Published online by Cambridge University Press: 11 December 2012
Theorists have identified a wide range of reasons why individual and collective actors have a moral responsibility to help alleviate global poverty. There is now widespread agreement that several of these reasons are valid. From the perspective of the poverty opponent, it might seem that the more reasons there are to alleviate poverty, the better. The difficulty is that different reasons for alleviating poverty point to different poverty-alleviating activities. This situation generates questions about both how actors should set priorities among different poverty-alleviating activities (‘actor-centred’ questions) and who should have primary responsibility for alleviating particular cases of poverty (‘case-centred’ questions). This article explains why actor-centred and case-centred questions are worth asking and sketches a promising way of responding to them.
University of Virginia (email: [email protected]). The author thanks Christian Barry, Barbara Buckinx, Ryan Davis, Gerald Doppelt, Chad Flanders, Peter Furia, John Goldberg, Robert Goodin, George Klosko, Troy Kozma, Thomas Pogge, Mike Ravvin, Robert Talisse, Claire Timperley, Leif Wenar, and three anonymous reviewers, as well as audiences at the Midwest Political Science Association Annual Meeting, a meeting of the Princeton Society of Fellows in the liberal arts, and the Vanderbilt seminar on Responsibility and Global Justice for extremely helpful comments on previous versions of this article.
1 Kenny, Charles, Getting Better: Why Global Development is Succeeding – And How We Can Improve the World Even More (New York: Basic Books, 2011)Google Scholar
Pogge, Thomas, Politics as Usual: What Lies Behind the Pro-Poor Rhetoric (New York: Polity Press, 2010)Google Scholar
2 Anderson, Elizabeth, ‘What is the Point of Equality?’, Ethics, 109 (1999), 287–337CrossRefGoogle Scholar
3 This article's vocabulary – in particular the discussion of ‘wealthy actors’ who ‘help’ to ‘alleviate poverty’ – has an unfortunate top-down and apolitical ring to it. I wish I had been able to find a more political vocabulary to concisely express the ideas presented here. But while form and content can never be entirely extricated, the argument of this essay is not intrinsically top-down: even the most democratic global poverty pluralist has to decide what to do and with whom to work, and so must address the questions discussed in this article.
4 According to Mason, ‘[t]he word “pluralism” generally refers to the view that there are many of the things in question (concepts, scientific world views, discourses, viewpoints etc.)’. See Elinor Mason, ‘Value Pluralism’, in Edward N. Zalta, ed., The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Spring 2008 Edition, http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2008/entires/value-pluralism, (2006).
5 Amartya Sen, Development as Freedom (New York: Anchor Books, 2000Google Scholar
Miller, David, ‘Distributing Responsibilities’, Journal of Political Philosophy, 9 (2001), 453–471CrossRefGoogle Scholar
6 By ‘activity’ I mean not only one-off, small-scale acts like digging a well, but also longer-term, larger-scale initiatives, campaigns, policies, etc.
7 If an actor has several reasons to alleviate poverty, but these reasons all point to the same (doable) activity, then actor-centred questions are of intellectual interest, but lack practical relevance.
8 I return to this issue in Section 4.
9 Barry, Christian, ‘The Contribution Principle: Its Meaning and Significance for Allocating Responsibility to Address Acute Deprivation’, doctoral dissertation, Columbia University, 2005Google Scholar
10 Miller, ‘Distributing Responsibilities’.
11 Noteworthy reasons left out of this list include those based on human rights, religious duty and virtue ethics. I also exclude non-moral reasons, such as self-interest, and moral reasons for undertaking other activities that have the positive externality of helping to alleviate severe poverty.
12 Pogge, Thomas, ‘Severe Poverty as a Violation of Negative Duties’, Ethics and International Affairs, 19 (2005), 55–83CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pogge, Thomas, World Poverty and Human Rights (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2002)Google Scholar
Caney, Simon, ‘Environmental Degradation, Reparations, and the Moral Significance of History’, Journal of Social Philosophy, 37 (2006), 464–482CrossRefGoogle Scholar
13 Young, Iris, ‘Responsibility and Global Justice: A Social Connection Model’, Social Philosophy and Policy, 23 (2006), 102–130CrossRefGoogle Scholar
14 Pogge, World Poverty and Human Rights, p. 201Google Scholar
15 Miller, Richard, Globalizing Justice: The Ethics of Poverty and Power (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
16 Miller, ‘Distributing Responsibilities’; Joel Feinberg, Harm to Others (New York: Oxford University Press, 1987)Google Scholar
17 Barry, ‘The Contribution Principle’, Ch. 2Google Scholar
18 My thanks to two anonymous reviewers for help with this reason, including suggesting the term ‘capacity’. See also Miller, ‘Distributing Responsibilities’.
