Hostname: page-component-7bb8b95d7b-5mhkq Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-10-04T23:48:38.989Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Missing the Archimedean Point: Liberalism's Institutional Presuppositions

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 August 2014

Robert Grafstein*
Affiliation:
University of Georgia

Abstract

Though liberalism has been widely criticized for its attempt to frame a detached judgment of society based on an asocial conception of individuals, insufficient attention has been paid to the particular social and political relationships this search for an Archimedean point presupposes. Using collective choice theory, I show that liberalism has adopted two distinct kinds of Archimedean points reflecting different and unjustified presuppositions about the true institutional relation between politics and society. Liberalism's Archimedean search is not merely unsuccessful but biased in a way that is significant even for positions critical of liberalism. It is possible, I argue, to have a normative political theory that avoids an asocial conception of individuals without falling victim to liberalism's specific biases concerning institutional relations. The implications for both Rawlsian- or Nozickian-style liberalism are discussed, including the possibility of a political philosophy that avoids their “analytical extremism.“

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © American Political Science Association 1990

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Ackerman, Bruce A. 1980. Social Justice in the Liberal State. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Anderson, Charles W. 1986. “Pragmatic Liberalism: Uniting Theory and Practice.” In Liberals on Liberalism, ed. Damico, Alfonso J.. Totowa, NJ: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
Arrow, Kenneth J. 1963. Social Choice and Individual Values. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Arrow, Kenneth J. 1984. Social Choice and Justice. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Aumann, Robert J., and Kurz, Mordecei. 1977. “Power and Taxes.” Econometrica 45: 1137–61.Google Scholar
Bachrach, Peter, and Baratz, Morton S.. 1970. Power and Poverty. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Barry, Brian. 1986. “Lady Chatterly's Lover and Doctor Fischer's Bomb Party.” In Foundations of Social Choice Theory, ed. Elster, Jon and Hylland, Aanund. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Becker, Gary S. 1976. The Economic Approach to Human Behavior. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Becker, Gary S. 1983. “A Theory of Competition among Pressure Groups for Political Influence.” Quarterly Journal of Economics 98: 371400.Google Scholar
Becker, Gary S. 1985. “Public Policies, Pressure Groups, and Dead Weight Costs.” Journal of Public Economics 28: 329–47.Google Scholar
Berlin, Isaiah. 1969. Four Essays on Liberty. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Brennan, Geoffrey, and Buchanan, James M.. 1985. The Reason of Rules: Constitutional Political Economy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Buchanan, James M. 1975. The Limits of Liberty. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Buchanan, James M. 1987. “The Constitution of Economic Policy.” Science 236: 1433–36.Google Scholar
Buchanan, James M., and Tullock, Gordon. 1962. The Calculus of Consent. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.Google Scholar
Care, Norman S. 1985. “Critical Review of Sandel's Liberalism.” Noûs 19:459–67.Google Scholar
Chapman, Bruce. 1983. “Rights and Constraints: Nozick versus Sen.” Theory and Decision 15.1–10.Google Scholar
Coleman, Jules L. 1988. Markets, Morals, and the Law. Cambridge: University Press.Google Scholar
Dahl, Robert A., and Lindblom, Charles E.. 1953. Politics, Economics, and Welfare. New York: Harper & Row.Google Scholar
Damico, Alfonso J., ed. 1986. Liberals on Liberalism: Totowa, NJ: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
Dworkin, Ronald. 1981. “What Is Equality?” Part 1. “Equality of Welfare.” Philosophy and Public Affairs 10: 185246.Google Scholar
Dworkin, Ronald. 1985. A Matter of Principle. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Elster, Jon. 1986. “The Market and the Forum: Three Varieties of Political Theory.” In Foundations of Social Choice Theory, ed. Elster, Jon and Hylland, Aanund. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Frohock, Fred M. 1987. Rational Association. Ithaca: Syracuse University Press.Google Scholar
Galston, William A. 1988. “Liberal Virtues.” American Political Science Review 82: 1277–89.Google Scholar
