Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-rcrh6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-22T11:15:41.711Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Reconsidering the Role of Procedures for Decision Acceptance

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  12 December 2016

Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Procedural fairness theory posits that the way in which authoritative decisions are made strongly impacts people’s willingness to accept them. This article challenges this claim by contending that democratic governments can achieve little in terms of acceptance of policy decisions by the procedural means at their disposal. Instead, outcome favorability is the dominant determinant of decision acceptance. The article explicates that while central parts of procedural fairness theory are true, outcome favorability is still overwhelmingly the strongest determinant of individuals’ willingness to accept authoritative decisions. It improves on previous research by locating all key variables into one causal model and testing this model using appropriate data. Findings from a large number of experiments (both vignette and field) reproduce the expected relationships from previous research and support the additional predictions.

Type
Articles
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
© Cambridge University Press 2016

Procedural fairness research has demonstrated that people care strongly about the way authoritative decisions are made. Acknowledging this preference, political scientists have long used procedural fairness theory to inform their analysis of citizens’ relationships with democratic authorities.Footnote 1 An important finding in procedural fairness research is that procedures are closely connected with decision acceptance. Drawing out real-world implications of this finding, leading scholars in the field maintain that democratic governments can generate citizen acceptance of difficult decisions if they follow fair procedures when making them. For example, Tyler recommends that authorities should focus on acting ‘in ways that encourage judgments that they are using just procedures when exercising their authority’.Footnote 2 And MacCounFootnote 3 warns that people’s preference for fair procedures is so strong that it leaves them ‘susceptible to manipulation and exploitation’.Footnote 4

In this article, we take a new look at the procedure-acceptance connection in the context of policy making. Contrary to conventional wisdom, we contend that democratic governments can achieve little in terms of acceptance of their policy decisions by optimizing the procedural means at their disposal. We do not dispute the key insight from procedural fairness research that people value what they perceive to be fair decision-making procedures. However, we explicate why outcome favorability is nevertheless a much stronger determinant of individuals’ willingness to accept policy decisions than the objective procedural arrangements that are available to government authorities.

Our reassessment of the procedure-acceptance connection targets three variables: objective procedural arrangements (the procedural means at democratic governments’ disposal), subjective procedural assessments (individuals’ evaluations of the fairness of the objective decision-making arrangements, which is the prime causal factor within the procedural fairness literature) and outcome favorability (the degree to which a decision coincides with an individual’s preference). As we will explore throughout this article, locating key variables in a properly specified model generates different results than would be expected when looking at the individual parts.

In the following, we first revisit procedural fairness theory to identify the conditions under which objective procedural arrangements for policy decisions generate decision acceptance and to highlight previous research that provides pieces of the puzzle we wish to complete. We discuss the theory in its abstract form as well as how it applies to policy decisions specifically.

Having discussed issues of design, data and measurements, we present findings from twenty-eight vignette and field experiments in which objective procedural arrangements are manipulated in a number of ways. The manipulations involve generic arrangements for policy decisions (direct majoritarian voting, representative decision-making and expert decision-making) as well as fair and unfair implementations of generic arrangements for decision-making (for example, whether or not an expert decision-making procedure allows affected individuals to voice concerns pre-decision). Using structural equation modeling to analyze these data, we reproduce all the typical findings from procedural fairness research and find support for the additional predictions that distinguish our study from much previous research in the field. We conclude by discussing the implications of our findings for theory and for authoritative decision-making in the real world.

THEORY

Procedural fairness theory is anchored in psychological social justice research.Footnote 5 Social justice theory assumes that fairness is one of the fundamental norms and values in society.Footnote 6 Like many powerful theories, its internal logic is simple: people experience an event and assess the fairness of their experience; these fairness assessments then generate reactions. Thus the theory is subjective in character; although rooted in objective events, fairness is an idea that exists within the minds of individuals.Footnote 7

Within this recursive three-variable framework (event–fairness assessment–reaction), procedural fairness theory stresses the procedural qualities of the experiences individuals have when subjected to authoritative decisions. The decision-making authority follows certain objective procedural arrangements (for instance, a parliamentary majority decides to raise the sales tax after an extensive debate in which different interests have presented their arguments), individuals assess the fairness of these arrangements and the assessments generate reactions (see Figure 1).

Fig. 1 Procedural fairness theory

For objective procedural arrangements to translate into decision acceptance, individuals must perceive that the decision has been reached in a fair way (the causal flow denoted by A), and then consider this information important for their reactions to the decision (the causal flow denoted by B). For the objective procedural arrangement effect to be substantial, both causal flows must be strong.

A general observation about research in this field is that scholars have been focusing on the complexities of each respective causal flow (A or B) and have been less concerned with modeling the full causal chain from event to outcome reaction (A and then B).Footnote 8 Moreover, studies that estimate the causal impact of objective conditions on reactions to the decision frequently study outcomes other than decision acceptance, such as changes in self-esteem.Footnote 9

Indicative of researchers’ inclination to focus on parts of the causal chain (A or B), influential social justice scholar Van den Bos suggests that the term ‘fair process effect’ should be reserved for reactions that emerge out of perceived procedural fairness (causal flow B), and that effects of objective conditions on procedural fairness assessments (causal flow A) should be labeled ‘voice effects’.Footnote 10 While this is a laudable effort to highlight the distinction between the effects of objective procedural arrangements and subjective fairness assessments, there is no term for the total impact of objective conditions on reactions (causal flow A multiplied by causal flow B).

Moreover, it is common to blur the objective–subjective distinction by letting terms like ‘procedures’ and ‘procedural factors’ denote subjective assessments of procedural fairness (we do it ourselves in the introduction). A classic book in the field by Lind and Tyler spells out the logic involved: ‘In order to avoid awkwardness of expression, we often write procedural justice being high or low when what we mean is that those involved feel that the process was fair or unfair.’Footnote 11 This convention might facilitate the presentation of findings, but it obscures the crucial distinction between how decisions are actually made and people’s perceptions of these procedural arrangements.

HOW OUTCOME FAVORABILITY INTERVENES IN THE PROCESS

In addition to maintaining the objective–subjective distinction, a properly specified model must account for how outcome favorability shapes citizens’ reactions to authoritative decisions, such as the introduction of a congestion tax. It is tempting to equate outcome favorability – the degree to which a decision coincides with an individual’s preference – with self-interest. However, this is not correct. Why an individual prefers one decision over another is irrelevant. The preference may be based on self-interested considerations, or on factors such as high-minded values and pro-social preferences for distributive fairness. For instance, opponents to the congestion tax may believe that it disproportionally affects poor people who have no alternative to using a car. Figure 2 illustrates how outcome favorability may intervene in the causal flows of interest here.Footnote 12

Fig. 2 How outcome favorability may intervene in the process

First, outcome favorability may color procedural fairness assessments (causal flow C) and thereby indirectly affect decision acceptance (through causal flow B). Individuals who receive an unfavorable outcome (opponents of the congestion tax) will assess objective procedural arrangements more negatively than those who receive a favorable outcome (supporters of the congestion tax). Referring to the theory of directional motivated reasoning,Footnote 13 both psychologistsFootnote 14 and political scientistsFootnote 15 have argued that procedural assessments are indeed endogenous to outcome favorability.

It is clear from a large number of experimental studies that procedural fairness assessments are anchored to a degree in objective procedural arrangements (causal flow A).Footnote 16 However, as discussed above, this literature does not typically consider that even a moderately strong outcome favorability effect on procedural fairness perceptions (causal flow C) could undermine the objective fair process effect (A multiplied by B).

