Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-lj6df Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-05T10:17:10.900Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Motive and Goal in Hannah Arendt's Concept of Political Action

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 August 2014

James T Knauer*
Affiliation:
Lock Haven State College

Abstract

Hannah Arendt's work is of major importance primarily because of the categories of thought she originates, especially her concept of political action. But this concept has frequently been criticized for being irrelevant to, or incapable of comprehending, strategic concerns. This criticism however, is based on a misreading of Arendt on the relationship of specific motives and goals to political action. The critical interpretations of three commentators are considered here: Kirk Thompson, Jürgen Habermas, and Martin Jay. A detailed explication of the relevant texts from Arendt demonstrates the misreading of Arendt on which these criticisms are based and at the same time reveals the subtlety and power of Arendt's conception of the relationship between instrumentality and meaning in political action. Once this relationship is correctly understood, it becomes possible to appreciate the implications of Arendt's work for questions of political strategy.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © American Political Science Association 1980

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Arendt, Hannah (1953). “Understanding and Politics.” Partisan Review 20: 377–92.Google Scholar
Arendt, Hannah (1958). The Human Condition. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Arendt, Hannah (1963). On Revolution. New York: Viking Press.Google Scholar
Arendt, Hannah (1968). Between Past and Future: Eight Exercises in Political Thought. New York: Viking Press.Google Scholar
Arendt, Hannah (1972). Crises of the Republic. New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich.Google Scholar
Aristotle, (1946). Politics. Edited and translated by Barker, Emest. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Botstein, Leon (1978). “Hannah Arendt: Opposing Views.” Partisan Review 45: 368–80.Google Scholar
Habermas, Jürgen (1970a). “On Systematically Distorted Communication.” Inquiry 13: 205–18.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Habermas, Jürgen (1970b). “Towards a Theory of Communicative Competence.” Inquiry 13: 360–75.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Habermas, Jürgen (1977). “Hannah Arendt's Communications Concept of Power.” Social Research 44: 324.Google Scholar
Isaak, Robert A., and Hummel, Ralph P. (1975). Politics for Human Beings. North Scituate, Mass.: Duxbury Press.Google Scholar
Jay, Martin (1978). “Hannah Arendt: Opposing Views.” Partisan Review 45: 348–67.Google Scholar
Knauer, James T (1976). “Hannah Arendt and the Reassertion of the Political: Toward a New Democratic Theory.” Ph.D. dissertation, State University of New York, Binghamton.Google Scholar
O'Sullivan, N. K. (1973). “Politics, Totalitarianism and Freedom: The Political Thought of Hannah Arendt.” Political Studies 21:183–98.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schwartz, Benjamin I. (1970). “The Religion of Politics.” Dissent 17: 144–61.Google Scholar
Thompson, Kirk (1969). “Constitutional Theory and Political Action.” Journal of Politics 31: 655–81.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Submit a response

Comments

No Comments have been published for this article.