Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-8ctnn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-23T23:15:02.610Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Tyranny and Self-Knowledge: Critias and Socrates in Plato's Charmides

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 August 2014

Paul Stern*
Affiliation:
Ursinus College

Abstract

Thinkers such as Derrida and Levinas locate the source of the totalitarian tyrannies of our century in totalizing thought, the view that claims the whole is perfectly explicable. Their response maintains that there is no determinate knower and thus no access to enduring intelligibles. This response, however, subverts any claims to political truth, leaving no principles as a basis for political judgment. Plato's Charmides provides a corrective of this difficulty. In this dialogue, Socrates discusses self-knowledge with Critias, who advocates a tyranny founded precisely on a claim of comprehensive knowledge and control. Socrates responds to this theory-based tyranny with a view of the elusiveness of self-knowledge that denies Critias' claim to know the human good with the precision necessary to establish his error-free society. But furthermore, this elusiveness is itself intelligible; possessing a discernible structure, it can substantiate specific political principles. Thus, Plato shows how we might resist such tyranny without subverting the very principles that allow us to judge it unjust.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © American Political Science Association 1999

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

Arendt, Hannah. 1973. The Origins of Totalitarianism. New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich.Google Scholar
Aristotle, . 1957. Politica, ed. Ross, W. D.. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
Benardete, Seth. 1984. The Being of the Beautiful: Plato's “Theaetetus,” “Sophist,” and “Statesman.” Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Benardete, Seth. 1986. “On Interpreting Plato's Charmides.” Graduate Faculty Philosophy Journal 11 (2): 936.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boesche, Roger. 1996. Theories of Tyranny from Plato to Arendt. University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press.Google Scholar
Bruell, Christopher. 1977. “Socratic Politics and Self-Knowledge: An Interpretation of Plato's Charmides.” Interpretation 6 (3): 141203.Google Scholar
Burnyeat, M. F. 1978. “Aristotle on Understanding Knowledge.” In Aristotle on Science: The Posterior Analytics, ed. Berti, Enrico. Padua: Editrice Antenore. Pp. 97139.Google Scholar
Coolidge, Francis. 1993. “The Relation of Philosophy to Sophrosune: Zalmoxian Medicine in Plato's Charmides.” Ancient Philosophy 13 (Spring: 2336.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Critchley, Simon. 1992. The Ethics of Deconstruction, Derrida and Levinas. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Crombie, I. M. 1962. An Examination of Plato's Doctrines. 2 vols. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Derrida, Jacques. 1973. Speech and Phenomena and Other Essays on Husserl's Theory of Signs. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.Google Scholar
Derrida, Jacques. 1978. “Freud and the Scene of Writing.” In Writing and Difference, trans. Bass, Alan. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Pp. 196231.Google Scholar
Derrida, Jacques. 1981. “Plato's Pharmacy.” In Dissemination, trans. Johnson, Barbara. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Pp. 63171.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Derrida, Jacques. 1982. “Difference.” In Margins of Philosophy, trans. Bass, Alan. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Pp. 127.Google Scholar
Derrida, Jacques. 1988. “Like the Sound of the Sea Deep within a Shell: Paul de Man's War,” trans. Kamuf, Peggy. Critical Inquiry 14 (Spring): 648.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Freeman, Kathleen. 1948. Ancilla to the Pre-Socratic Philosophers. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Guthrie, W. K. C. 1969. A History of Greek Philosophy, vol. III. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Griswold, Charles L. 1986. Self-Knowledge in Plato's Phaedrus. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Hyland, Drew. 1981. The Virtue of Philosophy. Athens: Ohio University Press.Google Scholar
Irwin, Terence. 1977. Plato's Moral Theory: The Early and Middle Dialogues. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