Secondly, outcome favorability may exert a direct effect on decision acceptance (causal flow D). When the direct effect is very strong, the subjective fair process effect (causal flow B) becomes substantially meaningless. Identifying a situation in which D dwarfs B, Skitka and colleagues argue that procedural fairness assessments are of little importance for individuals who have a strong moral conviction on the outcome.Footnote 17

OBJECTIVE ARRANGEMENTS FOR POLICY DECISIONS

Finally, an assessment of the procedure–acceptance connection must consider the objective arrangements that are available to democratic authorities. When theorizing about procedural arrangements, procedural fairness scholars have focused on three generic qualities: voice, consistency and dignity.Footnote 18 Voice, which is most frequently studied, is the opportunity for individuals to present their opinions in the decision-making process.Footnote 19 Consistency is the absence of systematic bias in the conduct of decision-making authorities.Footnote 20 Dignity is when authorities recognize individuals’ status as respected members of society during interactions.Footnote 21

Voice, consistency and dignity are theoretical constructs, the effects of which are commonly studied in isolation and in abstract laboratory milieus. However, in real-world democracies these procedural qualities are embedded in complex procedural arrangements. Further complicating inquiries into real-world conditions, there are fundamental procedural differences between implementation decisions in which the government exercises authority over individual citizens (such as when an authority rejects an application for a building permit) and policy decisions that affect many people simultaneously (such as a tax hike). As observed by social psychologists Leung, Tong and Lind, most procedural fairness research targets implementation decisions.Footnote 22 Because of this bias in previous research, we know comparatively little about the functioning of arrangements for policy decisions specifically.

Policy decisions are made by (a) elected representatives, (b) expert administrators in government agencies, (c) judges in the judiciary (if the constitution allows for judiciary review) and, less frequently, (d) citizens in referendums. Voice, dignity and consistency are part of all these generic policy-making arrangements, but each has additional qualities such as bringing expertise to the process.

To cover the means available to government authorities when deciding on policies, we need to make comparisons both among and within the respective types of generic procedural arrangements. Comparisons among such arrangements evaluate the extent to which it matters for decision acceptance that policies are decided by a particular generic arrangement (representative, expert, judicial and direct decision-making by the people). Correspondingly, comparisons within procedural arrangements evaluate the importance of following procedural standards for the respective type of arrangement (for example, the expectation that expert decision-makers are unbiased).

DESIGN, DATA AND MEASUREMENTS

To estimate all causal flows in the model we propose, a study must manipulate objective procedural arrangements and outcome favorability, and measure perceived procedural fairness and decision acceptance. Moreover, since our interest is in policy decisions, the study must be conducted in that context (and not in the context of implementation decisions).

In the vast procedural fairness literature, several lab experiments manipulate voice opportunities and outcome favorability in contexts that resemble implementation decisions.Footnote 23 However, since policy decisions are made using different procedural arrangements than implementation decisions, we should be cautious when generalizing between contexts.Footnote 24 Furthermore, it is important to note that many lab experiments on implementation decisions report outcome favorability effects that dwarf the objective procedural arrangement effect but regard them as manipulation checks that carry little substantial information.

The works by Skitka and Leung, Tong and Lind have sparked investigations into several of the causal processes that are central here,Footnote 25 for example how procedural fairness assessments are endogenous to outcome favorability (causal flows A and C),Footnote 26 how issue importance may undermine the subjective fair process effect (causal flow B)Footnote 27 and how voice affects fairness assessments in a policy decision (causal flow A).Footnote 28 However, while these and other studies report evidence on pieces of the puzzle, an account of the full range of relevant causal flows is missing in previous research.

Earle and Siegrist’s survey experiments in Switzerland and the United States come closest to studying the full range of causal flows in our suggested model. They find that procedural arrangements are inconsequential for outcome reactions when the policy issue is important for affected individuals.Footnote 29 While their study is developed within the framework of risk analysis, their findings fall well in line with our argument. However, Earle and Siegrist study general policy outcomes (‘strengthening laws and treaties’) rather than specific policy decisions, and the outcome of interest is citizens’ willingness to support the efforts of decision-makers rather than decision acceptance specifically. Moreover, their study only considers one type of variation within one type of decision-making arrangement (in an expert decision-making process, the public is, or is not, allowed a voice). Clearly, the generalizability of the results grows with the number of decision arrangements taken into account.

STUDY DESIGN

We will report findings from twenty-seven experiments that fulfill our design requirements, and from a complementary experiment designed to test the robustness of the findings. We present the results from such a large number of experiments in order to show that our results are robust when using different settings and specifications. The main experiments are vignette (eighteen) and field (nine).Footnote 30 Vignette experiments are standard in procedural fairness research, but field experiments are new to the subject area.Footnote 31 Given the many data collections, we focus here on fundamental design features. The online appendix contains the detailed protocols.

In our vignette experiments, subjects were initially presented with information regarding a certain policy issue (for instance, a proposition to ban religious symbols in school). Subjects were asked to imagine that a decision on the issue was to be made that would affect them personally (for instance, to ban religious symbols in all schools in their municipality) and they were then probed about their preferred outcome (whether they personally supported a ban). Following the lead of Van den Bos,Footnote 32 we thereafter primed procedural considerations by presenting subjects with a list of alternative decision-making arrangements as illustrated below:

The decision of whether to ban religious symbols in the schools in your municipality can be made in several different ways: One possibility is that the decision is made by expert administrators at the local school agency. Another possibility is that the decision is made by the politicians in the local council. A third possibility is that the decision is made by the citizens via referendum.

Following this, objective procedural arrangement and decision outcome were manipulated in the following manner:

Now that the time has come for your municipality to make the decision, the pros and cons of a ban have been debated in the media. Following the public debate, politicians in the local council // expert administrators at the local school agency // citizens in a referendum // make the final decision that religious symbols // should be banned // should not be banned // from the schools in your municipality.

To capture Outcome Favorability for each subject, the decision outcome was matched with subjects’ preferred outcome as reported prior to the treatments. While this means that the proportion of ‘winners’ and ‘losers’ is dependent on the opinion sentiments among subjects, the resulting variable is evenly distributed across treatments. The proportion of ‘winners’ in each experiment is reported in Appendix 3.Footnote 33 Perceived Procedural Fairness and Decision Acceptance were measured post-treatment.

In the field experiments, we provided a large number of high school classes with a substantial sum of money (on average, the equivalent of $290), and asked each class to decide whether to donate it to Doctors Without Borders or to keep it for a joint celebration.Footnote 34 The objective arrangements for reaching a decision were designed by us to replicate, on a small scale, decision making in large-scale democracies, and were randomly distributed across classes (for instance, the decision was made through a direct vote which was, or was not, fairly implemented).

The field experiment protocol followed the vignette experiments as closely as possible. Experimenters surveyed subjects for their favored outcome (to donate the money to charity, or to keep it for themselves), primed procedural considerations by reminding subjects that collective decisions can be made in different ways and then initiated a discussion of the merits of the two policy alternatives. When the intensity of the discussion began to fade (usually after about twenty minutes), subjects were surveyed again about their preferred outcome, and subsequently the decision was made using the randomly assigned procedural arrangement. Following the decision (our experimental manipulation), subjects assessed the fairness of the procedural arrangement that was used and stated their willingness to accept the decision.

