.10.1007/978-3-662-12831-2CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shelah, S., Was Sierpiński right? IV. Journal of Symbolic Logic, vol. 65 (2000), pp. 10311054.10.2307/2586687CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shelah, S., Successors of singulars, cofinalities of reduced products of cardinals and productivity of chain conditions. Israel Journal of Mathematics, vol. 62 (1988), pp. 213256.10.1007/BF02787123CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shelah, S., Cardinal Arithmetic, Vol. 29, Oxford Logic Guides, The Clarendon Press, Oxford University Press, New York, NY, 1994.Google Scholar
Shelah, S. and Steprāns, J., Universal graphs and functions on ${\omega}_1$ , preprint, 2016.Google Scholar
Steprāns, J., Combinatorial consequences of adding Cohen reals. Set Theory of the Reals , pp. 583617, Israel Math. Conf. Proc., 6, Bar-Ilan Univ., Ramat Gan, 1993.Google Scholar
Todorčević, S., Partitioning pairs of countable ordinals. Acta Mathematica, vol. 159 (1987), no. 3–4, pp. 261294.10.1007/BF02392561CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Todorčević, S., Partition Problems in Topology , vol. 84, Contemporary Mathematics, American Mathematical Society, Providence, RI, 1989.10.1090/conm/084CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Todorčević, S., Some partitions of three-dimensional combinatorial cubes. The Journal of Combinatorial Theory, Series A, vol. 68 (1994), no. 2, pp. 410437.10.1016/0097-3165(94)90113-9CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Todorčević, S., Oscillations of sets of integers. Advances in Applied Mathematics, vol. 20 (1998), no. 2, pp. 220252.10.1006/aama.1997.0572CrossRefGoogle Scholar