Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-gb8f7 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-26T03:13:30.331Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Simple nudges that are not so easy

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  11 August 2020

DENISE DE RIDDER*
Affiliation:
Department of Psychology, Utrecht University, Utrecht, The Netherlands
JORAM FEITSMA
Affiliation:
School of Governance, Utrecht University, Utrecht, The Netherlands
MARIËTTE VAN DEN HOVEN
Affiliation:
Ethics Institute, Utrecht University, Utrecht, The Netherlands
FLOOR KROESE
Affiliation:
Department of Psychology, Utrecht University, Utrecht, The Netherlands
THOMAS SCHILLEMANS
Affiliation:
School of Governance, Utrecht University, Utrecht, The Netherlands
MARCEL VERWEIJ
Affiliation:
Philosophy Group, Wageningen University, Wageningen, The Netherlands
TINA VENEMA
Affiliation:
Department of Psychology, Utrecht University, Utrecht, The Netherlands
ANASTASIA VUGTS
Affiliation:
Philosophy Group, Wageningen University, Wageningen, The Netherlands
EMELY DE VET
Affiliation:
Consumption and Healthy Lifestyles Group, Wageningen University, Wageningen, The Netherlands
*
*Correspondence to: Utrecht University – Social, Health, and Organizational Psychology, Utrecht, The Netherlands. Email: [email protected]
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

In this paper, we critically review three assumptions that govern the debate on the legitimacy of nudging interventions as a policy instrument: (1) nudges may violate autonomous decision-making; (2) nudges lend themselves to easy implementation in public policy; and (3) nudges are a simple and effective mean for steering individual choice in the right direction. Our analysis reveals that none of these assumptions are supported by recent studies entailing unique insights into nudging from three disciplinary outlooks: ethics, public administration and psychology. We find that nudges are less of a threat to autonomous choice than critics sometimes claim, making them ethically more legitimate than often assumed. Nonetheless, because their effectiveness is critically dependent on boundary conditions, their implementation is far from easy. The findings of this analysis thus suggest new opportunities for identifying when and for whom nudge interventions are preferable to more conventional public policy arrangements.

Type
Review Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2020. Published by Cambridge University Press

Introduction

More than a decade ago, nudges were introduced as a promising alternative to existing public policies that assume a citizen's ability and willingness to make choices in their own best long-term interests (Thaler & Sunstein, Reference Thaler and Sunstein2008). Nudges capitalize on the insight from behavioural science that human decision-making is not always rational (as determined by ‘narrow logical norms’; Gigerenzer, Reference Gigerenzer2015), which may lead to suboptimal choices in the face of difficult trade-offs between immediate benefits and long-run advantages. This type of choice has been documented in a wide variety of domains with a major impact on both individual lives and society as a whole, including personal finance and unhealthy lifestyles (Szaszi et al., Reference Szaszi, Palinkas, Palfi, Szollosi and Aczel2018). Nudges, which take the form of subtle hints towards more favourable options without forbidding alternative, less desirable options, can support individuals in making better decisions when hindered by myopia, inertia, lack of willpower (Bovens, Reference Bovens, Grüne-Yanoff and Hansson2009) or other documented biases in human reasoning.

Over the past 10 years, nudges have become a popular public policy instrument, as evidenced by the growing number of behavioural insight units that advise national governments on issues involving citizen choices (Whitehead et al., Reference Whitehead, Jones, Howell, Lilley and Pykett2014; Halpern, Reference Halpern2015). International organizations such as the Organisation for Economic Co-operation and Development (OECD, 2017) and the World Bank (2015) have also shown interest in nudges as an alternative for education and persuasion to engage citizens with matters of personal and societal interest, including poverty, early childhood development, productivity and climate change. As the popularity of nudges as a new policy instrument has increased, however, so has the debate about their legitimacy (e.g., Hausman & Welch, Reference Hausman and Welch2010; Johnson et al., Reference Johnson, Shu, Dellaert, Fox, Goldstein, Häubl, Larrick, Payne, Peters, Schkade, Wansink and Weber2012; Sunstein, Reference Sunstein2015), with proponents arguing that nudges acknowledge the bounded rationality in human reasoning, a claim elaborated by research on the heuristics and biases that characterize most human decision-making (Kahneman, Reference Kahneman2003). From this perspective, given that such subtle hints neither coerce nor forbid but involve only a gentle push towards what for most individuals will be the better choice, nudging can contribute to more effective public policies while still respecting citizen autonomy. Opponents, in contrast, criticize the manipulative nature of nudges, as they would exploit inherent weaknesses in human reasoning of which individuals themselves are unaware, which violates a liberal democratic society's requirement of transparency in public policy objectives (e.g., Grüne-Yanoff, Reference Grüne-Yanoff2012; Wilkinson, Reference Wilkinson2013; Nys & Engelen, Reference Nys and Engelen2017). Critics also express concern that government-initiated behaviour change will contribute to the rise of a ‘psychological state’ that interferes with the requirements of human dignity and free choice, thereby posing a threat to citizen autonomy (Jones et al., Reference Jones, Pykett and Whitehead2013; Leggett, Reference Leggett2014).

Whichever the stance taken, both proponents and opponents agree that autonomy is key to determining legitimacy in governmental use of nudging interventions (e.g., Hansen & Jespersen, Reference Hansen and Jespersen2013), while apparently assuming that behaviour change via nudging is easily achieved. Not only do they view nudges as a ‘simple’ (Mani et al., Reference Mani, Mullainathan, Shafir and Zhao2013; Martin et al., Reference Martin, Goldstein and Cialdini2014) tool for generating ‘big returns on small investments’ (Benartzi et al., Reference Benartzi, Beshears, Milkman, Sunstein, Thaler, Shankar, Tucker-Ray, Congdon and Galing2017), they imagine them to be easy to implement in public policy (Dolan et al., Reference Dolan, Hallsworth, Halpern, King, Metcalfe and Vlaev2012; Service et al., Reference Service, Hallsworth and Halpern2014; Halpern, Reference Halpern2015; Benartzi et al., Reference Benartzi, Beshears, Milkman, Sunstein, Thaler, Shankar, Tucker-Ray, Congdon and Galing2017; Mols et al. 2018; OECD, 2018). We, in contrast, posit that these assumptions are not only invalid, but also hinder progress in determining how and when nudges can be most effectively and efficiently applied in public policy. Specifically, we argue that these assumptions require closer scrutiny from each of the disciplines involved in nudging research before significant steps can be taken to employ nudges to steer individual choices for the benefit of all.

To date, however, rather than integrated multidisciplinary effort to reflect critically on these basic assumptions of nudging development and implementation, consideration has occurred in isolation, with behavioural scientists interested in nudging's effectiveness, philosophers considering its ethical requirements and political scientists examining how nudging insights can feed efficiently into public administration procedures. Hence, in this paper, we demonstrate the inefficacy of this isolationist approach by drawing on research from the Welfare Improvement through Nudging Knowledge (WINK) project, which examines nudging from the perspective of three core disciplines: ethics, public administration and psychology. Empirical studies from each of these disciplinary perspectives in our project have recently been published (e.g., Feitsma, Reference Feitsma2018, Reference Feitsma2019; Vugts et al., Reference Vugts, Van den Hoven, De Vet and Verweij2018; Venema et al., Reference Venema, Kroese, De Vet and de Ridder2019, Reference Venema, Kroese, Benjamins and de Ridder2020a, Reference Venema, Kroese, Verplanken and de Ridder2020b). Here, we focus on a synthesized review of the results from these studies, supplemented with literature discussing the issues that we identified as common themes in our multidisciplinary approach.