Table 1 lists the key characteristics of the twenty-seven main experiments (E1–E27). To help readers keep track of individual studies, we include information about the study identifier from Table 1 throughout the remainder of the article and in the online appendix. The overall expectation is that objective procedural arrangements that include higher levels of personal involvement and openness will yield higher levels of perceived procedural fairness and – consequently – higher levels of decision acceptance.Footnote 35

Table 1 Characteristics of the Experiments

Experiments E1–E15 compare procedural arrangements among three generic arrangements: direct vote in a referendum, representative decision-making by elected representatives and administrative decision-making by expert bureaucrats. Given theoreticalFootnote 36 and empiricalFootnote 37 claims about the benefits of personal involvement in decision making, we contrast direct vote procedures with respective alternative arrangements.

The remaining twelve experiments (E16–E27) compare procedures within the respective procedural arrangement. Three studies focus on procedural qualities that are commonly studied in procedural fairness research: voice and consistency. E16 and E17 manipulate opportunities for voice in expert decision making and direct votingFootnote 38 (that is, subjects were, or were not, allowed to discuss the merits of the proposal). E18 manipulates the neutrality of the third-party instigator in a direct vote arrangement (experimenters did, or did not, interfere in favor of the alternative that lost the initial vote by forcing subjects to vote a second time).

The final nine experiments (E19–E27) target variations within procedural arrangements that are specific to policy decisions. These treatments are new to procedural fairness research, and since we have no clear expectation about which type of arrangement will matter the most for citizens, we have identified a broad set of potentially important factors. While we cannot refer to a theoretical selection criterion, each targeted procedural arrangement is anchored in the literature on democratic policy making.

Three experiments (E19–E21) target variations within direct voting procedures: secret versus open votingFootnote 39 and spiteful versus calm public discourse pre-decision.Footnote 40 Finally, six experiments (E22–E27) target variations within representative decision-making: representatives are elected in high- or low-turnout elections,Footnote 41 representatives are acting on bounded or unbounded mandates,Footnote 42 the representatives that are elected by subjects (in-group representatives) constitute a majority or minority in the decision-making body,Footnote 43 and representatives are elected or selected by lottery.Footnote 44

To further facilitate generalizability, experiments covered both regulatory and redistributive policy issues.Footnote 45 Our primary regulatory policy issues concerned a proposition to prohibit students in school from wearing religious symbols such as a veil or a necklace with a crucifix (E1–E4, E9–E12, E19, E21–E24, E26). The proposal was modeled on a policy controversy in French politics. Additionally, two vignette experiments (E5, E13) focused on teachers’ right to seize noisy cell phones from students.

Our redistributive policy issue is the proposal to donate money to charity or to keep it for a festivity. For experimental subjects, the proposal represents a choice between spending money on one’s own welfare or redistributing the resources to the more needy. It was used throughout all the field studies (E7, E8, E15–E18, E20, E25, E27) and in two vignette experiments (E6, E14).

Lastly, to ensure that the results can be generalized to political controversies in large-scale democracy, our complementary experiment comprises a policy issue that at the time of the study was high on the national political agenda (to allow a local ban on begging). In the experiment, the decision was taken either by elected representatives or citizens in a referendum. The results of this robustness test will be reported separately following the main analysis.

CONTEXT AND SUBJECTS

The country context for our studies is Sweden. Since procedural effects have been reported more or less universally across economically developed countries, country context is not as important as the design and we had the ability to collect relevant data in Sweden.

For reasons of accessibility, subjects were predominantly high school students. Some would question the use of young citizens (ages sixteen to nineteen) for this purpose. While understandable, we believe the use of student subjects can be justified. Developmental psychologists have shown that high school students in contexts as diverse as Canada and China hold attitudes toward government that are similar to both each other and to the attitudes of adults.Footnote 46 In support of this argument, the experiments with young subjects reproduce the expected findings from previous research.

Moreover, we did study adult subjects in vignette experiments in a large-scale democracy setting (E1, E9) and in a school setting (E2, E10), as well as political science undergraduates in a large-scale democracy setting (E4, E12). As reported below, the results for both adults and political science undergraduates confirm what we found among high school students. Finally, we run a complementary experiment (E28) on a random sample of adult Swedes. Easing remaining doubts, this robustness test confirms the findings of our main experiments.

Adult subjects in the main experiments (E1 and E9) were recruited among travelers by bus and train at Gothenburg Central Station. The resulting diverse sample is somewhat skewed toward the elderly, but bears a reasonable resemblance to the general population (51 per cent females, N=451). Adults in the school setting were recruited in connection to a one-day internal seminar for teachers and other school personnel in the Gothenburg metropolitan area (50 per cent females, N=259). Political science students were recruited in connection to lectures at the University of Gothenburg and Lund University (53 per cent females, N=126).

Young subjects in the vignette experiments were recruited from high schools in the metropolitan areas of Gothenburg and Stockholm (173≤N≥284). All experimental sessions took place in the subjects’ schools and were integrated into the lessons. One field experiment involved twenty-one school classes (the level at which randomization was made) and 483 subjects at one high school unit; the other involved twelve school classes and 215 subjects at three high school units (all schools were in the Gothenburg metropolitan area). Each analysis involves a minimum of six school classes and ninety-five subjects.

We used political interest, left-right self-placement and gender as randomization controls. Appendix Tables A2a and A2b provide the results of the randomization checks: they show that in 86 per cent of cases, the covariates are balanced between the treatment groups. The validity of our manipulations is discussed in the Results section.

MEASUREMENTS AND MODELING STRATEGY

Measurements of procedural fairness and decision acceptance were identical in all experiments. Perceived procedural fairness was captured by the item, ‘How fair do you think matters were when the decision was made?’Footnote 47 Taking into account the nuances that are lost in translation, this is similar to standard indicators in procedural fairness research.Footnote 48 Decision acceptance was measured with the item, ‘How willing are you to accept and comply with the decision?’ On both items, responses were registered on seven-point scales with designated endpoints.

The use of generally phrased measurements allows us to compare across decision-making arrangements and policy issues. For a validity test we have employed additional measures in several of the experiments. Whether the measures of perceived procedural fairness are generally phrased (‘How fairly do you think you were treated when the decision was taken?’) or adapted to specific procedural arrangements (‘To what extent do you feel that you personally could affect the decision?’), all items are highly internally correlated (the inter-item simple correlation coefficient typically varies between 0.70 and 0.84). This suggests that the results are insensitive to the choice of precise indicator.Footnote 49 As a final precaution, we included additional measurements in the complementary experiment that will be reported below.

To facilitate interpretation and comparisons of effects, all independent variables are recoded to vary between 0 and 1. We use structural equation modeling (SEM) for estimates of direct and indirect effects to allow us to simultaneously estimate the different regression paths via mediators.Footnote 50 The significance tests of the indirect effects are performed with the bias-corrected percentile interval bootstrap tests (using 1,000 bootstrap sample draws). This is a more robust estimation method than other tests of indirect effects such as the traditional Sobel test.Footnote 51

In the first step we regress perceived procedural fairness on objective procedural arrangements and outcome favorability, and in the second step decision acceptance is regressed on perceived procedural fairness, decision-making arrangements and outcome favorability. This SEM model specification allows us to estimate the direct, indirect and total effects of the main independent variables in our framework on decision acceptance.

