Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-gxg78 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-23T05:27:55.821Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Liberal Plebeianism: John Stuart Mill on Democracy, Oligarchy, and Working-Class Mobilization

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  11 July 2022

GORDON ARLEN*
Affiliation:
Swarthmore College, United States
*
Gordon Arlen, Visiting Assistant Professor, Department of Political Science, Swarthmore College, United States, [email protected].
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

How should democratic societies address inequality in an age of plutocratic encroachment and populist indignation? What role should popular movements play in progressive reform efforts? This article turns to the nineteenth-century liberalism of John Stuart Mill for insights on an essential challenge facing democracy today: how to mobilize social movements against intensifying oligarchic threats while safeguarding liberal-democratic values. I advance a novel reading of Mill as a proponent of “liberal plebeianism”—that is, as an activist-theorist who confronted the threat of oligarchy by promoting working-class mobilization within a liberal, parliamentary framework. I trace two discourses within Mill’s writings and speeches: an antioligarchic discourse focused on countering “sinister interests” and a mobilization discourse focused on working-class incorporation. Both follow from Mill’s conviction that liberal reformers should operate as “tribunes of the poor.” This reading helps to clarify Mill’s contested legacy and provides potential resources for understanding how a plebeian orientation might enliven liberal democracy today.

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2022. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of the American Political Science Association

Introduction

How can contemporary democracies mobilize citizens to confront the challenges posed by plutocracy while avoiding the excesses of populism? Does the liberal tradition offer resources for addressing our moment of “democratic deconsolidation” (Levitsky and Ziblatt Reference Levitsky and Ziblatt2018), when oligarchic power is becoming more entrenched (Winters Reference Winters2011) and illiberal authoritarian alternatives more salient (Applebaum Reference Applebaum2020)? This article turns to the nineteenth-century liberalism of John Stuart Mill to help address these questions. I advance a novel reading of Mill as a proponent of “liberal plebeianism”: I present Mill as a theorist-activist who confronted the threat of oligarchy by vigorously advocating for working-class mobilization within a liberal parliamentary framework. I argue for liberal plebeianism as a normative-political posture that can enhance democratic aspirations in our age of plutocracy and populism.

Throughout his life, Mill deployed two political discourses that, together, constituted his liberal plebeianism: an antioligarchic discourse denouncing the “sinister interests” of socioeconomic elites and a popular mobilization discourse directed at incorporating the British working classes into a liberal reform coalition. Mill inherited the antioligarchic discourse from the radical Benthamite circles of his youth, and he developed the discourse of popular mobilization through his lifelong political activism. But it is the intersection of these discourses that proves so salient for contemporary challenges. In a neglected passage from 1837, Mill uses explicitly plebeian imagery, arguing that liberal reformers must operate as “tribunes of the poor” (Mill Reference Mill and Robson1982b, 396). Mill took on the task of becoming a “tribune of the poor,” a mediator who could ally with workers against oligarchs while simultaneously mediating between workers and other liberal reformers.

Liberalism, Plebeianism, and Contemporary Democracy

I offer this reading as a contribution to the “plebeian” turn in contemporary democratic theory. Recent democratic theorists have developed plebeian approaches in response to the increasingly unequal and oligarchic shape of contemporary political life (Arlen Reference Arlen2019; Breaugh Reference Breaugh and Lederhendler2013; Green Reference Green2016; Hamilton Reference Hamilton2014; Kalyvas Reference Kalyvas2019; McCormick Reference McCormick2011; Mulvad and Stahl Reference Mulvad and Stahl2019; Vergara Reference Vergara2020). Insofar as wealth concentration persists in environments where capital returns exceed rates of economic growth, Thomas Piketty (Reference Piketty and Goldhammer2014) argues, the political power of those with great wealth will increase. Numerous empirical political scientists have confirmed that this is happening (Bartels Reference Bartels2008; Gilens Reference Gilens2012; Winters Reference Winters2011; Winters and Page Reference Winters and Page2009). In this context, many plebeian democrats criticize mainstream liberalism for insufficiently attending to the deleterious effects of substantive inequalities—what Jeffrey Green (Reference Green2016) calls “the shadow of unfairness.” They worry that liberal norms of formal equality cannot protect citizens from oligarchic domination and systemic corruption.

Plebeian democrats respond to substantive inequality with new institutional proposals and novel theoretical approaches. Their proposals include plebeian constituent assemblies (Vergara Reference Vergara2020) and class-specific minipublics composed exclusively of nonwealthy citizens (McCormick Reference McCormick2011). And they make several important theoretical contributions to respond to contemporary inequality: they embrace plebeian identity as an intersubjective status, constructed around common citizens’ shared experience of vulnerability to “oligarchic harm” (Arlen Reference Arlen2019); they draw inspiration from premodern institutions, like the Athenian jury system (Ober Reference Ober1989) and the Roman tribunes of the plebs; and they deepen the concerns of neorepublican theorists (Pettit Reference Pettit2012) and critical realists (Bagg Reference Bagg2018; Rahman Reference Rahman2016) about responding to concentrated elite power by restoring more meaningful democratic agency (Landemore Reference Landemore2020; Thomas Reference Thomas2016).

But the relationship between modern plebeian perspectives and prevailing liberal perspectives remains undeveloped. While some plebeian theorists take their position to be at odds with liberalism, this article shows that Mill brought liberalism together with a core plebeian insight: democratic politics fundamentally concerns the mobilization of social movements against oligarchic threats. Contemporary plebeian theorists have drawn inspiration from classical republicans like Machiavelli (McCormick Reference McCormick2011; Winter Reference Winter2012) and socialists like Rosa Luxemburg (Vergara Reference Vergara2020). But they have claimed the liberal tradition too rarely, if at all. This neglect deprives plebeians of important historical allies while making mainstream liberals suspicious of the idea that plebeian proposals can strengthen liberal commitments. Mill is an effective liaison between these different camps. He is a canonical liberal, but he drew widely on a large range of intellectual influences, among them utilitarianism, German romanticism, and Greek virtue ethics. Mill reminds contemporary liberals that plebeian commitments to confronting oligarchy through popular mobilization can also be central to their project, and he offers a concrete roadmap for political engagement around these very issues.

Critics argue that Mill’s disciplinary tendencies (Arneil Reference Arneil2012; Zerilli Reference Zerilli1994), overarching concern with stability and control (Hamburger Reference Hamburger2001), and complicity in imperial politics (Lederman Reference Lederman2021; Mehta Reference Mehta1999; Pitts Reference Pitts2005) render him, at best, an antiquated “aristocratic liberal” (Kahan Reference Kahan1992). But recent scholarship has challenged conventional understandings of Mill’s liberalism and expanded our understanding of his primary concerns, moving beyond On Liberty to a fuller appreciation of Mill’s vast intellectual corpus.Footnote 1 Scholars have rediscovered Mill’s contributions to debates about democratic representation (Thompson Reference Thompson1976; Urbinati Reference Urbinati2002), power relations (Baum Reference Baum2000), gender norms and political economy (Hirschmann Reference Hirschmann2008), multiculturalism (Marwah Reference Marwah2019), international relations (Varouxakis Reference Varouxakis2013), economic citizenship (Englert Reference Englert2016), institutional corruption (Selinger Reference Selinger2019b), and democratic socialism (Baum Reference Baum, Urbinati and Zakaras2007; McCabe Reference McCabe2021). This paper builds on these sympathetic accounts while moving beyond them by emphasizing Mill’s concrete interactions with working-class movements. It was Mill’s tactical innovation as an activist, pamphleteer, theoretician, and parliamentarian, I argue, that proved central to sustaining the cross-cutting energies that infused the liberal reform movement of his period.

Ultimately, I suggest that Mill’s liberal plebeianism offers a robust alternative to, and corrective of, prevailing liberal approaches; it thus deserves a prominent place in contemporary democratic theory and normative political thought. Critics complain that mainstream Rawlsian liberalism lacks a sociological sensibility—that it fixates excessively on abstract rights claims and norms of procedural fairness to the neglect of concrete struggles by actual, institutionally embodied political movements (Klein Reference Klein2022). These criticisms take hold amid wider debates about the role of ideal vs. nonideal (Mills Reference Mills2005) and realist vs. moralist (Rossi and Sleat Reference Rossi and Sleat2014) approaches in political theory. In this context, liberal plebeians can widen political horizons through an amplified focus on class-based coalition building, social-movement mobilization, and antioligarchic institutional reforms. Liberal plebeianism infuses liberalism with a more radical ethos and a more realistic appreciation of the workings of power (Hayward Reference Hayward2000), without abandoning the core procedural commitments that provide safeguards against illiberal populist forces (Cohen Reference Cohen2019; Urbinati Reference Urbinati2019).