Gibbard, Alan. 1974. “A Pareto-consistent Libertarian Claim.” Journal of Economic Theory 7: 388410.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gill, Emily R. 1986. “Goods, Virtues, and the Constitution of the Self.” In Liberals on Liberalism, ed. Damico, Alfonso J.. Totowa, NJ: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
Grafstein, Robert. 1987. “The Significance of Modern State of Nature Theory.” Polity 19: 529–50.Google Scholar
Grafstein, Robert. 1988. “The Problem of Institutional Constraint.” Journal of Politics 50: 577–99.Google Scholar
Grafstein, Robert. 1989. “Getting the Whole To Play Its Part.” Social Choice and Welfare 6: 7783.Google Scholar
Green, Edward J. 1982. “Equilibrium and Efficiency under Pure Entitlement Systems.” Public Choice 39: 185212.Google Scholar
Gutmann, Amy. 1985. “Communitarian Critics of Liberalism.” Philosophy and Public Affairs 14: 308–22.Google Scholar
Hampton, Jean. 1980. “Contracts and Choices: Does Rawls Have a Social Contract Theory?Journal of Philosophy 77: 315–38.Google Scholar
Hare, R. M. 1974. “Rawls' Theory of Justice.” In Reading Rawls, ed. Daniels, Norman. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Hirshleifer, Jack. 1987. Economic Behaviour in Adversity. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Litan, Robert E. 1977. “On Rectification in Nozick's Minimal State.” Political Theory 5: 233–46.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maclntyre, Alasdair. 1981. After Virtue. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
Macpherson, Crawford B. 1962. The Political Theory of Possessive Individualism. London: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Millikan, Ruth Garrett. 1984. Language, Thought, and Other Biological Categories. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Moulin, Hervé, and Roemer, John. 1989. “Public Ownership of the External World and Private Ownership of the Self.” Journal of Political Economy 97: 347–67.Google Scholar
Nozick, Robert. 1974. Anarchy, State, and Utopia. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Peltzman, Sam. 1976. “Toward a More General Theory of Regulation.” Journal of Law and Economics 19: 211–40.Google Scholar
Perelli-Minetti, C. R. 1977. “Nozick on Sen: A Misunderstanding.” Theory and Decision 8: 387–93.Google Scholar
Plott, Charles. 1976. “Axiomatic Social Choice Theory: An Overview and Interpretation.” American Journal of Political Science 20: 511–96.Google Scholar
Pressler, Jonathan. 1987. “Rights and Social Choice.” Economics and Philosophy 3: 122.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rae, Douglas W. 1975. “The Limits of Consensual Decision.” American Political Science Review 69: 1270–94.Google Scholar
Rawls, John. 1971. A Theory of Justice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Rawls, John. 1980. “Kantian Constructivism in Moral Theory.” Journal of Philosophy 77: 515–72.Google Scholar
Rawls, John. 1985. “Justice as Fairness: Political Not Metaphysical.” Philosophy and Public Affairs 14: 223–51.Google Scholar
Rawls, John. 1987. “The Idea of an Overlapping Consensus.” Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 7: 125.Google Scholar
Roemer, John. 1982. A General Theory of Exploitation and Class. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sandel, Michael. 1982. Liberalism and the Limits of Justice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Sen, Amartya. 1982. Choice, Welfare, and Measurement. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Sen, Amartya. 1983. “Liberty and Social Choice.” Journal of Philosophy 80: 528.Google Scholar
Sen, Amartya. 1986. “Foundations of Social Choice Theory: An Epilogue.” In Foundations of Social Choice Theory, ed. Elster, Jon and Hylland, Aanund. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Steiner, Hillel. 1977. “Justice and Entitlement.” Ethics 87: 150–52.Google Scholar
Sugden, Robert. 1981. The Political Economy of Public Choice. Oxford: Martin Robertson.Google Scholar
Sugden, Robert. 1985. “Why Be Consistent? A Critical Analysis of the Consistency Requirements in Choice Theory.” Economica 52: 167–83.Google Scholar
Suppes, P. 1988. “Lorenz Curves for Various Processes: A Pluralistic Approach to Equity.” Social Choice and Welfare 5: 8991.Google Scholar
Taylor, Michael. 1987. The Possibility of Cooperation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Unger, Roberto Mangabeira. 1987. False Necessity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Walzer, Michael. 1983. Spheres of Justice. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Wolfinger, Raymond E. 1971. “Nondecisions and the Study of Local Politics.” American Political Science Review 65: 1063–80.Google Scholar
Submit a response

Comments

No Comments have been published for this article.