Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-gb8f7 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-22T06:44:52.622Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Principle of Plenitude and Natural Theology in Nineteenth-Century Britain

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 January 2009

Richard R. Yeo
Affiliation:
School of Humanities, Griffith University, Brisbane, Australia.

Extract

In his classic study, The Great Chain of Being, Arthur Lovejoy delineated a complex set of concepts and assumptions which referred to the perfection of God and the fullness of creation. In attempting to distil the basic or ‘unit idea’ which constituted this pattern of thought, he focused on the assumption that ‘the universe is a plenum formarum in which the range of conceivable diversity of kinds of living things is exhaustively exemplified’. He called this the ‘principle of plenitude’. Lovejoy argued that this idea implied two others—continuity and gradation—and that together these reflected a pre-occupation with the ‘necessity of imperfection in all its possible degrees’, a concern which had pervaded Western thought since Plato and gave rise to the powerful ontology known as the ‘great chain of being’.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © British Society for the History of Science 1986

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

I would like to thank the referee (Dr J. H. Brooke) and the editor for their helpful comments on an earlier draft.

1 Lovejoy, A.O., The Great Chain of Being. New York, 1960, p. 52, 338Google Scholar. For a recent account which stresses the principle of plenitude as ‘the very foundation of the Chain of Being’, see Formigari, L., ‘Chain of Being’, in Wiener, P. (ed.), Dictionary of the History of Ideas, 4 vols. New York, 19681973, pp. i, 324335(334)Google Scholar. For a recent dispute about the concept of plenitude and the category of ‘unit idea’, see Hintikka, J., ‘Gaps in the Great Chain of Being: an exercise in the methodology of the history of ideas’, Proceedings of the American Philosophical Association, (19751976), 49, 22CrossRefGoogle Scholar, and Gram, M.S. and Martin, R.M., ‘The perils of plenitude: Hintikka Contra Lovejoy’, Journal of the History of Ideas, (1980), 41, pp. 497511.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

2 See Lovejoy, , Essays in the History of Ideas, Baltimore and London, 1948, pp. 113Google Scholar and ‘Reflections on the history of ideas’, Journal of the History of Ideas, (1980), 41, pp. 487511Google Scholar. For other perspectives, see Skinner, Q., ‘Meaning and understanding in the history of ideas’, History and Theory (1969), 8, pp. 153 (10–14)CrossRefGoogle Scholar and Bresdorff, T., ‘Lovejoy's idea of “idea”’, New Literary History, (19761977), 8, pp. 195211CrossRefGoogle Scholar. See also Brinton, C., ‘Intellectual history’, In: Sills, D.L. (ed.), International Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences. 18 vols. New York, 19681979, 6, pp. 462468Google Scholar; White, H.V., ‘The tasks of intellectual history’, The Monist, (1969), 53, pp. 606630CrossRefGoogle Scholar, and Foucault, M., The Archaeology of Knowledge. London, 1972, pp. 134140.Google Scholar

3 Lovejoy, , op. cit. (1), p. 326Google Scholar and chs. ix–xi.

4 Bynum, W., ‘The Great Chain of Being after forty years: an appraisal’, History of Science, (1975), 13, pp. 128(3)CrossRefGoogle Scholar, also 7, 14, 18.

5 Lovejoy, , op. cit. (2), Essays, p. 169.Google Scholar

6 Bynum, , op. cit. (4), p. 20Google Scholar. See also Foucault, , The Order of Things, London, 1974, pp. 145157Google Scholar for a distinction between eighteenth- and nineteenth-century theories of evolution and their relation to the chain of being.

7 Lovejoy, , op. cit. (1), p. 52.Google Scholar

8 Ibid., p. 154.

9 Ibid., pp. 70–72.

10 Ibid., pp. 156–158.

11 Ibid., pp. 170–171.

12 Ibid., p. 272.

13 Ibid, III. For a study which also stresses the scientific thinking involved, see Dick, S.J., Plurality of Worlds: the Origins of the Extraterrestrial Life Debate from Democritus to Kant. Cambridge, 1982.Google Scholar