Certainly, Mill’s efforts to mobilize the working class for reform were not wholly successful. But what Mill’s career does offer is an opportunity to see how movement coordination played out during an extended period, through the mind of a canonical political theorist, and within a nineteenth-century political context that bears significant similarities to our own. By tracing the evolution of Mill’s liberal-plebeian discourse over time, I seek to deepen appreciation of how democratic movements can respond to oligarchic threats today.

The Early Years: Sinister Interest and the Critique of Oligarchy

“It was said without exaggeration before the Reform Bill, it may be repeated with very little exaggeration even yet, that the English Government is an oligarchy of landholders” (Mill Reference Mill and Robson1982a, 470). So Mill proclaimed in 1839. Mill’s antioligarchic discourse, I argue, provided a normative foundation for his subsequent mobilization discourse, his attempt to find common ground between liberal reformers and an increasingly emboldened working class. In this section, I explore the early foundations of both discourses as they emerged in the critique of sinister interest that animated Mill’s youth.

In a seminal comparative historical study, Jeffrey Winters suggests that modern oligarchs have acclimated to democratic norms, including universal suffrage, often retreating from formal rule while finding new ways to pursue their objectives within the confines of democratic constitutions (Winters Reference Winters2011) through various forms of state capture (Bagg Reference Bagg2018; Lindsey and Teles Reference Lindsey and Teles2017).

However, Mill’s antioligarchic discourse arose in a period when oligarchic elites might still have reclaimed formal power. Guiding this discourse was the concept of sinister interest, which Mill inherited from Jeremy Bentham, James Mill, and other radicals (Schofield Reference Schofield2006). Sinister interests are a subset of particular interests, those “detrimental to the greatest happiness, of the greatest number” by which “a man is prompted to sacrifice to it that all-comprehensive interest” (Bentham Reference Bentham and Schofield1989, 151).

What most concerned Bentham were instances where socioeconomic privileges were deployed to amplify the private benefits of pursuing selfish behavior. He famously associated this pathology with a judicial system in which the sinister interests of aristocratic elites were served by lawyers and judges who retained their own sinister interests. We might deploy the phrase sinister interest, then, in reference to repeated, institutionally mediated behavior on the part of elites from various stations who are incentivized to act in self-regarding ways that are injurious to the collective good. This behavior can feed off past activities in a constant cycle where the fulfillment of one sinister interest provides new opportunities for the fulfillment of others.

Mill clearly internalized this insight. He lauded Bentham for exposing sinister interest “through all its disguises” (Mill Reference Mill and Robson1985a, 109), agreeing that “of the evils incident to monarchical and aristocratic governments, a large proportion arise from this cause” (Mill Reference Mill and Robson1977c, 441). Mill saw sinister interests on full display among wealthy factions who conspired with the ruling ministry to defeat taxes on the affluent, thwart trade unions, moralistically regulate workers’ access to beer houses, and preserve the privileges of church elites (Mill Reference Mill and Robson1982d, 162 and 205–14).

Meanwhile, landowners commanded archaic rural magistracies (Mill Reference Mill and Robson1982a, 471). And commons were enclosed with no regard for the aesthetic life of the poor, even as public expenditures went toward extravagant Correggio paintings favored by wealthy connoisseurs (Mill Reference Mill and Robson1982d, 249). Oxford and Cambridge were bastions of aristocratic youth who feasted on constant nepotism (250, 259). The military had become so nepotistic that it functioned as an “engine for extracting large annual sums from the people under false pretenses, to give to the sons of the rich” (Mill Reference Mill and Robson1982c, 316). Common soldiers endured the brutish treatment “inherent in an army or a navy exclusively officered by gentlemen” (Mill Reference Mill and Robson1982d, 268–70). When the wealthy misbehaved, police imposed trivial fines, while the poor were imprisoned “on some trifling accusation” (Mill Reference Mill and Robson1982a, 483). In a commentary titled “The Rich and the Poor,” Mill invoked the case of a magistrate from Devon, convicted of the most “brutal assaults” against his maidservant, but given only a minor penalty: as Mill put it, “who ever heard of a magistrate dismissed for oppressing the poor” (Mill Reference Mill and Robson1982d, 267).

Confronting a “selfish oligarchy” (Mill Reference Mill and Robson1982a, 479), Mill and his political circle, the self-styled Philosophical Radicals, saw their struggles against British landowners as mirroring ancient Greek struggles between democratic and oligarchic factions. Mill drew inspiration from reform-minded classicist George Grote, who defended Athens against the pro-Spartan biases of Tory classicists (Mill Reference Mill and Robson1978a; Reference Mill and Robson1978b). Although slavery inhibited Athens from realizing democracy in its “purest and most honourable” form (Mill Reference Mill and Robson1978b, 324), Mill celebrated Athens as a regime that, unlike the “aristocratic Roman republic,” granted poorer citizens equal access to office (324). Ordinary Athenians were exemplary in their respect for legal forms, Mill thought, whereas Greek oligarchs constantly violated those norms and acted viciously (326–8).

Commenting on French affairs during the tumultuous July Revolution, Mill worried the French would exchange a “feeble despotism for a strong and durable oligarchy” (Mill Reference Mill, Robson and Robson1986a, 130; see also Mill Reference Mill, Robson and Robson1986b). When excluded from power, the moneyed interests held common cause with the people. Now, “being a narrow Oligarchy,” they indulged the same selfish pursuits of any oligarchy wherein “32 millions are governed by the 88 thousand richest” (132–3). In commentaries like Civilization (Mill Reference Mill and Robson1977a) and The Spirit of the Age (Mill Reference Mill and Robson1986c), Mill lamented the tendency of the wealthy to live complacently and to peddle an “idolatry of certain abstractions, called church, constitution, agriculture” (Mill Reference Mill and Robson1986c, 315). Among Mill’s chief targets was the protectionist “Corn Law interest,” that “master-evil” (Mill Reference Mill and Robson1982a, 470–6 at 476).

Mill, like Bentham, understood that sinister interests have a cascading quality: they proliferate throughout the social order, as one sinister interest produces incentives that support the pursuit of another sinister interest. The evidence surveyed above suggests that Mill understood the basic contours of this cascading process. But in what follows, I argue that the key to understanding Mill’s contribution as a liberal plebeian lies in his mobilization discourse, which intersected with his critique of oligarchy and allowed him to move beyond Bentham. I now explore the early foundations of this mobilization discourse.

Mobilizing the Working Class

Nadia Urbinati’s groundbreaking book Mill on Democracy boldly highlights Mill’s neo-Athenian contributions to the “making of the modern democratic vision” (Urbinati Reference Urbinati2002, 5). Whereas French liberals, haunted by republican excesses, contrasted “ancient” and “modern” liberty, Mill affirmed an agonistic agora politics instantiated through mechanisms, such as newspapers, that facilitated a robust public sphere. Here Mill saw the Socratic ethos thriving, despite modern threats of bureaucratic stagnation and collective mediocrity (Urbinati Reference Urbinati2002).

Urbinati is certainly correct that the ancients are critical to understanding Mill’s worldview. Yet along with positive lessons about the value of popular government, Athenian history also taught Mill more sobering lessons about oligarchic threats to democracy. Urbinati never explores this point fully, so she overlooks how Mill’s antioligarchic worldview guided his real-world engagement with working-class movements. Mill’s democratic theory was thus even more dynamic than Urbinati argues. It was not simply about fostering a deliberative ethos and reconciling the agora to modernity; it was also about strategically mobilizing the population against oligarchy.

Mill’s fixation on mobilization reflected disappointment with his principal movement allies, middle-class radicals who had failed to properly grasp the epochal significance of working-class ascendancy. In “Reorganization of the Reform Party” (1839) and other strategic essays published in outlets like the London and Westminster Review, Mill speculated on the liberal reform movement’s future (Mill Reference Mill and Robson1982a, 467–95). In “Parties and the Ministry” (1837), one of these crucial but neglected essays, Mill employed the plebeian language of “tribunes of the poor.” I argue that Mill’s strategy for working-class mobilization was predicated on this plebeian imagery of the liberal reformer as tribune: an ally of workers and an intermediary, one capable of liaising with sympathetic elites and fusing together a cross-class coalition.