RESULTS

We begin by testing support for the notion that outcome favorability is of primary importance for decision acceptance. Our experimental design allows for a straightforward test of the proposition: we need only to estimate the total (main) effect of the objective procedural arrangement and outcome favorability on decision acceptance. To facilitate subsequent analysis, we employ SEM modeling, and express estimates in the form of unstandardized SEM regression coefficients.

The results presented in Figures 3 and 4 provide strong support for our proposition. The total outcome favorability effect is consistently about twice as strong as the total effect that follows from the objective procedural arrangement. This is the case for both comparisons between procedural arrangements (Figure 3) and within procedural arrangements (Figure 4).

Fig. 3 Total effects on decision acceptance, amongactual decision-making arrangements

Fig. 4 Total effects on decision acceptance, within actual decision-making arrangements

Note that the results in Figure 3 represent the effects of letting the people decide by a direct vote rather than having experts or elected representatives make the decision. This is probably the single-most effective procedural arrangement available to democratic authorities in search of citizen acceptance of policy decisions, and in most polities it can only be used on rare occasions. If we instead focus on the more realistic procedural alternatives and compare expert decision making and representative decision-making, the results are even less impressive. In fact, whether the decisions were made by experts or elected representatives rarely made a difference in our subjects’ decision acceptance.

Having documented support for our main claim, we turn attention to the causal processes that generate the observed outcome. To reiterate, we expect to find that procedural fairness assessments are anchored to a degree in objective procedural conditions (causal flow A), and that these fairness assessments are linked to decision acceptance (causal flow B), but also that outcome favorability directly influences procedural fairness assessments (causal flow C) and decision acceptance (causal flow D).

We estimate SEM models for the mediated and unmediated effects of theoretical interest for each experimental comparison. To confirm that the variable Perceived Procedural Fairness mediates all causality that originates from objective procedural arrangements (an assumption in procedural fairness theory), we also allow for a (non-theorized) direct effect of the procedural arrangement on decision acceptance (that we label E). To save space, and since the results are largely consistent across studies, we only show one experimental comparison graphically, E1, which involves adults who react to a decision to ban religious symbols in schools that is made by local citizens in a referendum or by expert administrators on the local school board (Figure 5). The results from all twenty-seven studies are presented in Table 2.

Fig. 5 Effects on decision acceptance, SEM estimates Note: * p<0.05.

Table 2 Effects on Decision Acceptance

Note: unstandardized SEM coefficients. Standard errors in parentheses are observed information matrix standard errors for the direct effects in the vignette experiments, clustered robust standard errors at the class level for the direct effects in the field experiments, and bootstrapped standard errors (1,000 draws) for the indirect and total effects in both vignette and field experiments. Significance levels are corroborated with bias-corrected percentile interval bootstrap tests. * p<0.05.

With few exceptions, our data reproduce the two typical findings from previous research. In E1 and all other experimental comparisons, perceived procedural fairness has a statistically significant effect on decision acceptance (causal flow B). Correspondingly, the objective procedural arrangement has a significant effect on perceived procedural fairness in E1 and eighteen other studies (causal flow A). Moreover, corroborating that the variable Perceived Procedural Fairness captures the expected causal flows, only two studies (E18, E27) show a statistically significant and positive unmediated (non-theorized) effect of the objective procedural arrangement on decision acceptance (causal flow E).

As a validity check of our manipulations, we take a closer look at the studies in which procedural fairness assessments are decoupled from objective procedural arrangements (causal flow A is not significant). Most of these studies (six of eight) target within-arrangement comparisons. At first glance, it seems problematic that a voice manipulation in E17 failed to generate a statistically significant effect on perceived procedural fairness. However, the lack of effect is less remarkable considering that voice was manipulated in the context of a direct vote procedure (subjects were or were not allowed to discuss before a use-of-money decision was made in a direct vote). Thus while voice manipulations typically generate effects, the results from E17 suggest that adding voice to an arrangement in which subjects have other opportunities to engage in decision-making does not contribute to procedural fairness assessments.

The remaining five studies manipulate objective procedural arrangements that are specific to policy decisions, and as such have not been previously noticed by procedural fairness scholars: secret versus open voting (E20), calm versus spiteful discourse (E21), in-group dominance versus out-group dominance in the representative assembly (E22), unbounded versus bounded mandates (E25) and lottery-based versus election-based representation (E27). The fact that these manipulations fail to generate higher procedural fairness assessments (while outcome favorability does) is interesting for our understanding of policy decision-making processes and does not undermine the reliability of the data. Importantly, as we have seventeen experimental comparisons that reproduce all typical findings from previous research, our overall conclusion is not driven by the deviant cases.

Turning to the predictions that distinguish our study from conventional research in the field, we begin with causal flow C, which connects procedural assessments with outcomes. Confirming expectations, outcome favorability has a positive and statistically significant effect on perceived procedural fairness in twenty-five of twenty-seven studies. This is strong evidence that procedural fairness assessments are endogenous to the outcomes people are exposed to, especially since effect sizes are frequently on a par with, or stronger than, the effect of the objective procedural arrangement.

Support is even stronger for the second prediction, that outcomes directly affect the willingness to accept decisions (casual flow D). We register a positive and statistically significant effect of outcome favorability on decision acceptance in twenty-six of twenty-seven studies. In sum, we can conclude that when situated in a properly specified model, objective procedural arrangements are much less important than a favorable outcome for an individual’s willingness to accept policy decisions.

Returning finally to the subjective procedural fairness effect (causal flow B), it is clear from our experiments that procedural fairness assessments are strongly connected to decision acceptance. Moreover, as evidenced here and in previous research, this is also true in comparison with the direct effect of outcome favorability. However, to understand the role of procedures for decision acceptance we must account for the fact that they are endogenous to outcome favorability. In other words, procedural assessments are not only affected by objective arrangements; they are also heavily affected by outcome favorability. So while procedural considerations figure prominently in people’s minds when they react to policy decisions, it is unwarranted to conclude that they would have reacted much differently if the same decisions had been made using other another procedural arrangement.

A ROBUSTNESS TEST

To strengthen beliefs in our findings, we conducted a robustness test that addresses three concerns: (a) that we rely on non-probability samples consisting mostly of young citizens, (b) that we study policy issues that have a limited bearing on policy controversies in the real world and (c) that we rely on indicators of procedural fairness and decision acceptance that are imprecise measures of the underlying theoretical concepts.

To address these concerns, we designed a complementary vignette experiment (E28). To address (a), the experiment was run on a probability sample of the adult Swedish population. The fieldwork was conducted by the well-reputed survey company Novus, using their web-based ‘Sweden panel’. The panel consists of randomly selected Swedes aged eighteen to seventy-nine who are recruited into the panel by telephone (mainly). The participation rate in our study was 56 per cent, which yielded 1,001 responses.Footnote 52

To address (b), the experiment targeted a policy controversy that was high on the national political agenda at the time of the study – whether to allow a local ban on begging. The issue has arisen as a result of a large influx of poor migrants of primarily Romani origin. Using the protocol from the main experiments, subjects were presented the following scenario: ‘In the debate it is sometimes discussed that municipalities should be able to ban begging within its borders. What do you think about banning begging in the municipality where you live?’

To address (c), we included additional indicators of perceived procedural fairness and decision acceptance: ‘How just do you think that the decision process was?’ and ‘When it comes to follow or oppose the decision to ban begging // not to ban begging, where would you place yourself?’ As in the main experiments, responses were registered on seven-point scales with designated endpoints.