Based on this analysis, we argue not only that nudging threatens autonomy less than many critics assume, but also that nudging interventions may even promote it. This same research has also documented that nudges are neither easy to implement nor a facile means of changing behaviour – a finding that, although disappointing for nudging enthusiasts, does at least imply that the risk of government manipulation via nudging is far lower than hitherto assumed. By closely examining these fresh insights from the WINK project, we are able to suggest new opportunities for identifying when and for whom nudge interventions will be preferable to more conventional public policy arrangements.

In doing so, we will not focus on different types of nudges, but rather use the generic term ‘nudge’ to describe a diversity of interventions that may differ in scope and design, but have in common the aim of gently steering a choice without forbidding the alternative option (Thaler & Sunstein, Reference Thaler and Sunstein2008). Although we are aware that different categorizations have been proposed with possibly differential underlying mechanisms for specific types of nudges (e.g., Dolan et al., Reference Dolan, Hallsworth, Halpern, King, Metcalfe and Vlaev2012; Münscher et al., Reference Münscher, Vetter and Scheuerle2016), to date there is no widely accepted classification of nudging techniques (Marchiori et al., Reference Marchiori, Adriaanse and de Ridder2017). Moreover, we posit that considerations of ethics, implementation and effectiveness apply to nudges in general, despite their specific features, because there is no unidimensional framework that would predict in what way these reflections interrelate. For instance, whereas a default nudge for organ donation registration may be relatively easy to design and is generally considered to be effective (Johnson & Goldstein, Reference Johnson and Goldstein2003), it can still raise significant political and ethical debate about implementation – which would compromise the efficiency of this approach in public policy (Bramhall, Reference Bramhall2011; https://www.debatingeurope.eu/2017/03/30/everyone-considered-organ-donors-unless-opt/#.XkPhGWhKg2w). In a similar vein, a nudge to promote decreased meat consumption in cafeterias may be a little harder to design but can still be relatively easy to implement, whereas the effects may be relatively weak (Cadario & Chandon, Reference Cadario and Chandon2019). Having said this, we acknowledge that different nudges may speak to different psychological mechanisms. For instance, the typical case of defaults illustrates that it is not easy to discern how this nudge operates on a psychological level, as it is uncertain whether a default speaks to inertia (Smith et al., Reference Smith, Goldstein and Johnston2013), implicit recommendation (McKenzie et al., Reference McKenzie, Liersch and Finkelstein2006) or a reference point (Park et al., Reference Park, Jun and McInnis2000). Yet, for the specific purpose of this review examining the assumptions that dictate the discussion on the legitimacy of nudging as a public policy instrument, we will consider the generic concept of nudges.

Autonomous choice

Because autonomous choice is the cornerstone of democratic liberal societies and an essential requirement for individual well-being (Inglehart et al., Reference Inglehart, Foa, Peterson and Welzel2008; Ryan & Deci, Reference Ryan and Deci2000), the most prominent criticism in ethical debates on nudging is that nudges may violate autonomous choice through patronization or manipulation (Bovens, Reference Bovens, Grüne-Yanoff and Hansson2009; Hansen & Jespersen, Reference Hansen and Jespersen2013; Wilkinson, Reference Wilkinson2013; Baldwin, Reference Baldwin2014). Yet if nudges do not impose a choice, proponents respond: how can they be violating autonomy? In a recent study, we reconciled this dichotomy by revealing that different authors have different conceptions of autonomy (Vugts et al., Reference Vugts, Van den Hoven, De Vet and Verweij2018), although most concerns about nudging's violation of autonomy originate from a classic Millian view of the latter as unrestricted freedom of choice (Mill, Reference Mill1999). From this perspective, making certain choice options more or less prominent may prevent individuals from choosing freely among the available alternatives. Our analysis, in contrast, identified other notions of autonomy that depart from this classical view, including autonomy as agency, which involves an individual's capacity to choose, and autonomy as self-constitution, which relates to individual identity and living the life one wants (Korsgaard, Reference Korsgaard2009).

Although these finer distinctions have been previously noted in the literature, autonomy as agency and, to a lesser extent, as self-constitution are in fact the most endorsed ways of thinking about how nudges relate to autonomy (Vugts et al., Reference Vugts, Van den Hoven, De Vet and Verweij2018). As a result, the implications of the multiple approaches to autonomy have not yet been considered in full. Viewed from the autonomy-as-agency perspective, nudging not only allows for ‘autonomous choice’ – that is, selecting an alternative option without significant cost or effort (Thaler & Sunstein, Reference Thaler and Sunstein2008) − but can even facilitate the choice that individuals would have made given the opportunity (Saghai, Reference Saghai2013). By the same token, nudging may support individuals in making a preferred choice that agrees with their identity (i.e., is in line with their personal goals), but that they would otherwise not have made because of being confused by a multitude of options (Markus & Schwartz, Reference Markus and Schwartz2010). Take, for example, someone who wants to eat healthy snacks in between meals as a replacement for unhealthy snacks (as many people intend but not often manage to do; Verhoeven et al., Reference Verhoeven, Adriaanse, Evers and de Ridder2012), but who sees no opportunities to enact this plan because outlets are packed with unhealthy snacks. Making healthy snacks more accessible by a proximity nudge (Kroese et al., Reference Kroese, Marchiori and de Ridder2015; Van Gestel et al., Reference Van Gestel, Kroese and de Ridder2018) would help this person to consider the alternatives in a more balanced way and thus strengthen their agency insofar as the more prominent placement of the healthy option increases the opportunity to act in accordance with their intention, which would in turn contribute to their healthy-eater identity.

Viewed from the perspectives of autonomy-as-agency and autonomy-as-self-constitution, a choice arrangement that enables individuals to do as they wish may help them live their lives without continual deliberation on how to enact their intentions. It has therefore been argued that making one option more prominent does not undermine autonomy, but rather may actually increase it. That is, the sheer unlimited freedom of choice in many situations may compromise deliberative decision-making capacities and create uncertainty about what to choose, resulting eventually in decision fatigue (Markus & Schwartz, Reference Markus and Schwartz2010; Schwartz & Cheek, Reference Schwartz and Cheek2017). It has even been suggested that many citizens would probably “thank public officers for making the choice easy for them” (John, Reference John2018, p. 110).

