Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-hc48f Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-22T13:26:34.920Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Crisis and the construction of modern theoretical physics

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 March 2007

SUMAN SETH
Affiliation:
Department of Science and Technology Studies, 303 Rockefeller Hall, Cornell University, Ithaca, NY 14850, USA. Email: [email protected].

Abstract

This paper takes up the concept of ‘crisis’ at both historical and historiographical levels. It proceeds through two examples of periods that have been described by historians of physics using a language of crisis. The first examines an incipient German theoretical-physics community around 1900 and the debates that concerned the so-called ‘failure’ of the mechanical world view. It is argued, largely on the basis of what is now an extensive body of secondary literature, that there is little evidence for a widespread crisis in this period. Abandoning the term as both description and explanation, one comes to the far more intriguing suggestion that the conflict over foundations was not evidence of a divisive dissonance but rather of collective construction. What has been termed crisis was, in fact, the practice of theoretical physics in the fin de siècle. The second example is the period either side of the advent of quantum mechanics around 1925. Different subgroups within the theoretical-physics community viewed the state of the field in dramatically different ways. Those, such as members of the Sommerfeld school in Munich, who saw the task of the physicist as lying in the solution of particular problems, neither saw a crisis nor acknowledged its resolution. On the other hand those, such as several researchers associated with Niels Bohr's institute in Copenhagen, who focused on the creation and adaptation of new principles, openly advocated a crisis even before decisive anomalies arose. They then sought to conceptualize the development of quantum mechanics in terms of crises and the revolutions that followed. Thomas Kuhn's language of crisis, revolution and anomaly, it is concluded, arises from his focus on only one set of theoretical physicists. A closer look at intra-communal differences opens a new vista onto what he termed ‘normal’ and ‘revolutionary’ science.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
© 2007 British Society for the History of Science

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

I am indebted to many people for their comments on this paper, and their support as I thought it through. In particular, to Norton Wise, Ole Molvig, Rebecca Press Schwartz, Angela Creager, Peter Dear, David Kaiser, Charlotte Bigg, David Bloor, Michael Gordin, Kevin Lambert, Mike Mahoney, Annik Pietsch, Trevor Pinch, Simon Schaffer, Otto Sibum, Aminda Smith, Richard Staley and the Princeton History of Science Program Seminar. Research for the project was completed while I was a guest researcher at the Deutsches Museum, Munich and a postdoctoral fellow at the Max Planck Institute for the History of Science, Berlin. All translations, unless otherwise stated, are my own.