Mill was certainly aware of the crucial role that tribunes of the plebs played in Ancient Rome. From an early age, when he was exposed to authors like Livy, Mill was “engrossed” by the “struggles between the patricians and plebeians” (Mill Reference Mill, Robson and Stillinger1981, 17). Engagement with Henri de Saint-Simon and Auguste Comte encouraged Mill to think of society as an interrelated whole in which class divisions and relations form a crucial part (Mill Reference Mill and Robson1974, 912). Mill’s class analysis was thus guided by a stark contrast between two orders, which he called the “Privileged” and “Disqualified” classes. The former included large landowners and the richest commercial men. It also included privileged members of the army, clergy, and West India trading community (Mill Reference Mill and Robson1982a, 470–5). The disqualified, by contrast, encompassed the middle classes enfranchised in the 1832 Reform Act, small manufacturing interests outside of the protected trades, dissenters of various sorts, educated men lacking commensurate social prestige, and the vast working-class assemblage (475–8). By 1839, Mill was envisioning a broad “phalanx” spanning from more cautious “Whig Radicals” to “Ultra-Radicals and the working classes” (467). He instructed each side to ensure that their “separate interests, however legitimate,” did not undermine cooperation (478).

But throughout the 1830s, Mill’s aspirations for coalition building failed to materialize, and he blamed reform leaders in Parliament. Workers were mobilizing around Chartism, with its ominous slogan “peacefully if we can, forcibly if we must.”Footnote 2 In his 1837 essay, Mill implored the Radicals to hear out workers’ grievances: “No other political duty is so important” (Mill Reference Mill and Robson1982b, 396). Yet the Radicals were failing to seize their mantle as champions of the poor:

Hence it is that the poor do not love them, do not rally round them. They must be tribunes of the poor, and to some purpose too, if they mean to be anything. Those who will not flatter the people must make it doubly obvious that they are willing to serve them. (Mill Reference Mill and Robson1982b, 396)

To reiterate, Mill’s use of the plebeian language of “tribunes” is striking, especially given the importance afforded to Roman tribunes of the plebs in recent plebeian thought (McCormick Reference McCormick2011, 178–88). It came in the context of an acute political dilemma. A premature push for universal suffrage would endanger essential middle-class support (Mill Reference Mill and Robson1982a, 482). Yet workers had to be treated fairly “if Universal Suffrage is ever to come without a civil war” (483). Thus the motto “Government by means of the middle for the working classes” (483). For “the men of thews and sinews will never give their confidence to a party recommended only by willingness to take from the aristocracy and give to the shopocracy” (482).

While self-identifying with the “middle rank” James Mill had praised, John Stuart Mill proved far more alert than his father did to the threat of a hegemonic middle—the tyranny of opinion described in On Liberty. He thus believed that workers could usefully check the hegemonic pretensions of the middle rank, and the middle rank, for its part, could check the workers’ numerical superiority: “We wish [the workers] to be strong enough to keep the middle classes in that salutary awe, without which, no doubt, those classes would be just like any other oligarchy” (Mill Reference Mill and Robson1982a, 489). Mill’s delicate class analysis rested on the prospect of successful working-class incorporation.

Thus, Mill endorsed a twofold liberal reform strategy: appeasing middle-class moderates by moving gradually on universal suffrage while aggressively incorporating workers into the informal public sphere. To convince fellow reformers that working men could submit to the conventions of British politics, he argued that an educated stratum of workers was already participating in the public sphere: “The working classes themselves contain a middle as well as a lowest class,” Mill stressed. While repudiating the “Operative Radicals,” men confined to a “narrow district in the North” (Mill Reference Mill and Robson1982a, 485), Mill praised the Working Men’s Association in London, which “framed the People’s Charter” and continued to advocate for it in the press, as the “best and most enlightened aspect of working-class Radicalism” (485–6).

Mill believed enlightened labor leaders harbored conventional political ambitions. For “hardly any drunken or profligate working man is a politician. Such men do not read newspapers, or interest themselves in public measures; they take part in strikes, but not in Political Unions” (Mill Reference Mill and Robson1982a, 486). By 1839, despite his continued gradualism on universal suffrage, Mill believed that a portion of the “respectable” working class should be enfranchised as a counterweight to the new cohort of middle-class electors (489). He supported parliamentary bids by moderate Chartist leaders like William Lovett so that the “legislature should not have to learn the sentiments of the working-classes at second-hand” (489).

Workers, Mill saw, had reached an “organization and concert,” a degree of tactical awareness, “not yet reached by any other class of Reformers” (Mill Reference Mill and Robson1982a, 478). Mill recognized that without suffrage, some workers would continue to perceive Britain as a “mere oligarchy” (481). Mill hoped the “intelligent working classes” could be persuaded to accept gradualism on universal suffrage (488). Mill recognized that Britain had entered a “political age” in which the “desire of political rights, or the abuse of political privileges by the possessors of them, are the foremost ideas in the minds of most reading men” (Mill Reference Mill and Robson1967a, 383).

Of course, as first evidenced by his support for the 1834 Poor Law Amendment Act, Mill could display a critical attitude toward working-class behavior that he felt inhibited progress.Footnote 3 However, to read Mill solely as an elite disciplinarian intent on controlling working-class bodies (Zerilli Reference Zerilli1994) is to overlook Mill’s essential belief that workers deserved respect and agency. In “The Probable Futurity of the Labouring Classes,” a crucial section of his Political Economy, Mill criticized the ideology of dependence that demanded dutiful quietism from workers, suggesting that few workers would tolerate it (Mill Reference Mill and Robson1965b, 758–96).Footnote 4 The failure of paternalist approaches was settled the moment workers began to access newspapers and railroads, agitate for suffrage, and so on: “The working classes have taken their interests into their own hands” (762). Mill drew an analogy between socioeconomic and gender claims: “The same reasons which make it no longer necessary that the poor should depend on the rich, make it equally unnecessary that women should depend on men” (765). The section ends with some of Mill’s earliest reflections on worker cooperatives.

Mill recognized, however, that if workers remained dissatisfied, further agitation would ensue. The French insurrection of June 1848, its violent suppression, and the ascension of Louis Napoleon vividly underscored this threat (Mill Reference Mill and Robson1985b). But Britain possessed parliamentary traditions and a stable, if evolving, constitution. An incomplete but workable foundation for incorporating the working class into that constitution had been laid in 1832. This unfinished business guided Mill into the mature period of his intellectual life.

The Maturation of Mill’s Liberal Plebeianism

According to one conventional narrative, an intellectual awakening drove Mill away from the orthodox Benthamism of his youth and toward the more elitist views that guided canonical works like On Liberty and Considerations on Representative Government. As Dennis Thompson (Reference Thompson1976) argues, for example, Mill’s commitment to balancing “competence” and “participation” was not an aristocratic position but reflected Mill’s deep partisanship for representative democracy: an expanded working-class suffrage would be counterbalanced by measures, such as the Hare system of proportional representation, that preserved competence and protected distinguished minorities. What emerges on this and other “class balancing” accounts is a robust, but still elitist, democratic theory, chastened of the radical impulses of Mill’s earlier years.

In this section, I argue against interpretations that would view Mill’s radicalism as simply youthful exuberance. Mill’s mature period, I argue, was the culmination of his liberal-plebeian commitments: his critique of oligarchic sinister interest and his discourse of working-class mobilization culminated in Mill’s engagement as a Member of Parliament.

Clearly, Mill was sympathetic to an epistemic account of class balancing in which every major socioeconomic group has a voice, but no group dominates political life. Both Considerations and On Liberty offer compelling arguments for viewpoint balance. But while appreciating class balancing as an epistemic ideal, Mill never abandoned his earlier position that nonideal British politics required a tactical alliance with the working class. My argument here thus reveals important continuities between Mill’s earlier and later periods.

The young Mill was deeply class partisan. His complaints about oppressive magistrates, game laws, and so on emphasized the role of factionalist bias in social and political life: “Who is for the aristocracy and who for the people,” he wrote, “will be the plain question” during a “short and sharp” confrontation between the “two principles that divide the world” (Mill Reference Mill and Robson1982e, 300). Mill identified antiunion efforts, including policies inhibiting workers from forming cooperatives, as quintessential examples of systemic class bias (Mill Reference Mill and Robson1982a, 487). A “government which abdicates its legitimate office of a mediator and peace-maker, and assumes that of an auxiliary on either side … precludes itself from being listened to as an impartial and unprejudiced friend” (Mill Reference Mill and Robson1982d, 207).

Years later, in On Liberty, Mill reiterated that “class interests” and “feelings of class superiority” (Mill Reference Mill and Robson1977b, 221) guide the moral climate in pernicious ways. Mill’s critique of the despotism of custom and the dangers of majority opinion would certainly apply to a working class that could eventually become hegemonic. But On Liberty identifies the middle class as the greater immediate threat to impose its mores (286), and it criticizes disciplinary measures, such as restrictions on access to spirit houses, as inconsistent with the governance of a free laboring class (Mill Reference Mill and Robson1977b, 298–9).