As regards such citizen approval, studies on the acceptance of nudges have in fact shown that, to the extent that ‘soft’ paternalism is better appreciated than hard paternalistic imposition of a specific ‘choice’ (Schroeder et al., Reference Schroeder, Waytz and Epley2017), individuals value choice support via nudges both in hypothetical scenarios (Diepeveen et al, Reference Diepeveen, Ling, Suhrcke, Roland and Marteau2013; Junghans et al., Reference Junghans, Cheung and de Ridder2015; Reisch & Sunstein, Reference Reisch and Sunstein2016; Sunstein et al., Reference Sunstein, Reisch and Rauber2017) and in real-life settings (Kroese et al., Reference Kroese, Marchiori and de Ridder2015; Van Gestel et al., Reference Van Gestel, Kroese and de Ridder2018). Nonetheless, the appreciation of nudges as they relate to autonomy is strongly influenced by how they are explained to nudgees. In particular, when the emphasis lies on describing the purpose of the nudge (e.g., “We help you to make a healthy choice”; Junghans et al., Reference Junghans, Cheung and de Ridder2015; Kroese et al., Reference Kroese, Marchiori and de Ridder2015), respondents tend to voice positive attitudes. However, when the explication emphasizes that nudges operate via unconscious influences, respondents tend to show more concern (Wachner et al., Reference Wachner, Adriaanse and de Ridder2020). This observation not only holds for nudges. It has been shown that any description alerting people to potential negative consequences (e.g., manipulation) generally leads to unequivocal disapproval (Kareev & Trope, Reference Kareev and Trope2011). Studies in which people were merely made aware of the presence or purpose of a nudge – either defaults (Bruns et al., Reference Bruns, Kantorowicz-Reznichenko, Klement, Jonsson and Rahali2018) or positioning (Kroese et al., Reference Kroese, Marchiori and de Ridder2015) – suggest that they find choice support as such not to be disconcerting (Loewenstein et al., Reference Loewenstein, Bryce, Hagmann and Rajpal2015; Reisch & Sunstein, Reference Reisch and Sunstein2016; Paunov et al., Reference Paunov, Wänke and Vogel2018; Wachner et al., Reference Wachner, Adriaanse and de Ridder2020).

These differently focused observations demonstrate that nudges may empower individuals to make their actual preferred choices rather than succumbing to the well-documented intention–behaviour gap in which inertia, distraction or brief moments of failing willpower result in non-enactment of about 40% of intentions (Sheeran, Reference Sheeran2002). These different understandings of autonomy also have important implications for the implementation of nudging in public policy, which has prompted concerns of violating liberal democratic principles by luring individuals into unwanted choices (Grüne-Yanoff, Reference Grüne-Yanoff2012). The potential ability of nudging to increase autonomy by enhancing individual agency or self-constitution would not only legitimize the use of behavioural insights in public policy, but also provide strong support for even greater use.

Before discussing the implications of these new autonomy definitions for the debate on nudge effectiveness and nudge implementation in public policy, however, we need to address one other issue that applies to nudging proponents and critics alike. That is, both seemingly endorse individual autonomy as the essential value for judging the use of nudges, implying that less restrictive policies are always preferable over more restrictive options to accommodate citizen autonomy. Yet more restrictive policies have been defended as offering even better opportunities for citizens to act on their personal goals, with beneficial consequences for both individuals and the society as a whole (Conley, Reference Conly2012). Indeed, it has been argued that nudges may also put too much responsibility on individuals where governments should consider paternalistic measures in cases where individuals have little control over their choices (Verweij & Van den Hoven, Reference Verweij and Hoven2012). It is therefore urgent to broaden the autonomy debate from nudges potentially violating personal autonomy to nudges shifting too much responsibility from the state to the individual (Jones et al., Reference Jones, Pykett and Whitehead2013).

Even more importantly, those wishing to implement nudging must take into account other values that inform government policies, including the principles related to solidarity and justice, in which such services as health care and pension programmes are rooted. Highlighting individual autonomy without considering the common good may undermine solidarity and violate the idea that public policies should be beneficial to all, engendering the argument that nudging's ability to benefit the collective should figure more prominently in nudge design (Lynne et al., Reference Lynne, Czap, Czap and Burbach2016; Van der Linden, Reference Van der Linden2018). Given the recognition that values like solidarity and protection from harm are crucial parameters of public policy, there is an urgent need to replace the current focus on autonomy with an emphasis on incorporating these values into any consideration of nudging legitimacy. Discussion of the ethical permissibility of nudges would further benefit from debate on the safeguards that have to be built into the legal and political arrangements for employing nudges in public policy in order to bring them in line with constitutional rule of law values (McCrudden & King, Reference McCrudden, King, Kemmerer, Möller, Steinbeis and Wagner2016).

Easy implementation

Increasing governmental interest in supplementing traditional public policy instruments (e.g., regulation or incentives) with behavioural insights to influence citizen support for public priorities and corresponding policies is exemplified by the early installation of national behavioural insight units in both the UK (2010) and the USA (Obama, Reference Obama2015). In the first instance, former UK Prime Minister David Cameron was so impressed by Thaler and Sunstein's book that he recommended it to all conservative Members of Parliament (McSmith, Reference McSmith2010). Today, an estimated 135 behavioural insights units are in place worldwide, although not all are active in actually designing and implementing interventions (Whitehead et al., Reference Whitehead, Jones, Howell, Lilley and Pykett2014).

This popularity of the nudge concept in governmental circles is driven by the belief that successful policies in such important areas as taxing, traffic and sustainability rely on citizen behavioural commitment. For example, a government wanting to reduce CO2 emissions to meet the Paris climate agreement requirements of 2015 must consider whether citizens can act in accordance with policy objectives and replace grey energy contracts with green ones, install solar screens on their roofs and prioritize using public transport over their own cars (OECD, 2017). Designing policies without considering citizen ability to meet their requirements – what the Netherlands Scientific Council for Government Policy refers to as ‘citizen capacity to act’ (Keizer et al., Reference Keizer, Tiemeijer and Bovens2019) − fails to engage the public in policy objectives and renders the policies less effective.

Not only are behavioural insights required for the design of more effective policies when individual choices matter, but the popularity of nudging among policymakers also appears to be related to the apparent opportunities for easy implementation that would make these policies more efficient (Sanders et al., Reference Sanders, Snijders and Hallsworth2018). That is, they see nudges as ‘fast and furious’ (Haynes et al., Reference Haynes, Goldacre and Torgerson2012) interventions that teams of behavioural science experts can easily add into existing policies as ready-to-use devices (Benartzi et al., Reference Benartzi, Beshears, Milkman, Sunstein, Thaler, Shankar, Tucker-Ray, Congdon and Galing2017). They also consider these teams’ tasks as relatively straightforward in terms of ‘designing a behavioural intervention, testing this intervention rapidly and inexpensively, and then widely implementing the strategies that prove most effective’ (Benartzi et al., Reference Benartzi, Beshears, Milkman, Sunstein, Thaler, Shankar, Tucker-Ray, Congdon and Galing2017; cf., Service et al., Reference Service, Hallsworth and Halpern2014). In reality, however, the process of designing, testing and implementing nudge interventions is far more complicated, which questions the supposed ‘efficiency’ of nudges.

One recurring theme in discussions about behavioural policymaking is the extent to which nudge design and implementation should follow a systematic procedure, of which quick testing is a critical element (Lunn, Reference Lunn2012; John, Reference John2014; Lepenies et al., Reference Lepenies, Mackay and Quigley2018). The typical behaviour expertise approach would be to place the problem under behavioural scrutiny, design and disseminate a nudge based on observations and then evaluate its effectiveness as an intervention (Haynes et al., Reference Haynes, Goldacre and Torgerson2012). Public policy arrangements, however, are rarely designed so linearly, depending rather on (un)planned changes at many different layers and with various policy actors (Cairney, Reference Cairney2017). Consequently, the empirical cycle that behavioural experts usually employ in designing interventions does not map well onto the reality of public policymaking as part of a political process marked by compromise (Feitsma, Reference Feitsma2018; John & Stoker, Reference John and Stoker2019).