To make a good case for objective procedural arrangements, the experiment contrasted direct decision-making by referendum with representative decision-making. Using the protocol from the main experiments, respondents were randomly assigned to one of four treatments informing them (i) that the decision was taken by citizens in a local referendum // by the political representatives in the local municipality council and (ii) that the outcome of the decision was to ban begging in their municipality // not to ban begging in their municipality. Randomization checks confirmed that treatment groups were balanced with regard to education, age, gender and civil status.

We use an identical model specification to that in the main analyses and present the results in the left-most column in Table 3. The findings from the main experiments are replicated: perceived procedural fairness has a statistically significant effect on decision acceptance, and both the objective procedural arrangement (to decide by referendum rather than by representative decision-making) and outcome favorability have a significant effect on perceived procedural fairness. The total effect of objective procedural arrangement on decision acceptance is substantially small and not statistically significant. In contrast, the total effect of outcome favorability is significant and large in magnitude.

Table 3 Robustness Check: Testing the Relationship in a Population-based Survey Experiment (E28)

Note: unstandardized SEM coefficients. Standard errors in parentheses are observed information matrix standard errors for the direct effects in the bootstrapped standard errors (1,000 draws) for the indirect and total effects. Significance levels are corroborated with bias-corrected percentile interval bootstrap tests. * p<0.05.

In the right-most column in Table 3 we present corresponding results employing the alternative indicators. Overall, the results are replicated: the total effect of outcome favorability is large and strong, while the objective procedural arrangement has an even weaker effect than in the previous model. And again we see strong effects from outcome favorability via perceived procedural fairness regarding decision acceptance.

Hence, the results from the complementary study confirm that our results are not an artifact of the specific item construction employed in the main experiments, and that the same general pattern is found in a random sample of the population and for a real-world policy controversy.

CONCLUSION

This article takes a new look at the procedure–acceptance connection in the domain of policy decisions. Our core claim is that a democratic government in search of citizen acceptance of difficult decisions is little helped by the procedural means at its disposal. In line with procedural fairness theory, our experimental data show that objective procedural arrangements affect subjective procedural fairness assessments, and that subjective fairness assessments are linked to decision acceptance. Nevertheless, when following the causal flow from objective procedural arrangements to decision acceptance, and when taking outcome favorability into account, outcome favorability is the dominant determinant of decision acceptance. These findings are consistent across regulatory and distributive policy issues, across large-scale democracy and school settings, across comparisons among and within decision-making arrangements, and across vignette and field experiments.

Based on this article, we have three recommendations for future research on the procedure–acceptance connection: first, to carefully maintain the distinction between objective procedural arrangements and subjective procedural fairness assessments; secondly, to make sure that outcome favorability is fully integrated into the analysis; and thirdly, to not only study individual-level decisions, as in citizen encounters with legal authorities and street-level bureaucrats, but also policy decisions that affect large groups of citizens simultaneously. The latter recommendation is perhaps particularly important. Is it the case, as suggested by Leung, Tong and Lind,Footnote 53 that procedural factors matter less when citizens react collectively to, for example, tax increases and regulation of internet use than when they are subject to decisions from planning authorities and the police?

A further topic for research is the nature of the subjective procedural fairness effect (causal flow B). To put our favored hypothesis through a tough test, we have assumed a unidirectional causal relationship from fairness assessments to decision acceptance. Since we are dealing with two closely associated attitudinal variables, this is likely an oversimplification of the true relationship. For instance, one possibility to consider is conceptual overlap: one study of people’s spontaneous definitions of fair outcomes finds fuzzy boundaries between procedures and outcomes, suggesting that this may be a problem.Footnote 54

Reflecting on authoritative decision-making in the real world, our results help to put procedural theory in perspective. We maintain that proponents of procedural fairness theory have been overly optimistic about democratic governments’ ability to use procedural means to gain citizen acceptance of difficult policy decisions. Consider a decent democratic authority that is about to make a decision on a controversial collective matter and that wants both policy winners and losers to accept the outcome. As unfortunate as it may sound, it is unlikely that it has much to gain from trying to improve upon its current decision-making arrangements.

Regarding the scope of the argument, our focus here is on acceptance of specific policy decisions. Procedural justice researchers are increasingly emphasizing that procedural factors have long-term effects on the legitimacy of democratic authorities.Footnote 55 The long-term perspective gives relevance to the finding that people’s procedural fairness assessments are anchored to a degree in objective procedural arrangements. Even though people are unwilling to accept particular policy decisions because of the way they are made, fair decision-making arrangements may help to build long-term trust in authorities. Leung, Tong and Lind make a similar argument that procedural justice, collective outcomes and group identification play out differently in evaluations of authorities than in reactions to specific policy decisions.Footnote 56

Finally, we want to stress a point in relation to the general relevance of objective procedural arrangements. Agreement on procedures is a civilized way to solve collective decision-making problems.Footnote 57 Our study is a reminder that this insight needs to be repeated over and over again. For example, a democratic polity about to reach a decision on a controversial matter should discuss not only the pros and cons of policy options, but also the harsh reality that not all of us will get what we want on every issue. In the real world, sometimes the best we can hope for is that the decision is made according to acceptable procedural standards.

ACKNOWLEDGEMENT

Earlier versions of this article have been presented at the ECPR General Conference in Pisa, MPSA Meeting in Chicago, and a workshop on experimental research in Åbo. We are grateful to Jenny De Fine Licht, John Geer, Marcia Grimes, Andrej Kokkonen, Sofie Marien, Anders Sundell, and Chris Wlezien as well as the editors and three anonymous reviewers of the BJPS for their helpful comments and suggestions. We thank Ola Jodal, Martin Johansson, Jenny De Fine Licht, Jakob Lindahl, Erica Litzén, Anders Sundell and Rebecka Åsbrink for helping out with the data collection.

This research was supported by Grant no. 721-2004-3445 from the Swedish Research Council and Grant no. P10-0210:1 from Riksbankens Jubileumsfond (The Swedish Bank of Tercentenary Foundation).

Footnotes

*

Department of Political Science, University of Gothenburg, Sweden (email: [email protected]); Department of Political Science, University of Gothenburg (email: [email protected]); Department of Political Science, University of Gothenburg (email: [email protected]); Department of Psychology, Stockholm University, Sweden (email: [email protected]). Data replication sets are available at http://dataverse.harvard.edu/dataverse/BJPolS and online appendices are available at http://dx.doi.org/doi:10.1017/S0007123416000508.

1 E.g., Gangl Reference Gangl2003; Gibson 1989; Grimes Reference Grimes2006; Hibbing and Alford Reference Hibbing and Alford2004; Tyler Reference Tyler1990; Ulbig Reference Ulbig2008.

2 Tyler Reference Tyler2011, 14.

4 While usually less drastically expressed, this claim represents conventional wisdom: ‘(P)rocedural fairness has been shown to have substantial effects on virtually all important organizational outcomes’ (van Houwelingen, van Dijke, and De Cremer Reference Van Houwelingen, van Dijke and De Cremer2014); ‘A major reason why procedural justice is of interest for political theorists is its ability to lessen the impact of unpleasant decisions’ (Klosko Reference Klosko2000, 210); ‘Findings such as these suggest that experiencing fair procedures builds social values, and these values lead people to feel a long-lasting, personal obligation to accept decisions and support rules’ (Hechter Reference Hechter2013, 20).