14 Lovejoy, , op. cit. (1), pp. 118119.Google Scholar

15 See for example Ray, J., The Wisdom of God, new edn., London, 1827, p. 302.Google Scholar

16 Buckland, W., Geology and Mineralogy Considered with Reference to Natural Theology, 2 vols. London, 1836, i, p. 301CrossRefGoogle Scholar. A bequest of the eighth Earl of Bridgewater provided funds for the illustration of ‘the Power, Wisdom and Goodness of God as Manifested in the Creation’. Eight treatises, covering various scientific areas, were published between 1833 and 1836. See Brock, W.H., ‘The selection of the authors of the Bridgewater Treatises’, Notes and Records of the Royal Society of London, (1966), 21, pp. 162179.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

17 Roger, P.M., Animal and Vegetable Physiology Considered with Reference to National Theology, 2 vols. London, 1834, i, p. 11, 13Google Scholar. For a reflection on the contrast between the feminine image of ‘Nature’ in Roget and the masculine ‘Divine Artificer’ in Paley, see Gliserman, S., ‘Early Victorian science writers and Tennyson's “In Memoriam”: a study in cultural exchange’, Victorian Studies, (1975), 19, pp. 277308(290–291)Google Scholar. While this contrast is useful, it is important to recognize that Paley also emphasized the fecundity of nature in ways which went beyond the design argument.

18 [Chambers, R.] Vestiges of the Natural History of Creation. London, 1844, p. 367Google Scholar; also Bray, C., The Philosophy of Necessity, 2 vols. London, 1841, i, p. 24.Google Scholar

19 Dick, T., On the Improvement of Society. London, 1833, p. 257Google Scholar; for his calculations leading to the conclusion that there were more than sixty thousand billion ‘distinct ideas, conceptions or contrivances, in relation to the animal world’, see ibid., pp. 260–262.

20 Dick, T., The Christian Philosopher, new edn., 2 vols. Glasgow, 1863, i, p. 109.Google Scholar

21 Paley, W., Natural Theology, London, 1802, p. 490.Google Scholar

22 Malthus, T., An Essay on the Principle of Population, London, 1798Google Scholar, reprinted, Harmondsworth, , 1976, pp. 7172Google Scholar. For the relevant contemporary discussion, both scientific and social, see Gale, B.C., ‘Darwin and the Concept of a Struggle for Existence: A study in the extrascientific origins of scientific ideas’, Isis, 1972, 63, pp. 321344.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

23 Paley, , op. cit. (21), pp. 514516.Google Scholar

24 Ibid. p. 511.

25 Ibid., pp. 409–411.

26 Roget, , op. cit. (17), i, p. 9.Google Scholar

27 Ibid., pp. 48, 10–13.

28 Ibid., p. 48.

29 Paley, , op. cit. (21), pp. 7071.Google Scholar

30 Ibid., p. 69. This aspect of Paley's text has received little, if any, attention; one commentator has claimed that his concerns were ‘pastoral rather than philosophical’, that he ‘paid no attention to the principle of plenitude nor to the continuity of the great chain of being’. Manier, E., The Young Darwin and his Cultural Circle, Dordrecht, 1978, p. 72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

31 Paley, , op. cit. (21), p. 69.Google Scholar

32 Ibid., p. 70.

33 For a discussion of eighteenth-century theories of ‘evolution’ and the various meanings of the term, see Bowler, P.J., ‘Evolutionism in the Enlightenment’, History of Science, (1974), 12, pp. 159183CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed and ‘The changing meaning of “Evolution”’, Journal of the History of Ideas, (1975), 36, pp. 95114.Google Scholar

34 These two levels were, of course, related in the works of contemporaries. Erasmus Darwin made use of David Hume's exploitation of the phenomenon of generation as a possible model for creation. See Haber, F.C., in Glass, B., Temkin, O. and Straus, W. (eds): Forerunners of Darwin, Baltimore, 1959, p. 251Google Scholar. Darwin, 's Zoonomia, originally published between 1794 and 1796Google Scholar, reached a third edition in 1801, just before Paley's book appeared. It is likely that Paley had some of Darwin's arguments in mind—such as the determination of structure by use. See Paley, , op. cit. (21), pp. 7276Google Scholar. Although he did not mention Hume's Dialogues concerning Natural Religion, it does seem that he sought to counter some of the points in it—such as the problem of treating the world as logically equivalent to its constituent parts. See Le Mahieu, D.L., The Mind of William Paley: A Philosopher and his Age. Lincoln and London, 1976, pp. 6768.Google Scholar