These discrepancies were clearly made manifest in an elaborate ethnographic study − involving multiple behavioural insight units – that documented the organization of behavioural expertise in governmental circles (Ball & Feitsma, Reference Ball and Feitsma2019; Feitsma, Reference Feitsma2019). This study identified myriad ways of incorporating behavioural science insights into existing policymaking procedures, including informal networks of small groups of nudge adepts, more elaborate discussion groups of public policy officers, the availability of in-house experts for consultation, the hiring of external consultants and training for large groups of public policy officers on the basics of nudging (Ball & Feitsma, Reference Ball and Feitsma2019; Feitsma & Schillemans, Reference Feitsma, Schillemans, Strassheim and Beck2019; cf., Whitehead et al., Reference Whitehead, Jones, Howell, Lilley and Pykett2014). The research also revealed, however, that only about half of those in behavioural insight units (specifically, those employed in larger units) had a professional background in behavioural science (psychology or behavioural economics; Feitsma, Reference Feitsma2019). As a result, many teams were spending a great deal of time discussing the potentials of nudging without explicitly planning nudge design and implementation, sometimes even focusing primarily on clarifying nudges as a fuzzy concept (Feitsma, Reference Feitsma2019).

Such variations in behavioural insight unit operation illustrate that, in spite of growing recognition of the relevance of behavioural insights, uncertainty remains about how the nudge concept should be integrated into existing protocols and procedures for public policymaking. Yet if treated as standalone interventions implemented in isolation without consideration of the wider policymaking context, nudges will be less effective. Hence, there is an urgent need to develop formats that support the integration of behavioural expertise into public policy (Hansen, Reference Hansen2018; Sanders et al., Reference Sanders, Snijders and Hallsworth2018), a topic largely neglected in behavioural public administration research, which seems more concerned with adopting behavioural insights than with implementing them (Grimmelikhuijsen et al., Reference Grimmelikhuijsen, Jilke, Olsen and Tummers2017).

This need for more sophisticated implementation formats is even more urgent given the shift in most policymaking areas from singular governmental action to more complex governance by multiple actors, including external parties (Peters & Pierre 2001; Levi-Faur, 2014). In these cases, policymakers are not the unique choice architects responsible for setting the conditions for individual choice, but rather must collaborate with public organizations, corporations, non-profit organizations and civil communities. This scenario is even more likely when governments operate as ‘meta-choice architects’ (Jessop, Reference Jessop and Bang2003) influencing how direct choice architects may or may not nudge individuals towards desired behaviours.

All of the above observations highlight the naïveté of viewing nudges as a means of easy policymaking. Rather, acknowledging that public policymaking is an integral part of the political process has major implications for the development of procedures for nudge implementation. First, governments considering the use of nudge interventions to achieve policy objectives dependent on citizen commitment should be aware that these interventions require democratic control procedures well beyond the cycle of developing, testing and implementing simple (often small) discrete nudge interventions (Button, Reference Button2018; Lepenies et al., Reference Lepenies, Mackay and Quigley2018). In fact, successfully incorporating nudges into existing policies requires not only that nudge design and implementation adequately account for the value judgements and ethical considerations of public policy's regular democratic processes, but also that the conception of autonomy goes well beyond the conventional notion of free choice to emphasize the aspects of agency and identity. A more explicit consideration of how nudges can increase decision-making competence and self-reliance will open up new avenues for nudge design and implementation in public policy (cf., Hertwig & Grüne-Yanoff, Reference Hertwig and Grüne-Yanoff2017).

Ease of accomplishing behavioural change

A central assumption in the nudge literature is that because nudges speak to ‘fast’ non-analytical system 1 reasoning (Thaler & Sunstein, Reference Thaler and Sunstein2008), they easily influence behaviour and produce straightforward, predictable effects on decision-making. In fact, the popularity of nudging interventions among scholars and policymakers is largely due to the disappointing results from persuasion-directed behavioural change interventions that rely on ‘slow’ analytical system 2 processing (Marchiori et al., Reference Marchiori, Adriaanse and de Ridder2017). That is, the notion that nudging, by bypassing the need to process all choice pros and cons, enables less effortful decision-making has generated high expectations of nudging as a promising alternative for more traditional interventions (Marteau et al., Reference Marteau, Hollands and Fletcher2012). Nevertheless, whereas nudge proponents consider the potentially large nudge effect from simple interventions to be a major advantage (Martin et al., Reference Martin, Goldstein and Cialdini2014; Service et al., Reference Service, Hallsworth and Halpern2014), nudge critics fear it may lead to government exploitation of reasoning flaws, especially in individuals unaware of their decisions being influenced (John et al., Reference John, Smith and Stoker2009).

Yet even when nudges are used, choices are not as easily modified as generally assumed (Gigerenzer, Reference Gigerenzer2015), with several meta-analyses demonstrating that nudging effects are relatively modest regardless of nudge type and/or target behaviour (Hollands et al. Reference Hollands, Shemilt, Marteau, Jebb, Kelly and Nakamura2013; Szaszi et al., Reference Szaszi, Palinkas, Palfi, Szollosi and Aczel2018; Cadario & Chandon, Reference Cadario and Chandon2019; Hummel & Maedche, Reference Hummel and Maedche2019). One possible explanation for this is the contingency of nudge effects on individual goals and plans. Yet little empirical research to date has explicitly tested the oft-repeated claim that nudges are only acceptable when aligned with existing preferences (Bovens, Reference Bovens, Grüne-Yanoff and Hansson2009), although recent investigations have demonstrated that the impact of nudges on behaviour is critically dependent on these preferences. For example, a default nudge to automatically transfer taxpayer refunds into a savings account proved ineffective when the recipients had already made plans to spend them (Bronchetti et al., Reference Bronchetti, Dee, Huffman and Magenheim2013). Likewise, a centre-stage nudge that positioned the ‘wise’ choice (a small soft drink) in the middle (between medium and large options) to encourage less consumption of sugary soft drinks proved ineffective when excessive customer thirst produced a (nudge-incongruent) preference for large portions. This nudge was also made redundant in those with a strong health goal by a pre-existing (nudge-congruent) preference for a small soft drink (Venema et al., Reference Venema, Kroese, De Vet and de Ridder2019). In fact, nudges exert the strongest influence when individuals are uncertain or ambivalent about their choices and in need of choice support, as in the case of conflicting preferences (Venema et al., Reference Venema, Kroese, Benjamins and de Ridder2020a). Given the ethical debate on nudges potentially violating autonomous choice, these findings provide initial evidence that nudging may support action on ‘medium-size’ preferences (autonomy as self-constitution) and provide assistance in cases of decision uncertainty (autonomy as agency).

These new insights into ‘nudgeability’ (i.e., sensitivity to the influence of nudges; de Ridder et al., Reference de Ridder, Kroese and Van Gestel2020; cf., Goldin, Reference Goldin2015) call for further scrutiny of the processes supposedly underlying nudge effectiveness. One crucial empirical finding in this regard is that, contrary to the prevailing assumption, nudges may not exclusively target system 1 processing, implying that nudge effectiveness is not dependent on the decision-maker being in a system 1 processing mode. Rather, nudges have proven equally effective under low or high self-control (Hunter et al., Reference Hunter, Hollands, Couturier and Marteau2018), low or high cognitive load (Bruns, Reference Bruns2019) and presence or absence of distraction or fatigue (Cheung et al., Reference Cheung, Kroese, Fennis and de Ridder2017). In addition, despite the classic assumption that nudge effectiveness stems from recipient unawareness, explicit explanation of nudging's use does not render it ineffective (Kroese et al., Reference Kroese, Marchiori and de Ridder2015; Loewenstein et al., Reference Loewenstein, Bryce, Hagmann and Rajpal2015; Bruns et al., Reference Bruns, Kantorowicz-Reznichenko, Klement, Jonsson and Rahali2018; Paunov et al., Reference Paunov, Wänke and Vogel2018; Van Gestel et al., Reference Van Gestel, Kroese and de Ridder2018; Wachner et al., Reference Wachner, Adriaanse and de Ridder2020), which again suggests that nudges remain effective even in the presence of an opportunity to deliberate.

