Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-s2hrs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-02T20:17:46.210Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The ‘Beame of Diuinity’: Animal suffering in the Early Thought of Robert Boyle

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 January 2009

Malcolm R. Oster
Affiliation:
St. Cross College, University of Oxford, Oxford OX1 3LZ.

Extract

It has long been recognized that unnecessary cruelty to animals was held to be morally wrong by many classical moralists and medieval scholastics, and was echoed repeatedly in the early-modern period, though not necessarily reflecting any particular concern for animals, but rather to indicate the supposed brutalizing effects on the human character. The prevalence of the more radical view that cruelty to animals was wrong regardless of human consequences has only been dealt with comparatively recently, in the pioneering work of Keith Thomas with regard to early-modern England. Thomas suggested that a remarkably constant and coherent argument underpinned the bulk of pamphleteering and preaching against animal cruelty in the period; man was entitled to domesticate animals and kill them for food and clothing but not to cause them unnecessary suffering. While wild animals could be killed for food or in self-defence, and game and vermin could be hunted, it was deemed wrong to kill only for pleasure. While this position could be found among Protestants of many different persuasions, the particular focus of successive campaigners changed over time. Preceding the Civil War the attack was concentrated on cock-fighting, bear-baiting and the ill-treatment of domestic animals; in the later seventeenth century it broadened out to include the caging of wild birds, brutal methods of slaughter, hare-hunting and vivisection.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © British Society for the History of Science 1989

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

This paper was originally read at a seminar at the Wellcome Unit for the History of Medicine, (University of Oxford) May 1988.1 wish to thank the President and Fellows of the Royal Society, London, for permission to use and cite materials from the Boyle Papers. I am also grateful to the following who provided valuable comments and criticisms in earlier drafts of the paper: Charles Webster, John Harwood, Keith Thomas, Andrew Linzey and Michael Shortland.

1 Thomas, Keith, Man and the Natural World. Changing Attitudes in England 1500–1800, London, 1983.Google Scholar

2 Ibid., p. 153.

3 Ibid., p. 154.

4 Detailed documentation of Boyle's physiological activity can be found in Frank, Robert G., Harvey and the Oxford Physiologists, Berkeley, 1980, Chapter 6.Google Scholar

5 Some useful comments on Boyle's ethical attitudes during experiments are made by Shugg, Wallace, ‘Humanitarian Attitudes in the Early Animal Experiments of the Royal Society’, Annals of Science (1968), 24, pp. 227238.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

6 Descartes' correspondence with the Cambridge Platonist, Henry More, in 1648/1649 focused on this issue. More complained in a letter sent December 1648, ‘But I perceive clearly what drives you to hold that beasts are machines. It is simply a way of demonstrating the immortality of our souls, which reasoning, since it assumes that the body is in no wise able to cogitate, concludes that wherever there is cogitation there must needs be substance quite distinct from body, and hence immortal. From whence it follows that brutes, if they cogitate, have annexed to themselves immortal substances’. Descartes responded in February 1649 by reiterating the primacy of language: ‘For language is the one certain indication of latent cogitation in a body, and all men use it, even the most stupid and mentally deranged,… whereas on the other hand not a single brute speaks, and consequently this we may take for the true difference between man and beast’. Cited in Cohen, L.D., ‘Descartes and Henry More on the Beast Machine-A Translation of their Correspondence pertaining to Animal Automatism’, Annals of Science, (1936), 1, pp 51, 53.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

7 For the concepts of ‘animal automata’ and ‘animal soul’ see Young, R.M., ‘Animal Soul’, The Encyclopedia of Philosophy, (ed. Edwards, P.) (8 vols), New York, 1967, 1, pp. 122127Google Scholar; Rosenfield, Leonora C., From Beast-Machine to Man-Machine, 2nd edn, New York, 1968Google Scholar. The standard formulation of Cartesian dualism is in the ‘Discourse on Method’, in The Philosophical Works of Descartes, trans. Haldane, E.S. and Ross, G.R.T. (2 vols), Cambridge, 1969, 1, pp. 79130Google Scholar. For a contrasting perspective see Cottingham, J., ‘A Brute to the Brutes? Descartes' Treatment of Animals’, Philosophy, (1978), 53, pp. 551559.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

8 Thomas, (1). Natural World, p. 125.Google Scholar

9 The Boyle Papers, Royal Society Library, London. Vol. XXXVII. fols 186–193. The MS has been reproduced in Appendix 1. MS transcription scheme: [ ] deletion; 〈 〉 interlinear; {} marginal insertion;, // Robert Boyle, unless otherwise indicated. The folio references are inserted. Everything has been retained in the body of the text, as it enables the reader to follow Boyle's flow of thought and does not hinder, except on rare occasions, the cogency of his argument. The dating and background to the MS will be considered later in the paper.