35 Whewell, W., History of the Inductive Sciences, 3 vols. London, 1837, iii, p. 574Google Scholar. Compare Powell, B., Essays on the Spirit of the Inductive Philosophy, the Unity of Worlds, and the Philosophy of Creation. London, 1855, p. 385, 391.Google Scholar

36 For the presence of transmutationist ideas in England prior to Lyell's response, see Corsi, P., ‘The importance of French transformist ideas for the second volume of Lyell's Principles of GeologyBritish Journal for the History of Science, (1978), 11, pp. 221244CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Desmond, A., ‘Robert E. Grant: the social predicament of a pre-Darwinian transmutationist’, Journal of the History of Biology, (1984), 17, pp. 189223.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

37 Lyell, C., The Principles of Geology, 3 vols. London, 18301833, ii, p. 3.Google Scholar

38 Ibid., pp. 13–14. On the qualifications made by Lamarck to the complete continuity of the chain of being, and for the connection between his theory of mutability and his refusal to accept widespread extinction, see Burkhardt, R., The Spirit of System: Lamarck and Evolutionary Biology. Cambridge, Mass., 1977, pp. 54–4, 128137Google Scholar. See also Jordanova, L.J., Lamarck. Oxford, 1984.Google Scholar

39 Quoted in Rupke, N., The Great Chain of History: William Buckland and the English School of Geology (1814–1849), Oxford, 1983, p. 172Google Scholar. For the historicization of the principle of plenitude, see also Rudwick, M., The Meaning of Fossils. London, 1972, pp. 154155.Google Scholar

40 See Winsor, M.P., Starfish, Jellyfish and the Order of Nature. New Haven, 1976, ch. 1.Google Scholar

41 Desmond, , op. cit. (36), pp. 205207.Google Scholar

42 Ibid., p. 201.

43 [Fleming, J.] ‘Systems and methods in natural history’, Quarterly Review, (1892), 41, pp. 302327(327).Google Scholar

44 It is worth noting that such an assumption was not confined to treatises on natural theology. Lyell's discussion of the replacement of extinct species and the filling of any vacant ‘stations’ in the natural economy appears to rest on suppositions about the ‘fullness’ of God's creation. See Lyell, , op. cit. (37), i, p. 140Google Scholar; ii, p. 130. For references to this and to the various relationships between the views of Lyell and Darwin, see Hodge, M.J.S., ‘Darwin and the Laws of the Animate Part of the Terrestrial System (1835–1837): On the Lyellian Origins of his Zoonomical Explanatory Program’, Studies in History of Biology, (1983), 6, pp. 1106 (6, 23)Google Scholar. Although the opponents of transmutation feared the connotations of conceptual plenitude, it would be wrong to see this notion as subsidizing Darwin's theory of evolution. For the suggestion that Darwin saw nature as ‘full’ in the sense of all ecological niches being occupied rather than in the sense of a plenitude of forms, see Worster, D., Nature's Economy: the Roots of Ecology. New York, 1979, pp. 157158.Google Scholar

45 Quoted in Rupke, , op. cit. (39), p. 174Google Scholar. Conybeare was writing in 1821.

46 Bell, C., The Hand, its Mechanism and Vital Endowments, as Evincing Design, 3rd edn.London, 1834, p. 308.Google Scholar

47 Ibid., p. 307.

48 Kidd, J., On the Adaptation of External Nature to the Physical Condition of Man. London, 1833, pp. 335336.Google Scholar

49 Ibid., p. 338.

50 Kirby, W., On the Power, Wisdom and Goodness of God as Manifested in the Creation of Animals, and in their History, Habits and Instincts, 2 vols. London, 1835, i, xxivxxxiiiCrossRefGoogle Scholar. See Appel, T.A., ‘Henri de Blainville and the Animal Series: a nineteenth-century chain of being’, Journal of the History of Biology, (1980), 13, pp. 291317(299)CrossRefGoogle Scholar for Cuvier's attack on de Blainville, Geoffroy, Lamarck and Oken for their failure to distinguish adequately between nature and the Creator.