An alternative proposal is that system 2 nudges, which directly address the human capacity for reasoning and reflection, should be more effective − and more appreciated by the general public (Sunstein, Reference Sunstein2016) − because they can increase self-knowledge and decision-making competence (Hertwig, Reference Hertwig2017; Hertwig & Grüne-Yanoff, Reference Hertwig and Grüne-Yanoff2017). These findings align with an emerging understanding of the system 1–system 2 processing dichotomy, the theoretical framework that has informed nudging interventions. Debate is increasing on whether human behaviour is indeed governed by two separate systems (Melnikoff & Bargh, Reference Melnikoff and Bargh2018; Bago & De Neys, Reference Bago and De Neys2019) or whether it may be more accurate to talk about fast and slow thinking processes that do not necessarily operate in concert. Put simply, behaviour can be automatic (characteristic of system 1) while still being goal directed (characteristic of system 2). On the other hand, little evidence exists for the notion that fast, automatic processing is irrational or that slow, controlled thinking is inherently intentional. Thus, positioning nudging as a tool to influence behaviour by appealing to system 1 processing may not be accurate given its disregard of the human behavioural complexities not adequately captured by a strict dual system perspective. For nudging research, this revamped conceptualization of dual process theories bears important implications. Indeed, a recent study has suggested that nudges are equally effective regardless of whether people have the capacity to engage in careful thought or not (Van Gestel et al., Reference Van Gestel, Adriaanse and de Ridder2020).

Whereas the insight that nudge effectiveness depends on individual preferences may be disappointing to those who see nudges as a magic bullet, this finding is of great importance to the debate on boundary conditions for nudge implementation in public policy. Equally important is the finding that transparency via explicit notification that nudges are in use does not reduce their effectiveness. The fact that both of these debates centre on the question of whether nudges manipulatively take advantage of system 1 processing − thereby implicitly positioning governments as marketers of their own public policy agendas − in fact turns the seemingly negative message of lower-than-assumed nudge effectiveness into a positive for the continuing dispute over their legitimacy as a policy instrument. Viewed from this positive perspective, nudging has the potential to assist public policy officers struggling with implementation issues to determine when, how and for whom nudges should be employed. Guidelines for policymakers to deal with these pressing issues are required (Hertwig, Reference Hertwig2017).

These insights also generate new directions for the psychological research on nudging, whose finding that attempts to influence decisions are critically dependent on individual preferences and other moderators is based primarily on experimental examination of relatively trivial choices in artificial lab settings with a focus on immediate effects. It is thus urgent that such research begins to address the impact of nudges on major decisions with significant long-term impacts on citizens’ lives, including field experiments with underprivileged populations facing critical choices on health, finance and well-being (Mani et al., Reference Mani, Mullainathan, Shafir and Zhao2013; Ghesla et al., Reference Ghesla, Grieder and Schubert2018; Gillebaart & de Ridder, Reference Gillebaart and de Ridder2019). When conducting these latter experiments, researchers should also assess the acceptability of nudging interventions within these populations. At the same time, to avoid exclusive focus on when and how nudges are effective − which risks the provision of technocratic solutions for public policy issues − psychological research should emphasize the immediate versus the long-term effects of nudging beyond mere efficient steering of behaviour. By doing so, it can supplement the existing survey opinion data with critical insights into when and how nudges contribute to crucial behavioural regulation parameters, including decision-making competence, self-rule and capacity to act.

Discussion

Having critically reviewed three assumptions that dominate multidisciplinary perspectives on the nudging debate − that nudges are a simple, effective means for steering individual choices; that they are easily implemented in public policy; but that they represent a possible threat to autonomous decision-making – we conclude that none is supported by recent research on the ethical, public administration and psychological aspects of nudging. Rather, nudges are ethically more legitimate than is often assumed, but that they are dependent for their effectiveness on boundary conditions and are far from easy to implement. As regards the inherent assumption that autonomy is central to evaluating nudges as a public policy instrument, we identify a new understanding of autonomy as agency or self-constitution that strongly suggests nudging's potential to contribute to autonomy by increasing decision-making competence and helping individuals act upon their own priorities and preferences.

The recent research also provides increasing support for considering values beyond individual autonomy (e.g., solidarity) when judging the suitability of nudging as a public policy instrument. At the same time, the evidence that nudges should not be implemented as standalone interventions in existing policies refutes the assumption that nudge interventions are easily integrated into public policy. In reality, because public policymaking is part of a political process characterized by compromise between multiple actors, nudge implementation requires more sophisticated formats than are currently available. Finally, recent evidence that individual goals and plans are important moderators of nudge effectiveness negates the belief that nudge interventions have straightforward effects on behaviour, especially given emerging evidence that such effectiveness does not rely on a system 1 mode of thinking. Rather, nudges can also be effective when recipients are aware of their presence and have the opportunity to reflect on their choices.

These insights offer an important lesson for psychologists who tout nudge effectiveness without considering its acceptability by public policymakers and the general public and who pay insufficient attention to real-life effectiveness beyond the clean lab setting. At the same time, knowing more about the boundary conditions of nudge effectiveness may inform ethical debates on nudging's potential violation of individual autonomy, pointing rather to its potential to boost autonomous decision-making by providing better opportunities for preferred action. This latter should soften ethical concerns about government manipulation and prompt ethicists to recognize the possibility of public appreciation for choice support. Both psychologists and ethicists should also be more aware of the need for more complex procedures in the public policy context than simple implementation of nudges as standalone interventions. In particular, given both groups’ current focus on the large issues of autonomy and effectiveness, both may underestimate the potentially serious outcomes of public policy officers’ attempts to incorporate behavioural insights into policy arrangements. These practicalities are thus part of an incremental process that is informative to anyone unfamiliar with or neglectful of the nuts and bolts of policymaking.

Conclusion

An integrated perspective on the merits and boundary conditions of nudging interventions has important implications for the debate on nudging legitimacy as a public policy instrument. Acknowledging that nudges may contribute to autonomous decision-making is critical in deciding when nudges should be implemented because of their ability to engage the public in such important public policy issues as public health, climate change and migration, all of which involve more than a subtle steering of individual choice. This acknowledgement also means, however, that studies on nudging effectiveness should move beyond the mere investigation of whether nudges lead to desired choices and incorporate measures of agency and self-constitution to assess whether nudges are truly capable of increasing citizen involvement. Likewise, the realization that public policymaking requires more complex implementation procedures than regular behavioural interventions calls for behavioural experts and public policymakers to develop new methods of collaboration. Lastly, the recognition that nudge effectiveness is not as heavily reliant on an unreflective mind state as once thought should encourage ethicists to soften their critical evaluations while inspiring public policymakers to gear their interventions towards public policies that recognize citizens as competent decision-makers. Overall, then, an integrated perspective can foster the consideration of nudges in terms of autonomous choices that align with individual preferences while also improving chances for implementation by helping public policy officers overcome their hesitation as to when and how a nudge is preferable over more conventional public policy interventions.