Mill’s preoccupation with oppressive local magistrates, unfair tax policy, antiunion efforts, and obstacles to worker cooperatives, all highlight his long-standing view that real-world governments are not neutral arbiters of “class balance,” a view he pursued aggressively during his time in Parliament. During a campaign speech from 1865, Mill invoked his 1839 argument for worker cooperatives to highlight consistency on the issue (Mill Reference Mill, Robson and Kinzer1988b, 29). Because workers are distinctly disadvantaged, they require special redress, he insisted in a parliamentary address; “they require it more than any other class” (Mill Reference Mill, Robson and Kinzer1988d, 65) as the “chief sufferers” in need of advocacy (67).

Mill’s commentary on the American Civil War provides arguably his fiercest critique of elites. Mill drew heavily on political economist J. E. Cairnes, whose work The Slave Power depicted a plantation society embodying, in a phrase Mill quoted from Cairnes, “the distinctive vices of an oligarchy” (Mill Reference Mill and Robson1984a, 151).Footnote 5 It was this “white oligarchy of the South,” Mill insisted, that was propagating slavery as the “proper condition of the working classes everywhere” (Mill Reference Mill and Robson1984b, 135–6). With remarkable candor, he assailed England’s elites for sympathizing with Southern slaveholders. Mill certainly recognized that slavery was horrific in ways not generalizable to other forms of oligarchic corruption. Nonetheless, he saw the English aristocracy’s pro-Confederate sentiment as symptomatic of sinister interest more generally, of privilege inhibiting serious reflection on “what a dreadful thing slavery really is” (Mill Reference Mill, Robson and Kinzer1988b, 32–3 at 32). This “fanaticism of a class for its class privileges” provoked Mill’s “strongest feelings” (Mill Reference Mill, Robson and Stillinger1981, 266). He decried the “furious pro-Southern partisanship” expressed even by some English liberals. Workers were among “the sole exceptions” to this prevailing sentiment (267), and Mill applauded their moral clarity on the issue.

These events deeply shaped Mill’s outlook. With higher classes allied with Southern slaveholders, abstract ideals of class balance and viewpoint diversity were insufficient. The superior judgment of the working class on this issue deserved partisan political support, whereas the aristocracy’s pro-slaveholder sentiment reinforced “how far men could be carried away by their bias”: it was class bias, even when “unconscious and unintentional,” that “made the rich sympathize with the rich” (Mill Reference Mill, Robson and Kinzer1988b, 33). In a letter to Ralph Waldo Emerson, Mill drew analogies between Britain and America. In both societies, “all the fundamental problems of politics and society, so long smothered by general indolence and apathy, surge up and demand better solutions” (Mill Reference Mill, Mineka and Lindley1972c, 1307). Practically, the episode reminded Mill why rich MPs could never fully represent the interests of workers; he increasingly saw recruitment of working-class MPs as urgent.

Importantly, the terms oligarchy and plutocracy remained prominent in Mill’s later vocabulary; in 1859 he referred to oligarchy as that “monster evil” (Mill Reference Mill and Robson1977d, 333).Footnote 6 Such concerns were not simply derivative of Bentham but central to Mill’s own mature intellectual system. For example, Mill’s analysis of oligarchic tendencies in large manufacturing interests went well beyond Bentham. In an interview, Mill wrote that the “advantages which the possession of large capital gives … are growing greater and greater” as business “conducted on a large scale” facilitated a “great monopoly in the hands of the rich” (Mill Reference Mill and Robson1967c, 410; see also Mill Reference Mill and Robson1965a).

Mill’s critique of oligarchy increasingly led him to discuss excessive campaign spending. In “Thoughts on Parliamentary Reform” (1859), a precursor to Considerations, Mill analogized election spending with formal property requirements: “Morally, it is still worse … by the corrupting effect of the notion inculcated on the voter, that the person he votes for should pay a large sum of money” (Mill Reference Mill and Robson1977d, 320). Later, in 1864, Mill lamented the “number of persons that are constantly becoming wealthy, whose sole ambition is to obtain what wealth alone has not yet given them, namely, position” (Mill Reference Mill, Robson and Kinzer1988c, 10). The dangers of “what may be called plutocracy” could amplify preexisting challenges to strong democracy, Mill warned (10).

Mill continued to deploy the Benthamite language of sinister interest. In Considerations, for example, he discussed the “sinister interests” of power holders (Mill Reference Mill and Robson1977c, 442). Still influenced by Grote, with whom he maintained a lifelong correspondence, Mill invoked a sobering lesson from antiquity: political degeneration, “the incessant and ever-flowing current of human affairs towards the worse” (388) was always possible. Moving beyond Bentham, however, Mill argued that majoritarian democratic factions could also display sinister interests if left unchecked (442). This argument lends some support to the claim that Mill became more elitist over time. But it also raises questions about how sinister interests function in nonideal circumstances: Even if the working classes are capable of indulging sinister interests, political conditions may be such that the sinister interests of the upper classes are still more dangerous to democracy and more prone to abuse, as the Southern slaveholder example underscores. Even if class balancing was Mill’s normative ideal, he was operating in a decidedly unbalanced environment that still structurally favored elites; achieving long-term reform required immediate partisan efforts on behalf of workers and against the sinister interests of elites.

The Hare Plan: Toward the “Just Ascendency of Majorities”

This point provides the proper perspective for understanding Mill’s arguments for the Hare system of proportional representation and plural voting.Footnote 7 In Considerations, Mill advances his most sustained defense of elite epistemic competence. But Mill’s more radical impulses still surface here. Mill insisted that the Hare system would actually empower enfranchised workers in the near term because workers, although a majority of the population, currently constituted a minority of most constituencies (Mill Reference Mill, Robson and Kinzer1988g, 185). Of course, under universal suffrage, Hare would serve as a counterweight against working-class majorities. Yet even under Hare, “a minority would not be equivalent to a majority; a third of the electors could not outvote two-thirds” (183). Hare was thus a vehicle for the “just ascendency of majorities” (Mill Reference Mill, Robson and Kinzer1988h, 208). Mill praised working-class allies for being open minded about it (Mill Reference Mill, Mineka and Lindley1972d, 998).

Likewise, Mill’s enthusiasm for plural voting wavered when he came to realize it could be co-opted by conservatives. Plural-voting schemes were inadmissible under conditions of limited suffrage because they would simply create “an oligarchy within an oligarchy” (Mill Reference Mill and Robson1977d, 325). Increasingly, however, these nuances were lost; plural voting became associated with favoring property owners, which undermined its strategic value for reformers (Mill Reference Mill, Mineka and Lindley1972d, 998).

Mill’s willingness to deny the suffrage to illiterate citizens, nontaxpayers, and those on parish relief underscores that his epistemic defense of working-class participation had limits.Footnote 8 Yet Mill was acutely aware that in representative bodies “the minority must of course be overruled” (Mill Reference Mill and Robson1977c, 449). Even in a well-constituted democracy, the numerical majority would retain “absolute power, if they chose to exercise it” (467). The most necessary restraint would thus be the “good sense, moderation, and forbearance” of the majority itself (467). More broadly, Mill bristled at using the ideal of epistemic competence to justify a cloistered elite detached from everyday reality: “An intellectual aristocracy of lumières while the rest of the world remains in darkness fulfils none of my aspirations” (Mill Reference Mill, Mineka and Lindley1972b, 631).