51 Kidd, , op. cit. (48), p. 335.Google Scholar

52 Lyell, , op. cit. (37), ii, p. 65.Google Scholar

53 Bowler, P.J., ‘Darwinism and the argument from design: suggestions for a reevaluation’, Journal of the History of Biology, (1977), 10, pp. 2943CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Yeo, R., ‘William Whewell, natural theology and the philosophy of science in mid-nineteenth century Britain’, Annals of Science, (1979), 36, pp. 493516 (507–511)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Ospovat, D., The Development of Darwin's Theory: Natural History, Natural Theology and Natural Selection, 1838–1859. Cambridge, 1981, pp. 733, 140143Google Scholar; Lenoir, T., The Strategy of Life: Teleology and Mechanics in Nineteenth Century German Biology. Dordrecht, 1982Google Scholar; Rehbock, P.P., The Philosophical Naturalists: Themes in Early Nineteenth Century British Biology. Madison, 1983.Google Scholar

54 Roget, , op. cit. (17), i, pp. 4748.Google Scholar

55 Quoted in Ospovat, op. cit. (53), p. 34; also pp. 115–116.

56 For these ideas in British comparative anatomy during the early nineteenth century, see ibid., pp. 11–12, 17–23; Rehbock, op. cit. (53), ch. 3. For Roget's possible debt to Grant, see Desmond, , op. cit. (36), pp. 215216.Google Scholar

57 Quoted in Rehbock, , op.cit.(53), p. 56.Google Scholar

58 Roget, , op. cit. (17), ii, p. 627.Google Scholar

59 Paley, , op. cit. (21), pp. 482487Google Scholar. For a contemporary recognition of the spectre of polytheism, see [Gleig, G.R.], ‘Lord Brougham on Natural Theology’, Fraser's Magazine, (1835), 12, pp. 375393(386).Google Scholar

60 MacLeay, W.S., Horae Entomologicae, London, 18191821, p. 169CrossRefGoogle Scholar. MacLeay said that he had been told that his own theory of ‘a chain of being returning into itself militates against those notions of an ascending scale of nature, which are inculcated by revelation’.(162).

61 Kidd, , op. cit. (48), p. 333Google Scholar. Cuvier had asked: ‘What law would have unnecessarily constrained the Creator to produce useless forms, merely to fill voids in a chain, which is only a speculation of the mind?’ Quoted in Appel, , op. cit. (50), p. 299Google Scholar. Adam Sedgwick still thought it necessary to attack the notion of a continuous chain of being as late as 1850. See Sedgwick, A., A Discourse on the Studies of the University of Cambridge, with additions, and a preliminary dissertation, 5th edn. London and Cambridge, 1850, pp. ccxxiccxxvGoogle Scholar. For an earlier rejection, see [Voltaire, ] The Philosophical Dictionary for the Pocket. London, 1765, pp. 7273.Google Scholar

62 Roget, , op. cit. (17), i, pp. 5354.Google Scholar

63 Ibid., ii, p. 627.

64 Ibid., i, p. 50.

65 Kidd, , op. cit. (48), p. 338.Google Scholar

66 Carpenter, W.B., Principles of Comparative Physiology, 4th edn., new title. London, 1854, p. 105CrossRefGoogle Scholar. See also Powell, , op. cit. (35), pp. 388389Google Scholar; Roget, , op. cit. (17), ii, p. 635.Google Scholar

67 Roget, , op. cit. (17), ii, p. 640.Google Scholar

68 See ibid., ii, pp. 628–635 for Roget's interest in the ‘law of Gradation’ and embryology.

69 Buckland, , op. cit. (16), i, p. 585.Google Scholar

70 Roget, , op. cit. (17), ii, pp. 635638Google Scholar. Referring to the discussion of transmutation in the Philosopie Zoologique, he remarked: ‘If this be philosophy, it is such as might have emanated from the college of Laputa’ (638).