Financial support

This research was funded by the Netherlands Organization for Scientific Research (grant number 407-13-030).

References

Bago, B. and De Neys, W. (2019), ‘The Smart System 1: Evidence for the intuitive nature of correct responding on the bat-and-ball problem’, Thinking and Reasoning, 25: 257299. doi: ff10.1080/13546783.2018.1507949ff.ffhal-02106554fCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baldwin, R. (2014), ‘From regulation to behavior change: Giving nudge the third degree’, Modern Law Review, 77: 831857. doi: 10.1111/1468-2230.12094CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ball, S. and Feitsma, J. N. P. (2019), ‘The boundaries of behavioral insights: Observations from two ethnographic studies’, Evidence and Policy. doi: 10.1332/174426419X15643724702722CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Benartzi, S., Beshears, J., Milkman, K. L., Sunstein, C. R., Thaler, R. H., Shankar, M., Tucker-Ray, W., Congdon, W. J. and Galing, S. (2017), ‘Should governments invest more in nudging?’, Psychological Science, 28: 10411055. doi: 10.1177/0956797617702501CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bovens, L. (2009), The ethics of nudge, in Grüne-Yanoff, T. and Hansson, S. O. (eds), Preference change: Approaches from philosophy, economics and psychology, New York: Springer, 207219.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bramhall, S. (2011), ‘Presumed consent for organ donation: A case against’, Annals of The Royal College of Surgeons of England, 93: 270272. doi: 10.1308/147870811X571136bCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bronchetti, E. T., Dee, T. S., Huffman, D. B. and Magenheim, E. (2013), ‘When a nudge isn't enough: Defaults and saving among low-income tax filers’, National Tax Journal, 66: 609635. doi: 10.3386/w16887CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bruns, H. (2019), No evidence that distracted people are easier to nudge. An experiment on the interaction of cognitive scarcity and defaults in a public goods game. Retrieved from http://dx.doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.3417145CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bruns, H., Kantorowicz-Reznichenko, E., Klement, K., Jonsson, M. L. and Rahali, B. (2018), ‘Can nudges be transparent and yet effective?’, Journal of Economic Psychology, 65: 4159. doi: 10.1016/j.joep.2018.02.002CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Button, M. (2018), ‘Bounded rationality without bounded democracy: Nudges, democratic citizenship, and pathways for building civic capacity’, Perspectives on Politics, 16: 10341052. doi: 10.1017/S1537592718002086CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cadario, R. and Chandon, P. (2019), ‘Which healthy eating nudges work best? A meta-analysis of field experiments’, Marketing Science. doi: 10.1287/mksc.2018.1128CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cairney, P. (2017), ‘Evidence-based best practice is more political than it looks: A case study of the ‘Scottish Approach’’, Evidence & Policy, 13: 499515. doi: 10.1332/174426416X14609261565901CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cheung, T. T., Kroese, F. M., Fennis, B. M. and de Ridder, D. T. D. (2017), ‘The Hunger Games: Using hunger to promote healthy choices in self-control conflicts’, Appetite, 116: 401409. doi: 10.1016/j.appet.2017.05.020CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Conly, S. (2012), Against autonomy, Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
de Ridder, D. T. D., Kroese, F. M. and Van Gestel, L. C. (2020), Nudgeability: Mapping conditions of susceptibility to nudge influence. [Manuscript under review]CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Diepeveen, S., Ling, T., Suhrcke, M., Roland, M. and Marteau, T. M. (2013) ‘Public acceptability of government intervention to change health-related behaviors: A systematic review and narrative analysis’, BMC Public Health, 756: 17. doi: 10.1186/1471-2458-13-756Google Scholar
Dolan, P., Hallsworth, M., Halpern, D., King, D., Metcalfe, R. and Vlaev, I. (2012), ‘Influencing behaviour: The Mindspace way’, Journal of Economic Psychology, 33: 264277. doi: 10.1016/j.joep.2011.10.009CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feitsma, J. N. P. (2018), ‘‘Rationalized incrementalism’. How behavior experts in government negotiate institutional logics’, Critical Policy Studies, doi: 10.1080/19460171.2018.1557067Google Scholar
Feitsma, J. N. P. (2019), ‘Brokering behavior change: The work of behavioral insights experts in government’, Policy & Politics, 47: 3756. doi: 10.1332/030557318X15174915040678CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feitsma, J. N. P. and Schillemans, T. (2019), Behavior experts in government: From newcomers to professionals?, in Strassheim, H. and Beck, S. (eds), Handbook of Behavioral Change and Public Policy, Edward Elgar Publishing, 122137).Google Scholar
Ghesla, C., Grieder, M. and Schubert, R. (2018), Nudging the poor and the rich - A field study on the distributional effects of green electricity defaults. doi: 10.2139/ssrn.3147028CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gigerenzer, G. (2015), ‘On the supposed evidence for libertarian paternalism’, Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 6: 361381. doi: 10.1007/s13164-015-0248-1CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gillebaart, M. and de Ridder, D. T. D. (2019), ‘Distinguishing between self-control and perceived control over the environment to understand disadvantaged neighbourhood health and lifestyle outcomes’, Psychology & Health. doi: 10.1080/08870446.2019.1591409CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldin, J. (2015), ‘Which way to nudge? Uncovering preferences in the behavioral age’, The Yale Law Journal, 125: 226-270. doi: 10.2139/ssrn.2570930.Google Scholar
Grimmelikhuijsen, S., Jilke, S., Olsen, A. L. and Tummers, L. (2017), ‘Behavioral Public Administration: Combining insights from public administration and psychology’, Public Administration Review, 77: 4556. doi: 10.1111/puar.12609CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grüne-Yanoff, T. (2012), ‘Old wine in new casks: Libertarian paternalism still violates liberal principles’, Social Choice and Welfare, 38: 635645. doi: 10.1007/s00355-011-0636-0CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Halpern, D. (2015), Inside the nudge unit. How small changes can make a big difference, London: Ebury Publishing.Google Scholar
Hansen, P. G. (2018), ‘What are we forgettin–?’, Behavioral Public Policy, 2: 190197. doi: 10.1017/bpp.2018.13CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hansen, P. G. and Jespersen, A. M. (2013), ‘Nudge and the manipulation of choice: A framework for the responsible use of the nudge approach to behavior change in public policy’, The European Journal of Risk Regulation, 1: 328. doi: 10.1017/S1867299X00002762CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hausman, D. M. and Welch, B. (2010), ‘Debate: To nudge or not to nudge’, The Journal of Political Philosophy, 18: 123136. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-9760.2009.00351.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haynes, L., Goldacre, B. and Torgerson, D. (2012), Test, learn, adapt: Developing public policy with randomised controlled trials, London: Cabinet Office – Behavioral Insights Team.Google Scholar