Socioeconomic groups, Mill argued, are only secure when members can advocate for their interests (Mill Reference Mill and Robson1977c, 404), as otherwise these interests are neglected:

[Does Parliament] ever for an instant look at any question with the eyes of a working man? When a subject arises in which the labourers as such have an interest, is it regarded from any point of view but that of the employers of labour? I do not say that the working men’s view of these questions is in general nearer to truth than the other: but it is sometimes quite as near; and in any case it ought to be respectfully listened to. (Mill Reference Mill and Robson1977c, 405)

Suffrage has its own educative effects in broadening working-class horizons, and these epistemic improvements, Mill thought, would allow laborers to better advocate for their interests in formal venues.Footnote 9

Mill’s political interventions certainly reflected his belief that popular movements benefit from guidance. Mill self-identified as an educated elite, and he saw a functional role for such elites in democracy. But he never endorsed the epistocracy defended in our day by elitists, such as Jason Brennan (Reference Brennan2016), who direct their epistemic claims against democracy itself. Brennan insists that the “rule of the rich” can be a desirable outcome insofar as rich people have superior knowledge about politics. Mill would resist such simplistic justifications for epistocracy. His activism was firmly democratic and informed by his view that the upper classes forfeited epistemic respect when taking positions in accordance with their sinister interests, as with their support for Southern slaveholders. Conversely, working-class individuals deserved epistemic respect for their distinctive life experiences, especially on issues, like trade unionization, where their interests were most at stake.Footnote 10

In summary, far from departing from his earlier concerns with working-class incorporation, Mill’s mature theoretical works placed those issues front and center, even as he went beyond Bentham in developing a more nuanced and elitist position on the role of expertise in democracy. Yet the political landscape in Britain had changed considerably since the 1830s, with the continued decline of the old aristocracy and the rise of a commercial class that was beginning to harbor its own political ambitions. Against this backdrop, Mill pursued his brief but memorable career as a “moralist in and out of Parliament” (Kinzer, Robson, and Robson Reference Kinzer, Robson and Robson1992), an MP in William Gladstone’s liberal coalition. This episode, I argue, proved the culmination of Mill’s liberal-plebeian discourse and his effort to serve workers as a “tribune of the poor.”

Tribune of the Poor: Mill’s Working-Class Constituency

In his autobiography, Mill identified activism on working-class issues as a highlight of his parliamentary career (Mill Reference Mill, Robson and Stillinger1981, 277–8), alongside advocacy for women’s rights. In this section, I suggest that Mill’s liberal-plebeian discourses—oligarchic harm and working-class mobilization—reached their apex on the real terrain of parliamentary battle. Mill believed that reform politics demanded the protection of working-class interests through their representation by a tribune within the liberal reform movement. Mill thus undertook a parliamentary career to actualize the reform priorities he had maintained since the 1830s. It culminated with Mill’s dramatic intervention in a series of working-class suffrage protests.

Mill’s “attention to the interplay between freedom and power in the economic sphere,” as Bruce Baum argues, was “one of the most distinctive features of his liberalism” (Baum Reference Baum2000, 199). Mill believed that the passive or “quiescent” power of social groups must translate into “active” power through opinion formation and other collective activities (73–4). Baum’s innovative reading clarifies why power was so central to Mill’s theoretical agenda. Yet Baum overlooks just how personally invested Mill was in bringing about power mobilization. Baum criticizes Mill for underestimating “the degree to which achieving such change requires social and political struggle to overcome vested interests” (18). Mill, he says, was “better at outlining what a free society would look like than at offering us practical guidance on how to achieve it” (276). My argument challenges such claims.

Consider Mill’s tendency to reference his writings from the 1830s in engagements with working-class parliamentary constituents. When discussing the suffrage question at a constituent meeting, Mill appealed back to the period when reformers delayed immediate enfranchisement in exchange for attention to the “practical grievances” of workers, invoking his “Reorganization of the Reform Party” essay from 1839. It was in the 1830s that Mill first implored liberals to function as “tribunes of the poor.” It seems significant, then, that Mill directed working-class constituents to his early radical years to underscore continuity in his views and to stress that his support for worker cooperatives stretched back to the 1830s (Mill Reference Mill, Robson and Kinzer1988b, 29). Mill wanted workers to know that should he gain parliamentary power, he would put theory into practice and function as their parliamentary tribune.

During Mill’s electoral campaigns, his critique of sinister interest remained potent: In electoral speeches, he railed against a broken campaign finance system.Footnote 11 Without drastic reform, he said, Britain’s political system would morph into an oligarchic “Venetian Constitution, and that in a very bad form” (Mill Reference Mill, Robson and Kinzer1988c, 10). Mill watched as W. H. Smith, Jr., a wealthy Tory, spent massive resources on political ambitions, and he decried those seeking the political power that “wealth alone has not yet given them” (10).Footnote 12

Both while campaigning and after assuming office, Mill met frequently with disenfranchised workers to press his critique of “plutocracy.” He affirmed workers’ epistemic authority, which encompassed both axioms of “common sense and common observation” and more specialized knowledge on subjects like trade unionization (Mill Reference Mill, Robson and Kinzer1988d, 65). Privileged classes could rarely comprehend “what a working man has in his mind,” Mill argued, “because they do not know what is in his mind” (65). Let reasonableness prevail, and if workers “do not obtain what they desire, they will as readily acquiesce in defeat, or trust to the mere progress of reason for reversing the verdict, as any other portion of the community” (66).

Perhaps the most dramatic example of Mill’s operating as a “tribune” was his intervention in a notable working-class suffrage protest during the summer of 1866. This episode shows Mill attending to working-class grievances while still affirming the value of prevailing British political conventions. The Hyde Park protest came as William Gladstone’s reform effort, which would have enfranchised a subsection of the elite working class, stalled in June 1866, facing continued conservative opposition. In this tense climate, the Reform League, a prominent post-Chartist organization, announced intentions to stage a mass public meeting. On the evening of July 23, Reform Leaguers arrived at the park and were confronted with locked gates and a police barricade. Some protesters broke the barricades and descended on the park. Mill later recalled a scuffle in which “many innocent persons were maltreated by the police” (Mill Reference Mill, Robson and Stillinger1981, 278). In parliamentary discussion on July 24, he criticized the Home Secretary’s crackdown (1988e, 99–100).

Claiming the right of free assembly, the league was set to defy a restraining order. As Mill recalled, the protesters “shewed a determination to make another attempt at the meeting in the Park, to which many of them would probably have come armed” (Mill Reference Mill, Robson and Stillinger1981, 278). Disturbed, Mill attended, with several other radical MPs, a council of leading Reform Leaguers and working-class leadership, and the “task fell chiefly upon myself of persuading them to give up the Hyde Park project, and hold their meeting elsewhere” (278). Mill persuaded them to move the protest to a nearby agricultural hall. For a violent stand in Hyde Park was only justified “if the position of affairs had become such that a revolution was desirable, and if they thought themselves able to accomplish one. To this argument after considerable discussion they at last yielded” (278).

With the group reconvening at the agricultural hall on July 30, Mill accepted an invitation to address the Reform League.

Ladies and Gentlemen, this vast meeting is a sufficient guarantee that the cause of reform will suffer nothing by your having determined to hold your meeting here instead of repeating the attempt to hold it in the park… . You have been very much attacked for holding such large meetings, on the ground that they are inconsistent with discussion. But discussion is not the only use of public meetings. One of the objects of such gatherings is demonstration… . You want to make a display of your strength, and I tell you that the countries where the people are allowed to show their strength are those in which they are not obliged to use it. (Mill Reference Mill, Robson and Kinzer1988e, 103–4)Footnote 13

This episode figured prominently in Mill’s autobiography. “No other person,” Mill insisted, “had at that moment the necessary influence for restraining the working classes,” except for Prime Minister Gladstone and the radical MP John Bright, both of whom were unavailable (Mill Reference Mill, Robson and Stillinger1981, 279). This remarkable autobiographical citation highlights Mill’s confidence in his own ability to mediate with workers at a critical juncture, which underscored his belief that structural circumstances did not justify revolution. He subsequently spoke out against, and orchestrated the defeat of, a Tory bill to prevent public meetings in the parks (279).

It was in a similar spirit that, seven months after the Hyde Park episode, Mill responded to accounts of an angry Reform League meeting at which a general strike was entertained. In a letter to William Randal Cremer, a key trade-union leader, Mill criticized the meeting’s “direct appeal to revolutionary expedients” and the readiness among some attendees to “proceed at once to a trial of physical force if any opposition is made” to their demands (Mill Reference Mill, Mineka and Lindley1972a, 1247–8). Mill emphasized again that Britain’s parliamentary system provided for the “redress of grievances to be sought by peaceable and legal means” (1248).

Mill continued to reinforce this message up through his reelection campaign in 1868. The Reform Act of 1867 had finally brought some measure of suffrage expansion. From Mill’s perspective, however, this reform only reinforced the urgency of cultivating relationships with workers. Having finally achieved its enactment, would the working classes “have as the fruits of that Reform Bill a Tory Administration” (Mill Reference Mill, Robson and Kinzer1988f, 336)?