Kahn, Charles H. 1996. Plato and the Socratic Dialogue. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Klosko, George. “The Technical Conception of Virtue.” Journal of the History of Philosophy 19 (January: 95102.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levinas, Emmanuel. 1969. Totality and Infinity, trans. Lingis, Alphonso. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.Google Scholar
Levinas, Emmanuel. 1981. Otherwise than Being or Beyond Essence, trans. Lingis, Alphonso. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.Google Scholar
Levinas, Emmanuel. 1987a. “Meaning and Sense.” In Collected Philosophical Papers, trans. Lingis, Alphonso. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff. Pp. 75107.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levinas, Emmanuel. 1987b. “Philosophy and the Idea of Infinity.” In Collected Philosophical Papers, trans. Lingis, Alphonso. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff. Pp. 4759.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levinas, Emmanuel. 1989a. “Is Ontology Fundamental?” trans. Atterton, Peter. Philosophy Today 33 (Summer): 121–9.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levinas, Emmanuel. 1989b. “Time and the Other.” In The Levinas Reader. Oxford: Blackwell. Pp. 3758.Google Scholar
Levine, David Lawrence. 1984. “The Tyranny of Scholarship.” Ancient Philosophy 4: 6572.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lyons, John. 1969. Structural Semantics, An Analysis of Part of the Vocabulary of Plato. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Mara, Gerald. 1997. Socrates' Discursive Democracy. Albany: SUNY Press.Google Scholar
McClintock, Anne, and Nixon, Rob. 1986. “No Names Apart: The Separation of Word and History in Derrida's ‘Le Dernier Mot du Racisme.’Critical Inquiry 13 (Autumn): 140–54.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morris, T. F. 1989. “Knowledge of Knowledge and Lack of Knowledge in the Charmides.” International Studies in Philosophy 21 (1): 4961.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
North, Helen. 1966. Sophrosyne. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, Martha. 1986. The Fragility of Goodness. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Plato, . 1983. Platonis Opera, ed. Burnet, John. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Roochnik, David. 1986. “Socrates's Use of the Techne-Analogy.” Journal of the History of Philosophy 24 (July: 295310.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Roochnik, David. 1996. Of Art and Wisdom: Plato's Understanding of Techne. University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press.Google Scholar
Rosen, Stanley. 1987. Plato's “Symposium.” New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Rosen, Stanley. 1989. “Sophrosyne and Selbtsbewusstsein.” In The Ancients and the Moderns: Rethinking Modernity. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Pp. 83106.Google Scholar
Rutherford, R. B. 1995. The Art of Plato. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Santas, Gerasimos X. 1973. “Socrates at Work on Virtue and Knowledge in Plato's Charmides.” In Exegesis and Argument: Studies in Greek Philosophy Presented to Gregory Vlastos, ed. Lee, E. N.. Phronesis, supl. vol. 1. Assen, Netherlands: Van Gorcum. Pp. 105–32.Google Scholar
Schmid, W. Thomas. 1981. “Socrates' Practice of Elenchus in the Charmides.” Ancient Philosophy 2 (Spring): 141–7.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schmid, W. Thomas. 1983. “Socratic Moderation and Self-Knowledge.” Journal of the History of Philosophy 21 (July: 339–48.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sprague, Rosamond. 1976. Plato's Philosopher-King: A Study of the Theoretical Background. Columbia: University of South Carolina Press.Google Scholar
Strauss, Leo. 1991. On Tyranny. New York: Free Press.Google Scholar
Tuckey, T. G. 1951. Plato's “Charmides.” Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Wellman, Robert. 1964. “The Question Posed at Charmides 165a–165c.” Phronesis 9 (2): 107–13.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wolfsdorf, David. 1997. “Aporia in Plato's Charmides, Laches, and Lysis.” Ph.D. diss. University of Chicago.Google Scholar
West, Thomas G. and West, Grace Starry. 1986. Plato “Charmides.“ Indianapolis, IN: Hackett.Google Scholar
Xenophon, . 1985. Hellenica, trans. Brownson, Carleton L.. 2 vols. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Xenophon, . 1994. Memorabilia, trans. Bonnette, Amy L.. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Zuckert, Catherine. 1991. “The Politics of Derridean Deconstruction.” Polity 23 (1): 335–56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zuckert, Catherine. 1997. Postmodern Platos. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Submit a response

Comments

No Comments have been published for this article.