Hertwig, R. (2017), ‘When to consider boosting: Some rules for policy-makers’, Behavioral Public Policy, 1: 143161. doi: 10.1017/bpp.2016.14CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hertwig, R. and Grüne-Yanoff, T. (2017), ‘Nudging and boosting: Steering or empowering good decisions’, Perspectives on Psychological Science, 12: 973986. doi: 10.1177/1745691617702496CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hollands, G. J., Shemilt, I., Marteau, T. M., Jebb, S. A., Kelly, M. P., Nakamura, R., et al. (2013), ‘Altering choice architecture to change population health behavior: A large-scale conceptual and empirical scoping review of interventions within microenvironments’, BMC Public Health, 13: 1218. doi: 10.1186/1471-3458-13-1218CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hummel, D. and Maedche, A. (2019), ‘How effective is nudging? A quantitative review on the effect sizes and limits of empirical nudging studies’, Journal of Behavioral and Experimental Economics, 80: 4758. doi: 10.1016/j.socec.2019.03.005CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hunter, J. A., Hollands, G. J., Couturier, D. and Marteau, T. M. (2018), ‘Effect of snack-food proximity on intake in general population samples with higher and lower cognitive resource’, Appetite, 121: 337347. doi: 10.1026/j.appet.2017.11.101CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Inglehart, R. F., Foa, R., Peterson, C. and Welzel, C. (2008), ‘Development, freedom, and rising happiness: A global perspective (1981–2007)’, Perspectives on Psychological Science, 3: 264285. doi: 10.1111/j.1745-6924.2008.00078.xCrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Jessop, B. (2003), Governance and meta-governance: On reflexivity, requisite variety and requisite irony, in Bang, H. (ed.), Governance as social and political communication, Manchester: Manchester University Press, 101116.Google Scholar
John, P. (2014), ‘Policy entrepreneurship in UK central government: The behavioral insights team and the use of randomized controlled trials’, Public Policy and Administration, 29: 257267. doi: 10.1177/0952076713509297CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
John, P. (2018), How Far to Nudge? Assessing Behavioral Public Policy, Cheltenham/Northampton: Edward Elgar Publishing.10.4337/9781786430557CrossRefGoogle Scholar
John, P., Smith, G. and Stoker, G. (2009), ‘Nudge nudge, think think. Two strategies for changing civic behavior’, The Political Quarterly, 80: 361370. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-923X.2009.02001.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
John, P. and Stoker, G. (2019), ‘Rethinking the role of experts and expertise in behavioral public policy’, Policy & Politics, 47: 209226. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-923X.2009.02001.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Johnson, E. J. and Goldstein, D. G. (2003), ‘Do defaults save lives?’, Science, 302: 13381339.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Johnson, E. J., Shu, S. B., Dellaert, B. G. C., Fox, C., Goldstein, D. G., Häubl, G., Larrick, R. P., Payne, J. W., Peters, E., Schkade, D., Wansink, B. and Weber, E. U. (2012), ‘Beyond nudges: Tools of a choice architecture’, Marketing Letters, 23: 487504. doi: 10.1007/s11002-012-9186-1CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jones, R., Pykett, J. and Whitehead, M. (2013), Changing behaviors. On the rise of the psychological state, Cheltenham/Northampton: Edward Elgar Publishing.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Junghans, A. F., Cheung, T. T. L. and de Ridder, D. T. D. (2015), ‘Under consumers’ scrutiny. An investigation into consumers’ attitudes and concerns about nudging in the realm of health behavior’, BMC Public Health, 15: 336. doi: 10.1186/s12889-015-1691-8CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kahneman, D. (2003), ‘A perspective on judgment and choice: Mapping bounded rationality’, American Psychologist, 58: 697720. doi: 10.1037/0003-066X.58.9.697CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kareev, Y. and Trope, Y. (2011), ‘Correct acceptance weighs more than correct rejection: A decision bias induced by question framing’, Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 18: 103109. doi: 10.3758/s13423-010-0019-zCrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Keizer, A. G., Tiemeijer, W. and Bovens, M. (2019), Why knowing what to do is not enough. A realistic perspective on self-reliance, Springer Open.10.1007/978-94-024-1725-8CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Korsgaard, C. M. (2009), Self-constitution: Agency, identity, and integrity, Oxford: Open University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kroese, F. M., Marchiori, D. R. and de Ridder, D. T. D. (2015), ‘Nudging healthy food choices: A field experiment at the train station’, Journal of Public Health, 38: 133137. doi: 10.1093/pumed/fdv096CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Leggett, W. (2014).The politics of behavior change: Nudge, neoliberalism and the state’, Policy and Politics, 42: 319. doi: 10.1093/pubmed/fdv096CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lepenies, R., Mackay, K. and Quigley, M. (2018), ‘Three challenges for behavioral science and policy: The empirical, the normative and the political’, Behavioral Public Policy, 2: 174182. doi: 10.1017/bpp.2018.18CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Loewenstein, G., Bryce, C., Hagmann, D. and Rajpal, S. (2015), ‘Warning: You are about to be nudged’, Behavioral Science & Policy, 1: 3542. doi: 10.1353/bsp.2015.0000CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lunn, P. (2012), ‘Behavioral economics and policy making: Learning from the early adopters’, The Economic and Social Review, 43: 423449. https://EconPapers.repec.org/RePEc:eso:journl:v:43:y:2012:i:3:p:423-449Google Scholar
Lynne, G. D., Czap, N. V., Czap, H. J. and Burbach, M. E. (2016), ‘A theoretical foundation for empathy conservation: Toward avoiding the tragedy of the commons’, Review of Behavioral Economics, 3: 243279. doi: 10.1561/105.00000052CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mani, A., Mullainathan, S., Shafir, E. and Zhao, J. (2013), ‘Poverty impedes cognitive function’, Science, 341(6149): 976980. doi: 10.1126/science.1238041CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Marchiori, D. R., Adriaanse, M. A. and de Ridder, D. T. D. (2017), ‘Unresolved questions in nudging research: Putting the psychology back in nudging’, Social and Personality Psychology Compass, 11: e12297. doi:10.1111/spc3.12297CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Markus, H. R. and Schwartz, B. (2010), ‘Does choice mean freedom and well-being?’, Journal of Consumer Research, 37: 344355. doi: 10.1086/651242CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Marteau, T. M., Hollands, G. J. and Fletcher, P. C. (2012), ‘Changing human behavior to prevent disease: The importance of targeting automatic processes’, Science, 337: 14921495. doi: 10.1126/science.1226918CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Martin, S. J., Goldstein, N. and Cialdini, R. (2014), ‘The small big: Small changes that spark big influence’, London: Hachette.Google Scholar
McCrudden, C. and King, J. (2016), The dark side of nudging: The ethics, political economy, and law of libertarian paternalism, in Kemmerer, A., Möller, C., Steinbeis, M. and Wagner, G. (eds), Choice architecture in democracies. Exploring the legitimacy of nudging, Baden Baden: Nomos, 75139.Google Scholar
McKenzie, C. R., Liersch, M. J. and Finkelstein, S. R. (2006), ‘Recommendations implicit in policy defaults’, Psychological Science, 17: 414420. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-9280.2006.01721.xCrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
McSmith, A. (2010, August 12). ‘First Obama, now Cameron embraces ‘nudge theory’’, The Independent.Google Scholar
Melnikoff, D. E. and Bargh, J. A. (2018), ‘The mythical number two’, Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 22: 280293. doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2018.02.001CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Mill, J. S. (1999), On liberty, London: Longman. (Original work published 1859).Google Scholar