10 For the dating of ‘Philaretus’, see Maddison, R.E.W., The Life of the Honourable Robert Boyle, F.R.S., London, 1969, p. 1Google Scholar. The reference in ‘Usefulness’ can be found in The Works of the Honourable Robert Boyle, 2nd edn (ed. Birch, T.) (6 vols) London, 1772. II, p. 74.Google Scholar

11 Maddison, (10), Life, p. 57.Google Scholar

12 Boyle, (10). Works, Vol. 1, p. xxviiGoogle Scholar; Maddison, (10), Life, p. 61.Google Scholar

13 Frank, (4). Oxford Physiologists, p. 26.Google Scholar

14 Ibid., pp. 28–29.

15 Boyle, (10), Works, 1, p. 262Google Scholar. Highmore, who was also a kinsman of the young statistician and anatomist, William Petty, dedicated his The History of Generation, London, 1651Google Scholar, to Boyle, the earliest dedication to him in print.

16 Boyle, (10). Works, VI, p. 28Google Scholar; Maddison, (10). Life, pp. 7273.Google Scholar

17 Boyle drew up a list of his existing writings dated 25 January 1650 which are in B.P.XXXVI. It should be noted that Boyle attached a great significance to his birthdate, which he mentions in ‘Philaretus’ as being ‘upon St. Paul's Conversion day, being the 25th of January;’, See Maddison, , Life, p. 3Google Scholar. The Essay is in B.P.XXVI, fols 162–175. A portion of it was published by Westfall, R.S. in ‘Unpublished Boyle papers relating to scientific method’. Annals of Science (1956), 12, pp. 6373; 103117CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Note also Frank, (4), Oxford Physiologists, p. 94.Google Scholar

18 B.P.XXVI, fols 162–163.

19 Ibid., fol.169r. The reference to Aristotle in the Historia animalium, is 5.2.539b17–540a26.

20 Bynum, William F., ‘The Anatomical Method, Natural Theology, and the Functions of the Brain’, Isis, 64, (1973), p. 445.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

21 Some considerations touching the usefulness of Experimental Natural Philosophy, (1663) c. 16491651Google Scholar in Boyle, (10), Workes, II, p. 7.Google Scholar

22 Boyle, (10), Works, VI, p. 76Google Scholar; Maddison, (10), Life, p. 71.Google Scholar

23 Boyle, (10), WorksGoogle Scholar, Ibid.

24 Frank, (4), Oxford Physiologists, p. 25.Google Scholar

25 Though meeting to dissect Greene, a young woman hanged for infanticide, they discovered her corpse was still alive, and with the help of others, nursed her back to health, Ibid. p. 50. While autopsies provided valuable experience in anatomy, they also posed ethical problems. Boyle's recognition of this is discussed further on in the paper.

26 Boyle, (10), Works, VI, p. 54.Google Scholar

28 Detail on Boyle's early scientific links with the Anglo-Irish group of intellectuals he meets when he returns to England, and their desire to apply utilitarian projects in Ireland, can only be alluded to here. See Webster, Charles, The Great Instauration. Science, Medicine and Reform 1626–1660, London, 1975, pp. 5767Google Scholar; Barnard, T.C., Cromwellian Ireland, English Government and Reform in Ireland 1649–1660, Oxford, 1975, especially Chapter 8.Google Scholar

29 Boyle, (10), Works, VI, p. 633.Google Scholar

30 Full details on the scientific, political and philosophical composition of the ‘Club’ can be found in Webster, (28), Great Instauration, pp. 153178.Google Scholar

31 Frank, (4), Oxford Physiologists, p. 53.Google Scholar

32 Usefulness of Experimental Natural Philosophy, Pt.II.(1663) c. 16561657Google Scholar, in Boyle, (10), Works, II, p. 67.Google Scholar