71 For opposing positions on this issue in the 1830s, see Whewell, , op. cit. (35), iii, pp. 456478Google Scholar and Powell, B., The Connexion of Natural and Divine Truth. London, 1838, pp. 128135.Google Scholar

72 Owen, R. to Whewell, W., 31 10 1837Google Scholar, Whewell Papers, Trinity College, Cambridge, Add.MS.a.21054.

73 Owen, R., On the Nature of Limbs. London, 1849, pp. 40, 85–86CrossRefGoogle Scholar. On Owen, see MacLeod, R.M., ‘Evolutionism and Richard Owen, 1830–1868: an episode in Darwin's Century’, Isis, (1965), 56, pp. 259280CrossRefGoogle Scholar. For the institutional and ideological context of Owen's work, see Desmond, A., Archetypes and Ancestors: Paleontology in Victorian London 1850–1875. London, 1982Google Scholar and ‘Richard Owen's reaction to transmutation in the 1830s’, British Journal for the History of Science, (1985), 18, pp. 2550.Google Scholar

74 For the shift in Whewell, 's attitude, compare op. cit. (35), iii, pp. 456478Google Scholar and History of the Inductive Sciences, 3rd edn. London, 1857, iii, pp. 553562Google Scholar. Whewell believed that Owen offered a version of transcendental theory suitable to a British audience and referred to his ‘carefully chosen language’ (553). For other favourable responses, see Powell, , op. cit. (35), pp. 135137Google Scholar and McCosh, J. and Dickie, G., Typical Forms and Special Ends in Creation. Edinburgh, 1856.Google Scholar

75 See, for example, Whewell, W., The Philosophy of the Inductive Sciences, 2 vols. London, 1840, i, p. 629Google Scholar for the statement that: ‘The regular form of a crystal, whatever beautiful symmetry it may exhibit … does not prove design in the same manner in which design is proved by the provisions for the preservation and growth of the seeds of plants, and of the young of animals’. Sedgwick wrote to Louis Agassiz expressing anxiety about ‘the opinions of Geoffrey St. Hilaire and his dark school’, warning that these would ‘shut out all argument for design and all notion of a Creative Providence’. Sedgwick, A. to Agassiz, L., 10 04 1845Google Scholar, in Clark, J. and Hughes, T. (eds.): Life and Letters of the Reverend Adam Sedgwick, 2 vols. Cambridge, 1890, ii, p. 86Google Scholar. For the connection between morphology and transmutation in the contemporary debates, see Powell, , op. cit. (35), p. 392.Google Scholar

76 For an extensive study of this controversy which argues that Whewell's rejection of the plurality of worlds was a disguised attack on theories of transmutation, such as that of Robert Chambers, see Brooke, J.H., ‘Natural Theology and the Plurality of Worlds: observations on the Brewster–Whewell Debate’, Annals of Science, (1977), 34, pp. 221286CrossRefGoogle Scholar. For the connection with Whewell's epistemology, see Yeo, op. cit. (53). See also Heffernan, W.C., ‘The singularity of our inhabited world: William Whewell and A.R. Wallace in dissent’, Journal of the History of Ideas, (1978), 39, pp. 81100.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

77 In advising Whewell, Sir James Stephen predicted that ‘the habit of mankind, would be to disbelieve the Evangelists, rather than to disbelieve the Natural Theologians’. Stephen, to Whewell, , 10 11 1853Google Scholar, Whewell Papers, Trinity College, Cambridge, Add.MS.a.216142. For comments on these tensions, see Brooke, , op. cit. (76), pp. 232, 236237Google Scholar, and Bowler, P.J., ‘Sir Francis Palagraveon Natural Theology’, Journal of the History of Ideas, (1974), 35, pp. 144147CrossRefGoogle Scholar. For a criticism of Whewell from a Christian perspective, see: ‘Of the Plurality of Worlds’, British Quarterly Review, (1854), 20, pp. 4548 (81–82).Google Scholar

78 Dick, , op. cit. (13), ch. 6Google Scholar; also McColley, G.M., ‘The seventeenth-century doctrine of a Plurality of Worlds’, Annals of Science, (1936), 1, pp. 385430CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Knight, D.M., ‘Celestial worlds discover'd’, Durham University Journal, (1965), 27, pp. 2329.Google Scholar

79 Brewster, D., More Worlds than One: the Creed of the Philosopher and the Hope of the Christian, new edn. London, 1867, p. 183Google Scholar; first published in 1854. See also Dick, T., Celestial Scenery; or the Wonders of the Planetary System Displayed. London, 1871, p. 343Google Scholar for the remark that ‘so far as we are able to penetrate, it appears demonstrable that matter exists chiefly, if not solely, for the sake and convenience of sensitive and intelligent beings’. Yet it should be noted that this strong nexus between matter and life had already been questioned by the pre-organic eras revealed by geology. Buckland admitted this in his Treatise, Bridgewater, op. cit. (16), i, pp. 5657Google Scholar, and Whewell capitalized on it in his argument with Brewster.