5 Lind and Tyler Reference Lind and Tyler1988; Tyler et al. Reference Tyler, Boeckmann, Smith and Huo1997. Fair procedures are important because they: signal to people that they are respected by decision-makers (Tyler Reference Tyler1994; Tyler and Lind Reference Tyler and Lind1992), show that decision-makers can be trusted (Brockner Reference Brockner2002), enable individuals to reduce uncertainty about how to evaluate outcomes (Van den Bos and Lind Reference Van den Bos and Lind2002), are morally imperative (Folger, Cropanzano, and Goldman Reference Folger, Cropanzano and Goldman2005; Miller Reference Miller2001), lead to fair decisions, and possibly increase individuals’ chances of receiving a favorable outcome (Thibaut and Walker Reference Thibaut and Walker1975). The importance of fair procedures can also be expressed within a rational framework: people have preferences about how outcomes are generated, and when fulfilled, these preferences generate utility (Frey, Benz, and Stutzer Reference Frey, Benz and Stutzer2004). Recently, it has been argued that a concern about procedural fairness is the result of human evolutionary history (Bøggild and Petersen 2016).

8 Earle and Siegrist (Reference Earle and Siegrist2008) is an exception.

9 In an early phase of this project (in 2009), we surveyed 500 journal articles on procedural fairness theory. Of these, only fifty-two employed experimental manipulations of objective procedural arrangements (the remaining studies are observational and hence only study causal flow B). Of the experimental articles, only three targeted decision acceptance specifically, and no article systematically compared the strength of the respective causal flow (A and B). These proportions have not changed substantially in the more recent literature (for recent studies that focus explicitly on acceptance of policy decisions, see Gash and Murakami (2015) and Towfigh et al. 2016). See the online appendix for a detailed account of the systematic literature review.

10 Van den Bos Reference Van den Bos2005. The label ‘voice effect’ for causal flow A reflects that many social psychologists consider affected individuals’ ability to express their opinion about a decision to be the single-most important procedural quality.

11 Lind and Tyler Reference Lind and Tyler1988, 4.

12 Mullen and Skitka Reference Mullen and Skitka2006; Skitka Reference Skitka2002. Another alternative discussed in the literature is that outcome favorability interacts with subjective procedural fairness assessments to mitigate negative reactions to an unfavorable outcome (e.g., Bianchi et al. Reference Bianchi, Brockner, Van den Bos, Seifert, Moon, van Diljke and De Cremer2015). Since we found no evidence of interaction effects in our data, we left out this possibility.

15 Doherty and Wolak Reference Doherty and Wolak2012.

16 E.g., Folger Reference Folger1977; Van Prooijen, Van den Bos, and Wilke Reference Van Prooijen, Van den Bos and Wilke2004.

17 For a critique of this so-called moral mandate theory, see Napier and Tyler (Reference Napier and Tyler2008).

18 For a review, see Skitka and Wisneski (Reference Skitka and Wisneski2012).

19 De Cremer and Tyler Reference De Cremer and Tyler2007.

20 Crosby and Franco Reference Crosby and Franco2003.

21 Bies and Moag Reference Bies and Moag1986; Tyler and Blader 2003. Speaking of the complexity of psychological research on social justice, it is debated whether reactions to dignity processes are a separate form of ‘interactional justice’, which are distinguishable from procedural justice (e.g., Bies Reference Bies2005).

22 Leung, Tong, and Lind Reference Leung, Tong and Lind2007.

24 Leung, Tong, and Lind Reference Leung, Tong and Lind2007.

25 Leung, Tong, and Lind Reference Leung, Tong and Lind2007; Skitka Reference Skitka2002.

26 Doherty and Wolak Reference Doherty and Wolak2012.

29 Earle and Siegrist Reference Earle and Siegrist2008.

30 Experiments were embedded in twelve original data collections, of which ten used vignettes for treatment, and two were conducted in the field.

31 With a relatively low degree of ‘fieldness’ (Gerber and Green Reference Gerbner and Green2012, 8–13), our experiments might also be labeled ‘lab in the field’ (Morton and Williams Reference Morton and Williams2010, 296).

32 Van den Bos Reference Van den Bos2001.

33 We found no difference in reactions among the different types of losers and winners (for example, losers who opposed a proposition but received a ‘pro’ decision did not react differently from losers who favored a proposition but received a ‘con’ decision). Therefore, to save resources, the decision outcome was held constant in six of the later experiments (see the online appendix).

34 In our country context, and different from the US educational system, high school classes are stable social units that study most subfields together during their entire education. From a theoretical point of view, our field experiments are thus set in a large number of natural collectives of individuals with a shared history and future.

35 Esaiasson, Gilljam and Persson Reference Esaiasson, Gilljam and Persson2012.

36 Pateman Reference Pateman1970, 26–7.

37 Dalton and Welzel Reference Dalton and Welzien2014; Gibson, Caldeira, and Kenyatta Spence Reference Gibson, Caldeira and Kenyatta Spence2005; Lupia and Matsusaka Reference Lupia and Matsusaka2004; Smith and Tolbert Reference Smith and Tolbert2004; Mikael Gilljam 2009.

38 Mikael Persson 2013.

39 E.g., Brennan and Pettit Reference Brennan and Pettit1990.

40 E.g., Shea and Fiorina Reference Shea and Fiorina2013.

41 E.g., Lijphart Reference Lijphart2000.

43 E.g., Phillips Reference Phillips1995.

44 E.g., Manin Reference Manin1997.

45 E.g., Lowi Reference Lowi1972.

47 ‘Hur rättvist tycker du att det gick till när beslutet fattades?’ in the original.

48 E.g., Skitka, Winquist, and Hutchinson Reference Skitka, Winquist and Hutchinson2003.

49 Moreover, in the field experiments we included a measure of decision acceptance which more directly targeted behavioral reactions: ‘When it comes to comply with, or work against, the decision, where would you place yourself?’ (response scales 1–7). Overall, results are consistent with those presented in the main analyses (see Appendix Table A1).