Final Years: Increasing Radicalization

Yet Mill, like numerous other liberal candidates, lost in the election of 1868.Footnote 14 Mill largely blamed this electoral setback on the pathological role of money in elections, the “real cause” of the movement’s electoral misfortune (Reference Mill, Mineka and Lindley1972e, 1514–5). The defeat only expanded Mill’s commitment to movement building. He implored workers to make a “united and energetic appeal to Parl[iament] to clear away this obstacle to their representation” (1515). He reinforced his long-standing support for worker cooperatives in completing his Chapters on Socialism. Mill’s idiosyncratic position in the socialist tradition has attracted ongoing attention among scholars, who focus largely on the theoretical dimensions of his flirtation with socialist ideals and his criticism of specific socialist initiatives.Footnote 15 For my purposes, Chapters is notable less as a philosophical text than as a concrete culmination of Mill’s liberal-plebeian discourse.

Mill understood that suffrage acquisition was not sufficient to address the challenges facing workers (Ten Reference Ten and Skorupski1998, 387–8). As Baum (Reference Baum2000) argues, Mill’s vision of worker cooperatives stemmed directly from his focus on insulating workers from undue forms of dependence and paternalism. Yet cooperatives were not simply about protection but also about mobilization. In Chapters, Mill recognized that workers were maturing politically and would not act in the “disorderly and ineffective way” of those unfamiliar with the “legal and constitutional machinery” (Mill Reference Mill and Robson1967b, 707). Rather, their instruments would be “the press, public meetings and associations, and the return to Parliament of the greatest number of persons pledged to the political aims of the working classes” (707).

Mill’s preoccupation with worker cooperatives traced back to his early radicalism, when he criticized partnership laws that inhibited workers from forming cooperatives (Mill Reference Mill and Robson1982a, 487). Throughout his career, Mill viewed cooperatives as a crucial barometer, alongside suffrage expansion, for measuring working-class political inclusion. Cooperatives were distinctly democratic institutions: “labourers themselves on terms of equality, collectively owning the capital with which they carry on their operations, and working under managers elected and removable by themselves” (Mill Reference Mill and Robson1965b, 775). Efforts to inhibit their formation were thus symptomatic examples of the elite sinister interest Mill was determined to overcome.Footnote 16

Mill was skeptical of communism because he worried that selfish behavior would reemerge in communist societies (Mill Reference Mill and Robson1967b, 744). However, he believed that well-structured worker cooperatives could avoid these pathologies. Precisely because workers were becoming more politically powerful, it was essential for reformers to understand their emerging beliefs about economic reorganization (707). In the 1830s, Mill argued that worker cooperatives could have a profound “healing effect” in giving workers confidence in “fair play” (Mill Reference Mill and Robson1982a, 487), and he advanced a similar argument four decades later.

Socialism was a creed worthy of the most careful consideration at a time when workers had every right to demand reexamination of old customs. There was urgency in this appeal, as the “circumstances which have caused them, thus far, to make a very limited use of that power, are essentially temporary” (Mill Reference Mill and Robson1967b, 707). Note the striking parallel with Mill’s analysis in the 1830s, when he implored liberal reformers to address working-class grievances so as to stave off more destabilizing forms of revolutionary protest. Against those who argued that poverty is natural or “necessary,” Mill noted that similar arguments were made about “all the privileges of oligarchy” (710). This late usage of the term “oligarchy” again demonstrates the terminological consistency in Mill’s discourse. Ultimately, by the end of his life, Mill’s distinctive fusion of liberal reform and working-class mobilization had culminated in an advancing, though still unfinished, pursuit of democratic progress.

Conclusion: Mill and Liberal Plebeianism Today

John Stuart Mill’s legacy as a resource for contemporary political theory remains contested. I have argued that Mill’s work should be appreciated for its liberal plebeianism—for combining an antioligarchic discourse dedicated to combatting the “sinister interests” of entrenched elites with a discourse of mobilization intended to incorporate the British working classes into a liberal reform coalition.

By reading a canonical liberal through a plebeian frame, this paper has suggested that liberal and plebeian discourses can converge around a shared critique of oligarchy and a shared focus on mobilizing reform movements to strengthen democracy. Mill lived and wrote in a historical context where oligarchic threats proliferated and where mobilization was required to counteract them. He was committed to keeping reform movements within established norms of British politics. But as a “tribune” of the working-class, he adopted an aggressive antioligarchic posture. Standard class-balancing interpretations (i.e., Thompson Reference Thompson1976) overlook the full force of Mill’s advocacy on behalf of workers. Mill’s democratic theory sought to defend those most vulnerable to oppression, not simply to balance their interests with those of elites. He sought earnestly to be their tribune within a dynamic public sphere.

Mill’s liberal plebeianism shows the promise of a contemporary normative paradigm, not yet fully developed, that synthesizes different perspectives to find a productive balance between “plebeian” and “liberal” commitments. This synthesis requires both perspectives to acknowledge their mutual compatibility. Plebeians must acknowledge the critical resources that exist within the historical liberal tradition, including liberalism’s fierce criticism of legal inequalities, concentrated power, absolutism, antipluralism, and threats to individual liberty and property. Conversely, liberals must acknowledge the value of a plebeian attentiveness to class-based political distinctions and power imbalances. The proper balance between these different commitments cannot be determined a priori but must be struck in real-world political contexts. It takes democratic leaders, like Mill, to manage trade-offs within the constraints and opportunities afforded by a specific time and place (Beerbohm Reference Beerbohm2015).

Contemporary liberal plebeianism is thus fundamentally realist in orientation: It is concerned with forces like concentrated power and institutional corruption, which animated Mill’s engagement with his “nonideal” political environment. It harkens back to a period where political liberals were animated more by these practical political questions than by abstract debates in “ideal” theory (Sabl Reference Sabl2017; Sleat Reference Sleat2013; Waldron Reference Waldron2016). Contemporary liberal plebeians can probe this “lost history of liberalism” (Rosenblatt 2018) to highlight why and how the problems motivating earlier liberals are still relevant today. By responding to the messy balance of social forces that shapes their specific political context (Arlen and Rossi Reference Arlen and Rossi2021; Bagg Reference Bagg2018), liberal plebeians can distinguish their approach from the more abstract forms of analytic liberalism that emerged out of the Rawlsian revolution (Forrester Reference Forrester2019).

Building on Mill’s legacies, a contemporary liberal-plebeian orientation would involve, first, a diagnostic posture focused on mapping the terrain of oligarchic “sinister interests” as they manifest themselves in specific political orders, second, a mobilization posture in which this diagnosis aids in assembling different social classes around a reform agenda, and third, an institutionalization posture in which reform is pursued through formal institutions, like parliaments, that respect (at minimum) liberal procedural norms. Each of these phases is reflected in Mill’s own political career, from his early pamphleteering to his later involvement in parliamentary politics.

Consider how we might apply this orientation to a pressing contemporary issue. Global tax sheltering is arguably a paradigmatic example of oligarchic “sinister interest.” An estimated $7.2 trillion is sheltered abroad, through entities like shell companies, a problem vividly underscored by the Panama Papers and Pandora Papers scandals (Zucman Reference Zucman and Fagan2015). Political strategies that prove effective in confronting tax sheltering may prove less effective against other political challenges, such as the proliferation of “soft money” in the American campaign finance system (Lessig Reference Lessig2014; Skocpol and Hertel-Fernandez Reference Skocpol and Hertel-Fernandez2016). Nonetheless, a liberal-plebeian leader can diagnose the interlocking connections between different political challenges, showing how global tax sheltering might help special interests exert power domestically or vice versa. She might mobilize a political coalition around confronting these challenges while also working within formal institutions to enact progressive policy changes. Of course, tax sheltering raises important normative concerns that can be tackled from within existing Rawlsian liberal theories of justice, for example. However, liberal plebeians draw us further toward the real-world dynamics that perpetuate sheltering: not simply abstract problems of justice, fairness, and equality but concrete manifestations of entrenched oligarchic power.

The plebeian orientation thus works against the tendencies of some contemporary liberals to abstract away from the broader balance of social forces and to rely excessively on proceduralist crutches (Klein Reference Klein2022). Importantly, however, the liberal orientation recognizes the dangers of the populist tendency to stray too far from these same procedural norms. In contexts that are highly oligarchic, liberal plebeians can pursue democratic innovations, such as new forms of citizen assembly and oversight, that empower ordinary people to exert more formal political influence (Arlen Reference Arlen2022; McCormick Reference McCormick2011; Vergara Reference Vergara2020). Such reform proposals are weapons in the democratic arsenal. But unlike extreme populists, who see liberalism as an obstacle to progress, liberal plebeians still affirm the value of liberal parliamentarism as a framework through which to pursue progressive reforms.