19 Slim, Hugo, ‘Relief Agencies and Moral Standing in War: Principles of Humanity, Neutrality, Impartiality and Solidarity’, Development in Practice, 7 (1997), 342–352CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Waldron, Jeremy, ‘Welfare and the Images of Charity’, The Philosophical Quarterly, 36 (1986), 463–482CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kleinig, John, ‘Good Samaritan’, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 5 (1976), 382–407Google Scholar
Miller, David, Principles of Social Justice (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1999)Google Scholar
Williams, Bernard, ‘Is International Rescue a Moral Issue?’ Social Research, 62 (1995)Google Scholar
20 Rawls, John, A Theory of Justice, Revised Edition (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1999)Google Scholar
21 Rawls, A Theory of Justice, Revised Edition, p. 99Google Scholar
Rawls, John, The Law of Peoples with the Idea of Public Reason Revisited (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1999)Google Scholar
Rawls, Theory of Justice, Revised Edition, p. 99Google Scholar
22 Kymlicka, Will, Contemporary Political Philosophy Second Edition (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002)Google Scholar
23 Singer, Peter, ‘Famine, Affluence, and Morality’, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 1 (1972), 229–243Google Scholar
Singer, Peter, One World: The Ethics of Globalization (New Haven: Yale University Press, 2002)Google Scholar
Singer, Peter, ‘Outsiders: Our Obligations to Those Beyond Our Borders’, in Deen K. Chatterjee, ed., Ethics of Assistance: Morality and the Distant Needy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004)Google Scholar
Singer, Peter, The Life You Can Save (New York: Random House, 2009)Google Scholar
Unger, Peter, Living High and Letting Die (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
24 Walzer, Michael, Spheres of Justice: A Defense of Plurality and Equality (United States of America: Basic Books, 1983)Google Scholar
Tan, Kok-Chor, Justice Without Borders: Cosmopolitanism, Nationalism and Patriotism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kolodny, Niko, ‘Do Associative Duties Matter?’, Journal of Political Philosophy, 10 (2002), 250–266CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scheffler, Samuel, Boundaries and Allegiances (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001)Google Scholar
25 deParle, Jason, ‘In a World on the Move, a Tiny Land Strains to Cope’, The New York Times, 24 June 2007Google Scholar
World Bank, Global Economic Prospects 2006: Economic Implications of Remittances and Migration, November 2005)Google Scholar
26 See, for example, Tan, Justice Without Borders.
27 Anwander, Norbert, ‘Contributing and Benefiting: Two Grounds for Duties to the Victims of Injustice’, Ethics and International Affairs, 19 (2005), 39–45CrossRefGoogle Scholar
28 Pogge, ‘Severe Poverty as a Violation of Negative Duties’, p. 197Google Scholar
29 Oxfam International invoke this source of moral responsibility in a briefing paper (Oxfam International, ‘The World is Still Waiting: Broken G8 Promises are Costing Millions of Lives’, Briefing Paper No. 103, May 2007).
30 Sabl, Andrew, Ruling Passions: Political Offices and Democratic Ethics (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2002)Google Scholar
Thompson, Dennis, Political Ethics and Public Office (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1987)Google Scholar
31 Barry, Christian, ‘Global Justice: Aims, Arrangements, and Responsibilities’, in Toni Erskine, ed., Can Institutions Have Responsibilities? Collective Moral Agency and International Relations (New York: Palgrave MacMillan, 2004)Google Scholar
32 Green, Michael, ‘Institutional Responsibilities for Global Problems’, Philosophical Topics, 30 (2002)Google Scholar
33 Pogge, Thomas, ‘Moral Priorities for International Human Rights NGOs’, in Daniel A. Bell and Jean-Marc Coicaud, eds, The Ethical Dilemmas of International Human Rights and Humanitarian NGOs: Reflections on a Dialogue Between Practitioners and Theorists (Tokyo: United Nations University Press, 2007)Google Scholar
Daniel Weinstock, ed., Global Justice, Global Institutions (Calgary: University of Calgary Press, 2005)Google Scholar
Deen Chatterjee, ed., The Ethics of Assistance: Morality and the Distant Needy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004)Google Scholar
Ian Shapiro and Lea Brilmayer, Global Justice: Nomos XLI (New York: New York University Press, 1999)Google Scholar
Pogge, ‘Moral Priorities for International Human Rights NGOs’, p. 251Google Scholar
34 Here and throughout this article, I assume that outside actors selecting which cases of severe poverty to help alleviate are choosing among cases in which those affected want the sort of assistance or partnership that these outside actors are able to provide. Of course, sometimes those affected do not want external assistance or participation in their efforts to improve their own lives (or they do not perceive their lives as in need of improvement).