50 Cf. Muthen and Muthen 1998–2010.

51 Shrout and Bolger Reference Shrout and Bolger2002.

52 For more information about the sample, see http://novus.se/vara-tjanster/sverigepanel/.

53 Leung, Tong, and Lind Reference Leung, Tong and Lind2007.

55 E.g., Tyler Reference Tyler2006.

56 Leung, Tong, and Lind Reference Leung, Tong and Lind2007.

57 Cf. Klosko Reference Klosko2000, 208–46.

References

REFERENCES

Ambrose, Maureen. 2002. Contemporary Justice Research: A New Look at Familiar Questions. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 89:803812.Google Scholar
Bianchi, Emily, Brockner, Joel, Van den Bos, Kees, Seifert, Matthias, Moon, Henry, van Diljke, Marius, and De Cremer, David. 2015. Trust in Decision-Making Authorities Dictates the Form of the Interactive Relationship Between Outcome Fairness and Procedural Fairness. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 41:1934.Google Scholar
Bies, Robert. 2005. Are Procedural Justice and Interactional Justice Conceptually Distinct?. In Handbook of Organizational Justice, edited by Jerald Greenberg and Jason Colquitt, 85112. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.Google Scholar
Bies, Robert, and Moag, Joseph. 1986. Interactional Justice: Communication Criteria of Fairness. In Research on Negotiation in Organizations, edited by R. Lewicki, B. Sheppard and M. Bazerman, 4355. Greenwich, CT: JAI Press.Google Scholar
Brennan, Geoffrey, and Pettit, Philip. 1990. Unveiling the Vote. British Journal of Political Science 20:311333.Google Scholar
Brockner, Joel. 2002. Making Sense of Procedural Fairness: How High Procedural Fairness Can Reduce or Heighten the Influence of Outcome Favorability. Academy of Management Review 27:5876.Google Scholar
Colquitt, Jason, and Chertkoff, Jerome. 2002. Explaining Injustice: The Interactive Effect of Explanation and Outcome on Fairness Perceptions and Task Motivation. Journal of Management 28:591610.Google Scholar
Crosby, Faye, and Franco, Jamie L.. 2003. Connections Between the Ivory Tower and the Multicolored World: Linking Abstract Theories of Social Justice to the Rough and Tumble of Affirmative Action. Personality and Social Psychology Review 7:362373.Google Scholar
Dalton, Russell, and Welzien, Christopher, eds. 2014. The Civic Culture Transformed. From Allegiant to Assertive Citizens. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
De Cremer, David, and Tyler, Tom. 2007. The Effects of Trust and Procedural Justice on Cooperation. Journal of Applied Psychology 92:639649.Google Scholar
Doherty, David, and Wolak, Jennifer. 2012. When Do the Ends Justify the Means? Evaluating Procedural Fairness. Political Behavior 34:301323.Google Scholar
Earle, Timothy, and Siegrist, Michael. 2008. On the Relation Between Trust and Fairness in Environmental Risk Management. Risk Analysis 28:13951413.Google Scholar
Ellenbroek, Moniek, Verkuyten, Maykel, Thus, Jochem, and Poppe, Edwin. 2014. The Fairness of National Decision-Making Procedures: The Views of Adolescents in 18 European Countries. Journal of Community & Applied Social Psychology 24:503517.Google Scholar
Esaiasson, Peter, Gilljam, Mikael, and Persson, Mikael. 2012. Which Decision-Making Arrangements Generate the Strongest Legitimacy Beliefs? Evidence from a Randomised Field Experiment. European Journal of Political Research 51:785808.Google Scholar
Eulau, Heinz, Wahlke, John, Buchanan, William, and Ferguson, Leroy. 1959. The Role of the Representative: Some Empirical Observations on the Theory of Edmund Burke. American Political Science Review 53:742775.Google Scholar
Folger, Robert. 1977. Distributive and Procedural Justice: Combined Impact of ‘Voice’ and Improvement on Experienced Inequity. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 35:108119.Google Scholar
Folger, Robert. 1984. Emerging Issues in the Social Psychology of Justice. In The Sense of Injustice: Social Psychological Perspectives, edited by Roger Folger, 324. New York: Plenum.Google Scholar
Folger, Robert, Cropanzano, Russell, and Goldman, Barry. 2005. What is the Relationship Between Justice and Morality?. In Handbook of Organizational Justice, edited by Jerald Greenberg and Jason Colquitt, 215245. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.Google Scholar
Frey, Bruno, Benz, Matthias, and Stutzer, Alois. 2004. Introducing Procedural Utility: Not Only What, But Also How Matters. Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics 160:377401.Google Scholar
Gangl, Amy. 2003. Procedural Justice Theory and Evaluations of the Lawmaking Process. Political Behavior 25:119149.Google Scholar
Gerbner, Alan, and Green, Donald. 2012. Field Experiments. Design, Analysis and Interpretation. New York: Norton.Google Scholar
Gibson, James, Caldeira, Gregory, and Kenyatta Spence, Lester. 2005. Why Do People Accept Public Policies They Oppose? Testing Legitimacy Theory with a Survey-Based Experiment. Political Research Quarterly 58:187201.Google Scholar
Gilljam, Mikael, Esaiasson, Peter, and Lindholm, Torun. 2009. The Voice of the Pupils: An Experimental Comparison of Decisions Made by Elected Pupil Councils, Pupils in Referenda, and Teaching Staff. Educational Assessment, Evaluation and Accountability 22:7388.Google Scholar
Grimes, Marcia. 2006. Organizing Consent: The Role of Procedural Fairness in Political Trust and Compliance. European Journal of Political Research 45:285315.Google Scholar
Hechter, Michael. 2013. Alien Rule. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Helwig, Charles, Arnold, Mary Louise, Tan, Dingliang, and Boyd, Dwight. 2007. Mainland Chinese and Canadian Adolescents’ Judgments and Reasoning About the Fairness of Democratic and Other Forms of Government. Cognitive Development 22:96109.Google Scholar
Hibbing, John, and Alford, John. 2004. Accepting Authoritative Decisions: Humans as Wary Cooperators. American Journal of Political Science 48:6276.Google Scholar
Klosko, George. 2000. Democratic Procedures and Liberal Consensus. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kunda, Ziva. 1990. The Case for Motivated Reasoning. Psychological Bulletin 108:480498.Google Scholar
Leung, Kwok, Tong, Kwok-Kit, and Lind, Allan. 2007. Realpolitik Versus Fair Process: Moderating Effects of Group Identification on Acceptance of Political Decisions. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 92:476489.Google Scholar
Levi, Margaret, and Stoker, Laura. 2000. Political Trust and Trustworthiness. Annual Review of Political Science 3:475513.Google Scholar
Lijphart, Arend. 2000. Turnout. In International Encyclopedia of Elections, edited by Richard Rose, 314322. Oxford: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Lind, Allan, and Tyler, Tom R.. 1988. The Social Psychology of Procedural Justice. London: Plenum Press.Google Scholar
Lodge, Milton, and Taber, Charles. 2014. The Rationalizing Voter. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Lowi, Theodore. 1972. Four Systems of Policy, Politics and Choice. Public Administration Review 33:298310.Google Scholar
Lupfer, Michael, Weeks, Kelly, Doan, Kelly, and Houston, David. 2000. Folk Conceptions of Fairness and Unfairness. European Journal of Social Psychology 30:405428.Google Scholar
Lupia, Arthur, and Matsusaka, John. 2004. Direct Democracy: New Approaches to Old Questions. Annual Review of Political Science 7:463482.Google Scholar
MacCoun, Robert. 2005. Voice, Control and Belonging: The Double-Edged Sword of Procedural Fairness. Annual Review of Law and Social Science 1:171201.Google Scholar
Manin, Bernhard. 1997. The Principles of Representative Government. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Mayer, David, Greenbaum, Rebecca, Kuenzi, Maribeth, and Shteynberg, Garriy. 2009. When Do Fair Procedures Not Matter? A Test of the Identity Violation Effect. Journal of Applied Psychology 94:142161.Google Scholar
Miller, Dale. 2001. Disrespect and the Experience of Injustice. Annual Review of Psychology 52:527553.Google Scholar