There is a spectrum of different institutional possibilities from more to less aggressive, depending on how the liberal and plebeian commitments are balanced in any specific context. An effective liberal-plebeian leader can advocate institutional reforms that maximize the epistemic competence of the many (Landemore Reference Landemore2020) while pushing back against antipluralist forms of populism (Cohen Reference Cohen2019; Müller Reference Müller2016; Urbinati Reference Urbinati2019). Mill was a “parliamentary liberal” (Selinger Reference Selinger2019a) who nonetheless understood the distinctive political predicament of the working class as a force to be respected on its own terms, a force capable of participating in the reform and reshaping of institutions. Mill understood, better than many of his liberal allies, that working-class mobilization need not destabilize democracy. Mill’s mobilization model thus required educated elites and working-class activists to coordinate their epistemic capacities in a mutually reinforcing manner, drawing on the experience of both sides. In this spirit, contemporary liberal-plebeian leaders can facilitate the inclusion of voices that might not otherwise survive in formal channels of the political status quo while simultaneously attempting to convince progressively inclined fellow elites to ally with popular factions.

Ultimately, liberal plebeianism offers a unique and promising framework for confronting contemporary political challenges. Mill feared that oligarchic corruption would prevent ordinary working-class people from exercising political power. Those among us who share his concerns today should be no less vigilant.

ACKNOWLEdGMENTS

I am indebted to the APSR’s editors and anonymous reviewers for their highly constructive feedback. I am especially indebted to John McCormick and Enzo Rossi for their mentorship and unwavering support of this project. For comments on previous versions, I thank workshop participants at the University of Chicago, the University of Amsterdam, The International Society for Third-Sector Research Conference, and the APSA annual conference. I also thank Chiara Cordelli, Lea M. Klarenbeek, Steven Klein, William Levine, Patchen Markell, Natasha Piano, Jennifer Pitts, and Jason S. Canon. Alexander R. Cohen provided excellent assistance with editing and proofreading. I thank Rainer Forst, Beate Sutterlüty, Iris Koban, and the staff and fellows of the Forschungskolleg Humanwissenschaften of the Goethe University Frankfurt for creating an ideal research environment. Finally, I thank my current colleagues at Swarthmore College for their support and camaraderie.

FUNDING STATEMENT

The research for this piece was supported by the Dutch Research Council (NWO) Science Organization’s Vidi Project “Legitimacy beyond Consent” (grant n.016.164.351). The Justitia Center for Advanced Studies (Frankfurt) on behalf of the Alfons and Gertrud Kassel Foundation also provided funding.

CONFLICT OF INTEREST

The author declares no ethical issues or conflicts of interest in this research.

ETHICAL STANDARDS

The author affirms that this research did not involve human subjects.

Footnotes

1 On the tendency of some contemporary liberals to advance an overly simplistic reading of Mill, see Philips (Reference Philips2019).

2 For other literature on the Chartist movement and nineteenth-century class dynamics more generally, see the classic study by Thompson (Reference Thompson1966); see also Ashcraft (Reference Ashcraft1993).

3 On Mill’s Malthusianism as a disciplinary project see Zerilli (Reference Zerilli1994, 95–109). Arneil (Reference Arneil2012) sees a fundamental symmetry between Mill’s arguments for imperial rule abroad and his endorsement of a disciplinary approach to the idle poor in Britain. This posture is seen as consistent with a broader phenomenon of “domestic colonization” manifested through labor colonies and other disciplinary institutions. Lederman (Reference Lederman2021) likewise insists that Mill viewed the working class as fundamentally “barbaric” and had deep anxieties about popular politics. These readings are provocative in capturing some of Mill’s expressed concerns about working-class character and unregulated mass democracy. Nonetheless, they fail to acknowledge the full spectrum of Mill’s engagement with workers, which went far beyond the discipline, control, and dehumanization of workers or the denial of their political agency.

4 On Mill’s critique of paternalist philanthropy, see Saunders-Hastings (Reference Saunders-Hastings2014).

5 Mill is referencing J. S. Cairnes, The Slave Power, Its Character, Career, and Probable Designs, Being an Attempt to Explain the Real Issues Involved in the American Context (New York: Carlton, 1862).

6 Mill uses the term oligarchy here in reference to an earlier period in which the rich were “in complete possession of the Government (Mill Reference Mill and Robson1977d, 332–3). In such environments, the secret ballot is essential. Mill suggests that by 1859, electors are no longer “mere organs for putting power into the hands of a controlling oligarchy. The electors themselves are becoming the oligarch,” which renders public balloting essential as a constraint (333). These passages do lend some credence to the view that Mill was becoming more elitist and more concerned about unchecked power in the hands of the electorate. The passage is consistent with Mill’s evolving view that democratic majorities can also have sinister interests if left unchecked (Mill Reference Mill and Robson1977c, 442). However, importantly, Mill still expresses these concerns through the language of oligarchy, reinforcing the point that the concept of oligarchy was still central to his mature political vocabulary. Moreover, as the 1860s progressed, Mill increasingly worried about new forms of wealth-based oligarchy threatening democratic progress, as this article argues.

7 The system of proportional representation notably proposed by the reformer Thomas Hare (1806–1891) employed a single transferable vote. Under it, each voter would rank candidates, and once a candidate had enough votes to be elected, that candidate’s surplus votes would be transferred to other candidates.

8 As Englert (Reference Englert2016) notes, these exclusions suggest that Mill endorsed an idea of economic membership in which some forms of economic participation are prior to political participation in providing the basis for common life. However, in practice the exclusions created a dichotomy within the lower classes between those who were participating in economic life (as workers) and those who remained idle (Englert Reference Englert2016, 576). As Carlisle (Reference Carlisle and Eisenach1998) emphasizes, analysis of working-class “character” was indeed a central preoccupation in the Victorian period.

9 As Selinger (Reference Selinger2019a) argues, Mill was devoted to the theory and practice of British parliamentarism, and Considerations was his attempt to reconcile its normative commitments with a rising mass democracy, echoing a prevailing Victorian view that Parliament could function as the “mirror of the nation,” with diverse views represented in a deliberative body (Conti Reference Conti2019, 1).

10 Alongside his belief that participation is an intrinsic good in democratic societies, Mill thus saw instrumental value in participation as a tool to ward off oligarchic threats and pursue specific reform objectives.

11 As Selinger (Reference Selinger2019b) shows, Mill articulated a remarkably modern critique of campaign finance practices, going well beyond bribery to broader concerns about how private money could corrupt the practice of campaigning itself.

12 Some of the campaign and parliamentary speeches cited here represent journalistic transcriptions or reporting of Mill’s utterances. Insofar as they are presented as faithful representations of Mill’s speeches, and consistent with their inclusion in his collected works, I treat these speeches as Mill’s words.

13 The quote as presented here omits some textual notes from the Collected Works that describe audience reaction to Mill’s speech.

14 For an especially informative account of Mill’s parliamentary career and the reasons for his electoral defeat, see Kinzer, Robson, and Robson (Reference Kinzer, Robson and Robson1992).

15 As McCabe (Reference McCabe2021, 7) notes, “there is no consensus about Mill’s socialism,” and his writings on the subject are often seen as tangential and peripheral to his mature liberal project. However, McCabe (Reference McCabe2021) vigorously argues that Mill’s views on socialism are central, not peripheral, and that they began at a young age. Sarvasy (Reference Sarvasy1984, 586) argues that Mill’s socialist objectives are intricately related to his democratic theory, with the latter being a mechanism for facilitating socialist development; see also Baum (Reference Baum, Urbinati and Zakaras2007), Medearis (Reference Medearis2005), and Ten (Reference Ten and Skorupski1998).