Münscher, R., Vetter, M. and Scheuerle, T. (2016), ‘A review and taxonomy of choice architecture techniques’, Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 29: 511524. doi: 10.1002/bdm.1897CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nys, T. and Engelen, B. (2017), ‘Judging nudging: Answering the manipulation objection’, Political Studies, 65: 199214. doi: 10.1177/0032321716629487CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Obama, B. (2015), Executive order—Using behavioral science insights to better serve the American people. Retrieved from https://www.whitehouse.gov/the-press-office/2015/09/15/executive-order-using-behavioral-science-insights-betterserve-American.Google Scholar
OECD (2017), Behavioral Insights and Public Policy. Lessons from Around the World, Paris: OECD Publishing.Google Scholar
OECD (2018), BASIC – A practitioner's toolbox & ethical guidelines for applying behavioral insights in public policy, Paris: OECD Publishing.Google Scholar
Park, C. W., Jun, S. Y. and McInnis, D. J. (2000), ‘Choosing what I want versus rejecting what I do not want: An application of decision framing to product option choice decisions’, Journal of Marketing Research, 37: 187202. doi: 10.1509/jmkr.37.2.187.18731CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Paunov, Y., Wänke, M. and Vogel, T. (2018), ‘Transparency effects on policy compliance: disclosing how defaults work can enhance their effectiveness’, Behavioral Public Policy, 2: 122. doi: 10.1017/bpp.2018.40Google Scholar
Reisch, L. A. and Sunstein, C. R. (2016), ‘Do Europeans like nudges?’, Judgment and Decision Making, 11: 310325. doi: 10.2139/ssrn.2739118CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ryan, R. M. and Deci, E. L. (2000), ‘Self-determination Theory and the facilitation of intrinsic motivation, social development, and wellbeing’, American Psychologist, 55: 6878. doi: 0.1037//0003-066x.55.1.68CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Saghai, Y. (2013), ‘Salvaging the concept of nudge’, Journal of Medical Ethics, 39: 487493. doi: 10.1136/medethics-2012-100727CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sanders, M., Snijders, V. and Hallsworth, M. (2018), ‘Behavioral science and policy: Where are we now and where are we going?’, Behavioral Public Policy, 2: 144167. doi: 10.1017/bpp.2018.17CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schroeder, J., Waytz, A. and Epley, N. (2017), ‘Endorsing help for others that you oppose for yourself: Mind perception alters the perceived effectiveness of paternalism’, Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 146: 11061125. doi: 10.1037/xge0000320CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Schwartz, B. and Cheek, N. N. (2017), ‘Choice, freedom, and well-being: Considerations for public policy’, Behavioral Public Policy, 1: 106121. doi: 10.1017/bpp.2016.4CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Service, O., Hallsworth, M. and Halpern, D. (2014), EAST: Four simple ways to apply behavioral insights. Retrieved from http://www.behaviouralinsights.co.uk/publications/east-four-simple-ways-to-apply-behavioural-insights/Google Scholar
Sheeran, P. (2002), ‘Intention—behavior relations: A conceptual and empirical review’, European Review of Social Psychology, 12: 136. doi: 10.1080/14792772143000003CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, N. C., Goldstein, D. G. and Johnston, E. J. (2013), ‘Choice without awareness: Ethical and policy implications of defaults’, Journal of Public Policy and Marketing, 32: 159172. doi: 10.1509/jppm.10.114CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sunstein, C. (2015), ‘The ethics of nudging’, Yale Journal on Regulation, 32: 6. Available at: http://digitalcommons.law.yale.edu/yjreg/vol32/iss2/6.Google Scholar
Sunstein, C. R. (2016), ‘People prefer System 2 nudges (kind of)’, Duke Law Journal, 66: 121168. doi:10.2139/ssrn.2731868Google Scholar
Sunstein, C. R., Reisch, L. A. and Rauber, J. (2017), A worldwide consensus on nudging? Not quite, but almost. Regulation and Governance. doi: 10.1111/rego.12161.Google Scholar
Szaszi, B., Palinkas, A., Palfi, B., Szollosi, A. and Aczel, B. (2018), ‘A systematic scoping review of the choice architecture movement: Toward understanding when and why nudges work’, Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 31: 355366. doi:10.1002/bdm.2035.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thaler, R. H. and Sunstein, C. S. (2008), ‘Nudge’, Improving decisions about health, wealth, and happiness. Penguin Books.Google Scholar
Van der Linden, S. (2018), ‘The future of behavioral insights: On the importance of socially situated nudges’, Behavioral Public Policy, 2: 207217. doi:10.1017/bpp.2018.22CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Van Gestel, L. C., Adriaanse, M. A. and de Ridder, D. T. D. (2020), ‘Unraveling the effects of a default nudge under type 1 and type 2 processing’, Comprehensive Results in Social Psychology (Preregistered Stage 1 Manuscript accepted for publication).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Van Gestel, L. C., Kroese, F. M. and de Ridder, D. T. D. (2018), ‘Nudging at the checkout counter - A longitudinal study of the effect of a food repositioning nudge on healthy food choice’, Psychology & Health, 33: 800809. doi: 10.1080/08870446.2017.1416116CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Venema, T. A. G., Kroese, F. M., Benjamins, J. S. and de Ridder, D. T. D. (2020a), ‘When in doubt, follow the crowd? Responsiveness to social proof nudges in the absence of clear preferences’, Frontiers in Psychology Cognition, 11. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2020.01385Google ScholarPubMed
Venema, T.A.G, Kroese, F. M., De Vet, E. and de Ridder, D. T. D. (2019), ‘The one that I want: Strong personal preferences render the center-stage nudge redundant’, Food Quality and Preference, 78: 103744. doi: 10.1016/j.foodqual.2019.103744CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Venema, A. G., Kroese, F. M., Verplanken, B. and de Ridder, D. T. D. (2020b), ‘The (bitter) sweet taste of nudge effectiveness: The role of habits in a portion size nudge, a proof of concept study’, Appetite, 151. doi: 10.1016/j.appet.2020.104699CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Verhoeven, A. A. C., Adriaanse, M. A., Evers, C. and de Ridder, D. T. D. (2012), ‘The power of habits: Unhealthy snacking behavior is primarily predicted by habit strength’, British Journal of Health Psychology, 17: 758770. doi: 10.1111/j.2044-8287.2012.02070.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Verweij, M. and Hoven, Van den, M. (2012).Nudges in public health: Paternalism is paramount’, American Journal of Bioethics, 12: 1617. doi: 10.1080/15265161.2011.634489CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Vugts, A., Van den Hoven, M., De Vet, M. and Verweij, E. (2018), ‘How autonomy is understood in discussions on the ethics of nudging’, Behavioral Public Policy, 2: 116. doi:10.1017/bpp.2018.5Google Scholar
Wachner, J., Adriaanse, M. A. and de Ridder, D. T. D. (2020), And how will that make you feel? Expectations about nudging affecting autonomy. [Manuscript under review]Google Scholar
Whitehead, M., Jones, R., Howell, R., Lilley, R. and Pykett, J. (2014), Nudging all over the World. Economic and Social Research Council of the UK.Google Scholar
Wilkinson, T. M. (2013), ‘Nudging and manipulation’, Political Studies, 61: 341355. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-9248.2012.00974.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
World Bank (2015), Mind, Society and Behavior, Washington: World Bank Group.Google Scholar