33 Boyle, (10), Works, II, p. 68.Google Scholar

35 Ibid., p. 88.

36 Ibid. Boyle provides no dates for these injection trials, but Wren wrote to Robert Wood (1622–1685), physician and mathematician, of their success in June 1656, and the previous March was the final time Boyle, Wilkins and Wren were in Oxford together. See Frank, (4), Oxford Physiologists, p. 332.Google Scholar

37 Boyle, (10), Works, II, p. 89.Google Scholar

38 Ibid., p. 67.

39 Ibid. pp. 67–68.

40 New Experiments Physico-Mechanical in Boyle, (10), Works, IGoogle Scholar, Hooke's difficulty with the cruelty of many experiments he was involved with is described in Shugg, (5), ‘Humanitarian Attitudes’, pp. 231232.Google Scholar

41 Boyle, (10), Works, I, p. 97.Google Scholar

42 Ibid., p.99.

43 Sprat, Thomas, History of the Royal Society, London, 1667, p. 195Google Scholar. See Hunter, M., Science and Society in Restoration England, Cambridge, 1981, pp. 2931Google Scholar for useful comment on Sprat's History.

44 Boyle, (10), Works, I, pp. 106107.Google Scholar

45 Ibid., pp. 109–110.

46 Philosophical Transactions, 1670, V, pp. 20172019.Google Scholar

47 Ibid., p. 2018.

48 Royal Society Commonplace Bock MS 195 of which MS 192 appears a draft. The Aretology or Ethical Elements of Robert Boyle. Begun at Stalbridge, The of [Blank] 1645Google Scholar. That's the tru Good that makes the owner so. For the dating of MS 195 note the title page and Boyle, (10), Works, I, pp. 17, 20.Google Scholar

49 Aretology, (48), fol. 78v.Google Scholar

50 Ibid., fols 67–67v.

51 Ibid., fol. 20.

52 Maddison, (10), Life, p. 41.Google Scholar

53 Boyle, (10), Works, I, p. 302Google Scholar. Noted in Rogers, G.A.J.. ‘Descartes and the Method of English Science’, Annals of Science, (1972), 29, pp. 248249CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed. Boyle may have been acquainted with Descartes's Principles of Philosophy, 1644Google Scholar, by 1647–1648, and more particularly the Cartesian mechanism of Sir Kenelm Digby, a rare English advocate of the beast-machine doctrine. However, no direct evidence is forthcoming.

54 B.P.XXXVII. (9) Appendix 1, lines 1, 15–19.

55 The first mention of Boyle's link with Mallet is in November 1651 when Boyle writes to him of a sudden sickness. See B.L.Harl. MSS. 7003. fol.179. However, Mallet's family had lived in Boyle's neighbourhood for many years and Mallet's father had been an occasional legal advisor for Boyle. Correspondence between Samuel Hartlib and John Mallet was maintained in the early 1650s and Boyle informed Hartlib that Mallet was willing to help in improving Hartlib's work on husbandry. See B.L. Add. MSS.32093, fol.293. In a letter of Boyle to Mallet, sent from Ireland in 1653, Birch, in his edited works of Boyle, inserts a short introduction to Boyle's ‘highly honoured friend John Mallet, Esq; at Poynington, near Sherbourne’. See Boyle, (10), Works, I, iGoogle Scholar. In the letter Boyle shows high regard for Mallet's knowledge of nature and is therefore delighted that he has prompted him to begin ‘a friendship for the Eastern tongues’, despite being ‘a person so used to the study, and replenished with the nature of things…’ Boyle, (10), Works, I, i.Google Scholar

56 It is unnecessary to detail here Dury's pivotal role in Boyle's early association with scientific circles in the mid-1640s, and his own contribution to projects for Protestant union, the advancement of learning and the refashioning of knowledge on Baconian lines. Extensive information on Dury can be found in Batten, J.M., John Dury: Advocate of Christian Reunion, Chicago, 1944Google Scholar; Turnbull, G.H., Hartlib, Dury and Comenius, Liver-pool, 1947Google Scholar; Webster, (28), Great Instauration.Google Scholar

57 B.P.XXXVII (9) Appendix 1, lines 19–41; Thomas, (1), Natural World, p. 139.Google Scholar

58 Burns, Norman, Christian Mortalism from Tyndale to Milton, Camb, 1972, pp. 11, 28, 29.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

59 SirDigby, Kenelm, Two Treatises: in the One of Which the Nature of Bodies; in the Other, the Nature of Man's Soule is Looked into, Paris, 1644.Google Scholar