80 [Whewell, W.] Of the Plurality of Worlds: an Essay. Also a Dialogue on the Same Subject. 2nd edn.London, 1854, p. 334.Google Scholar

81 Ibid., p. 330. Compare the following passage from Darwin, 's Origin of Species, 1859, ed. Burrow, J.W., Harmondsworth, 1968, p. 116Google Scholar, cited in Gale, , op. cit. (25), p. 329Google Scholar: ‘We behold the face of nature bright with gladness, we often see superabundance of food; we do not see, or we forget, that the birds which are idly singing round us mostly live on insects or seeds, and are thus constantly destroying life’. Hume had exploited this theme in his attack upon natural theology: ‘What an immense profusion of beings, animated and organized, sensible and active! You admire this prodigious variety and fecundity. But inspect a little more narrowly … The whole presents nothing but the idea of a blind nature, impregnated by a great vivifying principle, and pouring forth from her lap, without discernment or parental care, her maimed and abortive children!’ Hume, D., Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion, 1779, (ed. Aiken, H.D.), New York, 1948, p. 79.Google Scholar

82 ‘The plurality of worlds’, Rambler, (1854), II, 2, pp. 129137 (135–136).Google Scholar

83 ‘The plurality of worlds’, Eclectic Review, (1854), II, 2, pp. 513531 (527–528).Google Scholar

84 [Whewell, ] Of the Plurality of Worlds. 1853Google Scholar, printer's copy containing chapters cancelled from published work, Whewell Papers, Trinity College, ADV.C.16.27, 245. Sedgwick appears to have thought Whewell's book might encourage Pantheism. Whewell could not see the logic of this objection and protested that: ‘The proper antithesis to Pantheism is not intelligent creatures besides man, but a Divine Mind’. Whewell, to Sedgwick, , 8 06 1854Google Scholar, in Douglas, J. Stair, The Life and Selections from the Correspondence of William Whewell, 2nd edn.London, 1882, p. 434.Google Scholar

85 In his own Treatise, Bridgewater, Astronomy and General Physics Considered with Reference to Natural Theology, London, 1834, pp. 269271Google Scholar, Whewell had entertained the likelihood of the plurality of worlds. For the scientific reaction to ‘Vestiges’, see Yeo, R., ‘Science and intellectual authority in mid-nineteenth-century Britain: Robert Chambers and Vestiges of the Natural History of Creation’, Victorian Studies, (1984), 28, pp. 531.Google Scholar

86 Whewell did admit the possibility of animal life on other planets but not the existence of other moral, intellectual beings. Whewell, , op. cit. (80), p. 112, 118.Google Scholar

87 Whewell, , op. cit. (80), p. 318.Google Scholar

88 Whewell, , op. cit. (84), p. 269.Google Scholar

89 Whewell, , op. cit. (80), p. 360Google Scholar; also pp. 363–364.

90 Ibid., p. 364. Owen had in fact inferred the possibility of different forms of life on other planets from the non-existence of possible permutations of the archetype on earth. And in contrast with his other qualifications of teleology, Owen suggested that the support of life was ‘the only conceivable purpose’ of the planets. See Owen, , op. cit. (73), pp. 8384.Google Scholar

91 Whewell, , op. cit. (80), p. 366Google Scholar. For a similar notion, see Sedgwick, A., Discourse on the Studies of the University of Cambridge, 3rd edn.Cambridge, 1834, pp. 106107.Google Scholar

92 Whewell, , op. cit. (80), p. 365.Google Scholar

93 Ibid., p. 366.

94 Heffernan, , op. cit. (76), p. 96Google Scholar remarks that ‘the dissenters [the opponents of the plurality of worlds] were moved by a belief in the intricate design of creation and the sufficiency of man as an end to himself’. But in Whewell's case, as argued above, the affirmation of man's uniqueness was linked with some severe qualifications of the notion of design.