Morton, Rebecca, and Williams, Kenneth. 2010. Experimental Political Science and the Study of Causality: From Nature to the Lab. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Mullen, Elizabeth, and Skitka, Linda. 2006. Exploring the Psychological Underpinnings of the Moral Mandate Effect: Motivated Reasoning, Identification, or Affect? Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 90:629643.Google Scholar
Muthen, Linda, and Bengt, Muthen. 1998–2010. Mplus Users’ Guide, 6th Edition, Los Angeles, CA: Muthen and Muthen.Google Scholar
Napier, Jamie, and Tyler, Tom. 2008. Does Moral Conviction Really Override Concerns About Procedural Justice? Social Justice Research 22:509528.Google Scholar
Pateman, Carole. 1970. Participation and Democratic Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Persson, Mikael, Esaiasson, Peter and Gilljam, Mikael. 2013. The Effects of Direct Voting and Deliberation on Legitimacy Beliefs: An Experimental Study of Decision-Making in Small Groups. European Political Science Review 5:381399.Google Scholar
Phillips, Anne. 1995. The Politics of Presence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Shea, Daniel, and Fiorina, Morris. 2013. Can We Talk? The Rise of Rude, Nasty, Stubborn Politics. New York: Pearson.Google Scholar
Shrout, Patrick, and Bolger, Niall. 2002. Mediation in Experimental and Non-Experimental Studies: New Procedures and Recommendations. Psychological Methods 7:422445.Google Scholar
Skitka, Linda. 2002. Do the Means Always Justify the Ends or Do the Ends Sometimes Justify the Means? A Value Protection Model of Justice Reasoning. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 28:588597.Google Scholar
Skitka, Linda, and Houston, David. 2001. When Due Process Is of No Consequence: Moral Mandates and Presumed Defendant Guilt or Innocence. Social Justice Research 14:305326.Google Scholar
Skitka, Linda, and Mullen, Elizabeth. 2008. Moral Convictions Often Override Concerns About Procedural Fairness. A Reply to Napier and Tyler. Social Justice Research 22:529546.Google Scholar
Skitka, Linda, Winquist, Jennifer, and Hutchinson, Susan. 2003. Are Outcome Fairness and Outcome Favorability Distinguishable Psychological Constructs? A Meta-Analytic Review. Social Justice Research 16:309341.Google Scholar
Skitka, Linda, and Wisneski, Daniel. 2012. Justice Theory and Research: A Social Functionalist Perspective. In Handbook of Psychology. Volume 5: Personality and Social Psychology, edited by Irving Weiner, Howard Tennen and Jerry Suls, 407428. Hoboken, NJ: John Wiley and Sons.Google Scholar
Smith, Daniel, and Tolbert, Caroline. 2004. Educated by Initiative: The Effects of Direct Democracy on Citizens and Political Organizations in the American States. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.Google Scholar
Taber, Charles, and Lodge, Milton. 2006. Motivated Skepticism in the Evaluation of Political Beliefs. American Journal of Political Science 503:755769.Google Scholar
Terwel, Bart, Harinck, Fieke, Ellemers, Naomi, and Daamen, Dancker. 2010. Voice in Political Decision Making: The Effect of Group Voice on Perceived Trustworthiness of Decision Makers and Subsequent Acceptance of Decisions. Journal of Experimental Psychology 16:173186.Google Scholar
Thibaut, John, and Walker, Laurens. 1975. Procedural Justice: A Psychological Analysis. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.Google Scholar
Tyler, Tom. 1990. Why People Obey the Law: Procedural Justice, Legitimacy and Compliance. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Tyler, Tom. 1994. Governing and Diversity: The Effect of Fair Decision-Making Procedures on the Legitimacy of Government. Law and Society Review 28:809831.Google Scholar
Tyler, Tom. 2000. Social Justice: Outcome and Procedure. International Journal of Psychology 35:117125.Google Scholar
Tyler, Tom. 2006. Psychological Perspectives on Legitimacy and Legitimation. Annual Review of Psychology 57:375400.Google Scholar
Tyler, Tom. 2011. Why People Cooperate. The Role of Social Motivations. Princeton. NJ: Princeton University Press: Tyler. Tom, and Steven Blader. 2003. The Group Engagement Model: Procedural Justice, Social Identity, and Cooperative Behavior. Personality and Social Psychology Review 7:349–61.Google Scholar
Tyler, Tom, Boeckmann, Robert, Smith, Heather, and Huo, Yuen. 1997. Social Justice in a Diverse Society. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.Google Scholar
Tyler, Tom, and Lind, Allan. 1992. A Relational Model of Authority in Groups. In Mark Zanna, (ed.) Advances in Experimental Social Psychology 25:115191.Google Scholar
Ulbig, Stacy. 2008. Voice is Not Enough – The Importance of Influence in Political Trust and Policy Assessments. Public Opinion Quarterly 72:523539.Google Scholar
Van den Bos, Kees. 2001. Fairness Heuristic Theory: Assessing the Information to Which People Are Reacting Has a Pivotal Role in Understanding Organizational Justice. In Theoretical and Cultural Perspectives on Organizational Justice, edited by Stephen Gilliland, Dirk Steiner and Daniel Skarlicki. Greenwich, CT: Information Age Publishing.Google Scholar
Van den Bos, Kees. 2005. What is Responsible for the Fair Process Effect? In Handbook of Organizational Justice, edited by Jerald Greenberg and Jason Colquitt, 273300. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associations.Google Scholar
Van den Bos, Kees, and Lind, Allan. 2002. Uncertainty Management by Means of Fairness Judgments. In Advances in Experimental Social Psychology, edited by Mark P. Zanna, 160. Cambridge, MA: Academic Press.Google Scholar
Van den Bos, Kees, Maas, Marjolein, Waldring, Ismintha, and Semin, Gün. 2003. Toward Understanding the Psychology of Reactions to Perceived Fairness: The Role of Affect Intensity. Social Justice Research 16:151168.Google Scholar
Van den Bos, Kees, Vermunt, Riël, and Wilke, Henk. 1997. Procedural and Distributive Justice: What Is Fair Depends More on What Comes First Than on What Comes Next. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 72:95104.Google Scholar
Van den Bos, Kees, Wilke, Henk, Lind, Allan, and Vermunt, Riël. 1998. Evaluating Outcomes by Means of the Fair Process Effect: Evidence for Different Processes in Fairness and Satisfaction Judgments. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 74:14931503.Google Scholar
Van Houwelingen, Gijs, van Dijke, Marius, and De Cremer, David. 2014. Fairness Enactment as Response to Higher Level Unfairness: The Roles of Self-Construal and Spatial Distance. Journal of Management. doi: 10.1177/0149206314530166.Google Scholar
Van Prooijen, Jan-Willem, Van den Bos, Kees, and Wilke, Henk. 2004. Group Belongingness and Procedural Justice: Social Inclusion and Exclusion by Peers Affects the Psychology of Voice. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 87:6679.Google Scholar
Wu, Xuan-Na, and Wang, Er-Ping. 2013. Outcome Favorability as a Boundary Condition to Voice Effect on People’s Reaction to Public Policymaking. Journal of Applied Social Psychology 43:329337.Google Scholar
Figure 0

Fig. 1 Procedural fairness theory

Figure 1

Fig. 2 How outcome favorability may intervene in the process

Figure 2

Table 1 Characteristics of the Experiments

Figure 3

Fig. 3 Total effects on decision acceptance, amongactual decision-making arrangements

Figure 4

Fig. 4 Total effects on decision acceptance, within actual decision-making arrangements

Figure 5

Fig. 5 Effects on decision acceptance, SEM estimates Note: * p<0.05.

Figure 6

Table 2 Effects on Decision Acceptance

Figure 7

Table 3 Robustness Check: Testing the Relationship in a Population-based Survey Experiment (E28)

Supplementary material: Link

Esaiasson et al. Dataset

Link
Supplementary material: File

Esaiasson supplementary material

Appendix

Download Esaiasson supplementary material(File)
File 180.7 KB