60 Boyle, (10), Works, IV, pp. 12, 13.Google Scholar

61 B.P.XXXVI1. (9) Appendix 1, lines 62–69.

62 The classic treatment of the doctrine remains, Lovejoy, A.O., The Great Chain of Being, New York, 1936. 2nd edn, 1960.Google Scholar

63 Locke's solution to the dilemma Descartes had raised was to employ sensationalist psychology which did not reject dualism, but did fragment Cartesian indivisible substance, thereby allowing continuous degrees of intelligence on the scale of being. By distinguishing ideas of sensation and reflection, Locke was able to declare that animals had particular sensory ideas and a degree of reason but no general ideas or powers of abstraction and consequently no language for their expression. This was uncomfortably close to how children were generally perceived. His sensory picture was via the analogy of atoms and corpuscles. For Boyle's strong influence on Locke see Rogers, G.A.J., ‘Boyle, Locke and Reason’, Journal of the History of Ideas, (1966), 27, pp. 205216CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Alexander, Peter, Ideas, Qualities and Corpuscles: Locke and Boyle on the External World, Cambridge, 1985.Google Scholar

64 SirBrowne, Thomas, Religio Medici, London, 1643Google Scholar. Pt.1. Para. 36. Cited in Thomas, (1), Natural World, p. 129.Google Scholar

65 Bynum, (20), ‘Anatomical Method’, pp. 449450.Google Scholar

66 B.P.XXXVII, (9), Appendix 1, lines 25–32.

67 B.P.XXXVII, fols 196–203. ‘The Duty of a Mother's being a Nurse asserted’.

68 Ibid., fol.196v.

69 While at Christ College, Cambridge, Power embarked on extensive investigation of plants, animals, minerals and pharmacology. Sir Thomas Browne's letter of advice to him, in 1646, spurred him on, and he became an able disciple of Harvey, extending work on blood circulation, and corresponding with Browne on plant morphogenesis and embryology. See The Works of Sir Thomas Browne, (ed. Keynes, G.) 4 vols, London, 1968, IV, pp. 255266Google Scholar; 259–260. Power was elected first member of the Royal Society with Isham, 1 July, 1663.

70 B.L. MS. 1326, fols 48v–49.

71 Ibid., fol.48v.

73 Ibid., fol.49.

74 Ibid., fol.49v.

75 Power, Henry, Experimental Philosophy in Three Books, Microscopical, Mercurial, Magnetical, London, 1664Google Scholar. BK.III has the subtitle That the World was not made Primarily nor Solely for the use of Man, nor in subserviency unto Him and his Faculties.

76 B.P.XXXVII, (9), Appendix 1, lines 50–56. Cf. Notes 6,51.

77 Moore, John, A Map of Man's Mortalitie, London, 1617, p. 43.Google Scholar

78 Thomas, (1), Natural World, pp. 137138.Google Scholar

79 Ibid., p.99.

80 B.P.XXXVII. (9) Appendix 1, lines 73–85.

81 Boyle, (10), Works, II, p. 350Google Scholar. In a further ‘Reflection’, Boyle recalls sending his spaniel for a glove, which gave the dog so much satisfaction ‘that the very use of speech would not enable him to express it better…’ Ibid., p. 388.

82 The impetus behind a new philosophical language is detailed in Salmon, Vivian, The Works of Francis Lodwick. A Study of his Writings in the Intellectual Context of the Seventeenth Century, London, 1972, especially Chapter 1Google Scholar; also Knowlson, James, Universal Language Schemes in England and France 7600–7800, Toronto, 1975.Google Scholar

83 Boyle, (10) Works, 1, xxxvii.Google Scholar

84 Knowlson observes, ‘it was felt by Puritan reformers that children learn best through the senses and the imagination. They believed, therefore, that it was wise to appeal to this natural capacity by introducing the young as often as possible to natural objects either directly or by means of illustrations’, Knowlson, (82), Language Schemes, p. 35.Google Scholar

85 B.P.XXXVII (9), Appendix 1, lines 86–119.

86 B.P.XXXVII (9), Appendix 1, lines 119–210.

87 Cf. Note 45.

88 B.P.XXXVII (9), Appendix 1, lines 223–239.

89 Thomas, (1), Natural World, p. 295Google Scholar. He comments, ‘There seems to have been no legal authority for this notion, but it was held throughout the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries by scores of commentators who should have known better.’ The general unease about meat eating, despite its being a national symbol, is discussed on pp. 287–300. Boyle follows orthodox teaching in the sanction given for meat eating in Genesis 9:23. See Boyle, (10), Works, V, p. 396.Google Scholar