35 Reddy, Sanjay, ‘The Role of Apparent Constraints in Normative Reasoning: A Methodological Statement and Application to Global Justice’, Journal of Ethics, 9 (2005), 119–125CrossRefGoogle Scholar
36 Sometimes pressuring third parties, for example by donating to an INGO seeking to reform the World Bank, is a way for individuals to discharge their own moral responsibilities. At other times pressuring third parties is morally optional, in which case it should take second priority to the individual discharging his or her own responsibilities.
37 Miller, ‘Distributing Responsibilities’.
38 Bernard Williams, ‘A Critique of Utilitarianism’ in J.C. Smart and Bernard Williams, eds, Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973)Google Scholar
39 Fraser, Nancy, ‘Rethinking Recognition’, New Left Review, 3 (2000)Google Scholar
Thomas Pogge, ed., Freedom from Poverty as a Human Right: Who Owes What to the Very Poor? (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007)Google Scholar
40 Walker, Margaret Urban, ‘Restorative Justice and Reparations’, Journal of Social Philosophy, 37 (2006), 377–395CrossRefGoogle Scholar
41 I return to and qualify this statement in Section 4.
42 Miller, ‘Distributing Responsibilities’.
43 O'Neill, Onora, Bounds of Justice (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rainbolt, George, ‘Perfect and Imperfect Obligations’, Philosophical Studies, 98 (2000), 233–256CrossRefGoogle Scholar
44 George Rainbolt conceives of the perfect/imperfect distinction as a continuum rather than a dichotomy (see Rainbolt, ‘Perfect and Imperfect Obligations’).
45 Barry, ‘The Contribution Principle’, Ch. 2Google Scholar
46 Rawls, John, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1971)Google Scholar
47 Shue, Henry, ‘Mediating Duties’, Ethics, 98 (1988), 687–704CrossRefGoogle Scholar
48 Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 114Google Scholar
49 Miller, David, ‘Who is Responsible?’ The Philosophers’ Magazine (2006), p. 62Google Scholar
50 Miller, ‘Distributing Responsibilities’.
51 Miller acknowledges this in passing.
52 Ruth Chang, ed., Incommensurability, Incomparability and Practical Reason (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1997)Google Scholar
53 Goodin, Robert E., Utilitarianism as a Public Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kymlicka, Contemporary Political Philosophy, Ch. 2Google Scholar
Pettit, Philip, ‘When Wrong is Right’, Times Literary Supplement, 28 September 2005Google Scholar
54 I thank Leif Wenar for pressing this point.
55 I address this issue extensively elsewhere.
56 However, as I argue in Between Samaritans and States: The Political Ethics of Humanitarian NGOs (forthcoming), donors should not treat NGOs as ‘do-gooding machines’.
57 Caney, Simon, ‘Global Poverty and Human Rights: The Case for Positive Duties’ in Thomas Pogge, ed., Freedom from Poverty as a Human Right: Who Owes What to the Very Poor? (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007), 275–302Google Scholar
58 Wenar, Leif, ‘Responsibility and Severe Poverty’ in Thomas Pogge, ed., Freedom from Poverty as a Human Right, p. 258Google Scholar
59 Duggan, Celia W., ‘A Joint Attack on Many Perils of Africa's Young,’ The New York Times, 23 December 2006Google Scholar
60 My thanks to an anonymous reviewer for help on this point.
61 My discussion here is indebted to Wenar, ‘Responsibility and Severe Poverty’.
62 The driving example is dis-analogous to global poverty in two ways: all drivers are sometimes front drivers and sometimes rear drivers, so assigning the responsibility to rear drivers distributes the burden among all drivers. In contrast, everyone is not sometimes very poor. In addition, while one can avoid paying for a traffic accident by avoiding hitting drivers in front of oneself, because global poverty already exists, there is no way for everyone to avoid responsibility for it by being careful (except, perhaps, if one only recognizes direct causal responsibility as a moral reason to help alleviate poverty).
63 Caney makes this point in terms of respect rather than fairness (see Caney, ‘Global Poverty and Human Rights’).