Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-rcrh6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-20T06:35:03.861Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Kant and the Problem of Peace

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  25 October 2024

Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Extract

Core share and HTML view are not available for this content. However, as you have access to this content, a full PDF is available via the ‘Save PDF’ action button.

Between the philosopher who returns thanks “to nature for the incompatibility, for the envious emulating vanity, for the insatiable appetite to acquire, or even to rule, (for) without them all the excellent natural predispositions in mankind would slumber to all eternity without being developed,” and the General who proclaims that “war is not merely a necessary element in the life of nations, but an indispensable factor of culture,"* for “without war, inferior or decaying races would easily choke the growth of healthy budding elements, and a universal decadence would follow,” there is a striking “air de famille.”

We may well wonder how the old man of Konigsberg, who saw in human struggles “the direction of a wise Creator,” could write an essay on “Perpetual Peace,” and can easily understand how the controversy as to whether Kant were pacifist or imperialist arose.

It can be affirmed without doubt that Kant was at heart a pacifist, his treaty on “Perpetual Peace” being sufficient proof of that. But had he written this essay alone, he would never have gained his present authority among philosophers; he would rapidly have been relegated to the little comer reserved for an Abbé de St. Pierre, a de Tattel, and other utopists.

Kant’s works may be divided into two parts:

(1) his destructive work, which culminates in the Critique of Pure Reason;

(2) his constructive work, with his Critique of Practical Reason, his writings on Morals and Right, and his study on Universal and Perpetual Peace, which “constitutes not merely a part, but whole final purpose and end of the Science of Right.”

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © 1935 Provincial Council of the English Province of the Order of Preachers

References

1 Kant, An Idea of an Universal History in a Cosmopolitwal View.

2 F. von Bernhardi, Germany and the Next War, transl. by Allen H. Powler, p. 14.

3 Ibid., p. 20.

4 Kant, Loc. Cit., Ibid.

5 Kant, The Science of Right, Conclusion, transl. by W. Hastie.

6 Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, p. 36.

7 Kant, Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Ethics, transl. by T. K. Abbot. Third Section, p. 86.

8 Kant, The Science of Right. Preface.

9 Introduction to the Metaphysic of Morals, trans. by T. K. Abbot, iii, 19.

10 The Science of Right. Preface.

11 Introduction to the Metaphysic of Morals, iii, 19.

12 The Science of Right. Preface.

13 Introduction to the Metaphysic of Morals, iii, 20.

14 The Science of Right, p. 33.

15 Sum. Theol., Ia 2ae, q. 1, a. 1.

16 Matt. xv, 18.

17 Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Ethics. Second Section, p. 42.

18 Introduction to the Metaphysic of Morals, iii, 20.

19 Introduction to the Science of Right. Tr. by W. Hastie. Sect. D.

20 The Science of Right, p. 61.

21 Introduction to the Metaphysic of Morals, iii, 20.

22 Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Ethics. Second Section, P. 53.

23 Introduction to the Metaphysic of Morals, iii, 19.

24 Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Ethics. First Section, p. 21.

25 Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Ethics. Third Section, pp. 78–79.

26 Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Ethics. Second Section, p. 55.

27 Ibid., p. 56.

28 Ibid., p. 53.

29 Ibid., Third Section, p. 98.