90 Boyle, (10), Works, 1, p. 316.Google Scholar

91 B.P.XIV, fols 15–26. c. 1650.

92 Ibid., fol.16.

93 Thomas, (1), Natural World, p. 177.Google Scholar

94 B.P.XXXVII (9), Appendix 1, lines 239–311.

95 This memory of the stables in Florence dates from his stay there in the winter of 1641. See Maddison, (10), Life, p. 41.Google Scholar

96 See the Encyclopaedia of Islam, 2nd edn, 5 vols. Leiden & London, 19131934Google Scholar; reprinted 1960, III, pp. 306–308; 314–315. Apart from the similarity ian Moslem teaching in refraining from consuming the spilt blood of animals, in general Muslims were counselled to treat animals well. There were in Turkey a great number of aetiological legends concerning animals, many of which were original creations of Turkish folklore. The veneration of the horse seems to have conferred on it, in certain circumstances, an aura of saintliness. The tomb of the horse of Sultan Othman II at Uskudar became a place of pilgrimage where sick horses were brought. Dr Tom Patterson (Wellcome Unit, Oxford) has pointed out to me in conversation that the reports Boyle has heard of are far more likely to have been Hindu practice, particularly around Goa.

97 Luther's Works, (ed. Pelikan, J. and Lehman, H.) 56 vols. Philadelphia and St. Louis, 1955, 26, 45Google Scholar. Cited in Gary Deason, B., ‘Reformation Theology and the Mechanistic Conception of Nature’, in God & Nature: Historical Essays on the Encounter between Christianity and Science, ed. Lindberg, D. and Numbers, R., Berkeley, 1986, p. 174.Google Scholar

98 Aretology, (48), fol. 188v.Google Scholar

99 Ibid., fol. 190r.

100 Ibid., fol. 190v.

101 Thomas, (1), Natural World, p. 156Google Scholar. A highly negative view of the Christian perception of nature is evident in Passmore, J., Man's Responsibility for Nature, London, 1974Google Scholar and ‘The Treatment of Animals’, in Journal of the History of Ideas, (1975), 36, pp. 195218Google Scholar. For a critique and balanced corrective of Passmore see Attfield, R., ‘Christian Attitudes to Nature’, Journal of the History of Ideas, (1983), 44, pp. 369386.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

102 Crane, R.S., ‘Suggestions towards a Genealogy of the “Man of Feeling,” E.L.H. A Journal of English Literary History, (1934), 1, pp. 205230.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

103 Ibid, pp. 208–209. Cited from Glanville, Essay 7, pp. 21–22.

104 Ibid., p. 209.

105 Ibid., p. 210. Glanville, p. 31.

106 This is the approach taken by J. Jacob in his analysis of the Aretology in ‘The Ideological Origins of Robert Boyle's Philosophy’ in Journal of European Studies, (1972), 2, pp. 18Google Scholar, and Robert Boyle and the English Revolution, New York, 1977, Chapter 2Google Scholar. Jacob's representation of Boyle's early development and his motives in writing the Aretology is arguably flawed. I hope to show this in further work.

107 The detailed treatment of this question is found in Kendall, R.T., Calvin and English Calvinism to 1649, Oxford, 1979Google Scholar. Ames, 's Marrow of Sacred Divinity, London, 1642Google Scholar, was catalogued as being present in that edition in Boyle's library. A listing of the library, which may be incomplete, is in MS 23. Royal Society. I am grateful to Dr J. Harwood for providing me with a copy of the list he discovered.

108 The impact of humanist influence on Protestant thinking can be found in Todd, Margo, Christian Humanism and the Puritan Social Order, Cambridge, 1987.Google Scholar

109 Ibid., p. 178.

110 The poem is in The Gentleman's Magazine, 1740, 10, p. 194Google Scholar. It is reproduced in Maddison, (10), Life, pp. 231232Google Scholar, i B.P.XXXVII (9) Appendix 1, lines 231–233.

111 Burner, Gilbert, A Sermon preached at. the Funeral of the Hon. Robert Boyle, London, 1692Google Scholar. Cited in Boyle, (10), Workes, I, p. cxliv.Google Scholar