16 Cooperatives were also central to Mill’s long-standing interest in harnessing productive as opposed to “idle” labor.

References

Applebaum, Anne. 2020. Twilight of Democracy: The Seductive Lure of Authoritarianism. New York: Doubleday.Google Scholar
Arlen, Gordon, and Rossi, Enzo. 2021. “Must Realists Be Pessimists about Democracy: Responding to Epistemic and Oligarchic Challenges.” Moral Philosophy and Politics 8 (1): 2749.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arlen, Gordon. 2022. “Citizen Tax Juries: Democratizing Tax Enforcement after the Panama Papers.” Political Theory 50 (2): 193220.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arlen, Gordon. 2019. “Aristotle and the Problem of Oligarchic Harm: Insights for Democracy.” European Journal of Political Theory 18 (3): 393414.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arneil, Barbara. 2012. “Liberal Colonialism, Domestic Colonies and Citizenship.” History of Political Thought 33 (3): 491523.Google Scholar
Ashcraft, Richard. 1993. “Liberal Political Theory and Working-Class Radicalism in Nineteenth-Century England.” Political Theory 21 (2): 249–72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bagg, Samuel. 2018. “The Power of the Multitude: Answering Epistemic Challenges to Democracy.” American Political Science Review 112 (4): 891904.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bartels, Larry. 2008. Unequal Democracy: The Political Economy of the New Gilded Age. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Baum, Bruce. 2000. Rereading Power and Freedom in J. S. Mill. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baum, Bruce. 2007. “J. S. Mill and Liberal Socialism.” In J. S. Mill’s Political Thought: A Bicentennial Reassessment, eds. Urbinati, Nadia and Zakaras, Alex, 98123. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beerbohm, Eric. 2015. “Is Democratic Leadership Possible?American Political Science Review 109 (4): 639–52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bentham, Jeremy. 1989. First Principles Preparatory to Constitutional Code, ed. Schofield, Philip. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Breaugh, Martin. 2013. The Plebeian Experience: A Discontinuous History of Political Freedom, trans. Lederhendler, Lazer. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Brennan, Jason. 2016. Against Democracy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Carlisle, Janice. 1998. “Mr. J. Stuart Mill, M.P., and the Character of the Working Classes.” In Mill and the Moral Character of Liberalism, ed. Eisenach, Eldon J., 143–68. University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press.Google Scholar
Cohen, Jean L. 2019. “What’s Wrong with the Normative Theory (and the Actual Practice) of Left Populism?Constellations 26 (3): 391407.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Conti, Gregory. 2019. Parliament the Mirror of the Nation: Representation, Deliberation, and Democracy in Victorian Britain. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Englert, Gianna. 2016. “Liberty and Industry: John Locke, John Stuart Mill, and the Economic Foundations of Political Membership.” Polity 48 (4): 551–79.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Forrester, Katrina. 2019. In the Shadow of Justice: Postwar Liberalism and the Remaking of Political Philosophy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Gilens, Martin. 2012. Affluence and Influence: Economic Inequality and Political Power in America . Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Green, Jeffrey. 2016. The Shadow of Unfairness: A Plebeian Theory of Liberal Democracy. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hamburger, Joseph. 2001. John Stuart Mill on Liberty and Control. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Hamilton, Lawrence. 2014. Freedom is Power: Liberty through Political Representation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hayward, Clarissa R. 2000. De-Facing Power. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hirschmann, Nancy J. 2008. “Mill, Political Economy, and Women’s Work.” American Political Science Review 102 (2): 199213.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kahan, Alan S. 1992. Aristocratic Liberalism: The Social and Political Thought of Jacob Burckhardt, John Stuart Mill, and Alexis de Tocqueville. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kalyvas, Andreas. 2019. “Democracy and the Poor: Prolegomena to a Radical Theory of Democracy.” Constellations 26 (4): 538–53.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kinzer, Bruce L., Robson, Ann P., and Robson, John. 1992. A Moralist In and Out of Parliament: John Stuart Mill at Westminister, 1865–1868. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.Google Scholar
Klein, Steven. 2022. “Democracy Requires Organized Collective Power.” Journal of Political Philosophy 30 (1): 2647.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Landemore, Hélène. 2020. Open Democracy: Reinventing Popular Rule for the Twenty-First Century. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Lederman, Shmuel. 2021. “Representative Democracy and Colonial Inspirations: The Case of John Stuart Mill.” American Political Science Review, 113. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0003055421001283.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lessig, Lawrence. 2014 . “ What an Originalist Would Understand ‘Corruption’ to Mean .” California Law Review 102 (1): 1 24.Google Scholar
Levitsky, Steven, and Ziblatt, Daniel. 2018. How Democracies Die. New York: Crown.Google Scholar
Lindsey, Brink, and Teles, Steven M.. 2017. The Captured Economy: How the Powerful Enrich Themselves, Slow Down Growth, and Increase Inequality. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Marwah, Inder S. 2019. Liberalism, Diversity and Domination: Kant, Mill and the Government of Difference. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCabe, Helen. 2021. John Stuart Mill: Socialist . Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCormick, John P. 2011. Machiavellian Democracy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Medearis, John. 2005. “Labor, Democracy, Utility, and Mill’s Critique of Private Property.” American Journal of Political Science 49 (1): 13549.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mehta, Uday S. 1999. Liberalism and Empire: A Study in Nineteenth Century British Liberal Thought. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mill, John S. 1963–91. The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, 33 vols, ed. Robson, John M.. Toronto: University of Toronto Press; London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. All citations to the Collected Works are to the scanned version provided by Liberty Fund. https://oll.libertyfund.org/title/robson-collected-works-of-john-stuart-mill-in-33-vols.Google Scholar
Mill, John S. 1965a. Principles of Political Economy, with Some of Their Applications to Social Philosophy, Books I–II , Vol. 2 of The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, ed. Robson, John M.. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.Google Scholar
Mill, John S. 1965b. Principles of Political Economy, with Some of Their Applications to Social Philosophy, Books III–IV and Appendices , Vol. 3 of The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, ed. Robson, John M.. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.Google Scholar
Mill, John S. 1967a. “The Claims of Labour.” In Essays on Economics and Society, bk. 1, Vol. 4 of The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, ed. Robson, John M., 363–89. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.Google Scholar
Mill, John S. 1967b. “Chapters on Socialism.” In Essays on Economics and Society, bk. 2, Vol. 5 of The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, ed. Robson, John M., 705–53. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.Google Scholar
Mill, John S. 1967c. “The Savings of the Middle and Working Classes.” In Essays on Economics and Society, bk. 2, Vol. 5 of The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, ed. Robson, John M., 405–29. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.Google Scholar
Mill, John S. 1972a. “Letter to William Randal Cremer.” In The Later Letters of John Stuart Mill, 1849–1873, Vol. 16 of The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, eds. Mineka, Francis E. and Lindley, Dwight N., 1247–48. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mill, John S. 1972b. “Letter to Alexander Bain.” In The Later Letters of John Stuart Mill, 1849–1873, Vol. 15 of The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, eds. Mineka, Francis E. and Lindley, Dwight N., 630–32. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mill, John S. 1972c. “Letter to Ralph Waldo Emerson.” In The Later Letters of John Stuart Mill, 1849–1873, Vol. 16 of The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, eds. Mineka, Francis E. and Lindley, Dwight N., 1306–07. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mill, John S. 1972d. “Letter to Max Kyllmann.” In The Later Letters of John Stuart Mill, 1849–1873, Vol. 16 of The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, eds. Mineka, Francis E. and Lindley, Dwight N., 997–99. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mill, John S. 1972e. “Letter to R. C. Madge.” In The Later Letters of John Stuart Mill, 1849–1873, Vol. 16 of The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, eds. Mineka, Francis E. and Lindley, Dwight N., 1513–15. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mill, John S. 1974. A System of Logic Ratiocinative and Inductive, Being a Connected View of the Principles of Evidence and the Methods of Scientific Investigation, Books IV–VI and Appendices, Vol. 8 of The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, ed. Robson, John M.. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.Google Scholar
Mill, John S. 1977a. “Civilization.” In Essays on Politics and Society, Vol. 18 of The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, ed. Robson, John M., 117–47. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.Google Scholar
Mill, John S. 1977b. “On Liberty.” In Essays on Politics and Society, Vol. 18 of The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, ed. Robson, John M., 213310. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.Google Scholar
Mill, John S. 1977c. “Considerations on Representative Government.” In Essays on Politics and Society, Vol. 19 of The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, ed. Robson, John M., 371577. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.Google Scholar
Mill, John S. 1977d. “Thoughts on Parliamentary Reform.” In Essays on Politics and Society, Vol. 19 of The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, ed. Robson, John M., 311–39. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.Google Scholar
Mill, John S. 1978a. “Grote’s History of Greece (I).” In Essays on Philosophy and the Classics, Vol. 11 of The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, ed. Robson, John M., 271305. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.Google Scholar
Mill, John S. 1978b. “Grote’s History of Greece (II).” In Essays on Philosophy and the Classics, Vol. 11 of The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, ed. Robson, John M., 307–37. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.Google Scholar
Mill, John S. 1981. “Autobiography.” In Autobiography and Literary Essays, Vol. 1 of The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, eds. Robson, John M. and Stillinger, Jack, 1290. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.Google Scholar
Mill, John S. 1982a. “Reorganization of the Reform Party.” In Essays on England, Ireland, and the Empire, Vol. 6 of The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, ed. Robson, John M., 465–96. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mill, John S. 1982b. “Parties and the Ministry.” In Essays on England, Ireland, and the Empire, Vol. 6 of The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, ed. Robson, John M., 381404. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mill, John S. 1982c. “Postscript: The Close of the Session.” In Essays on England, Ireland, and the Empire, Vol. 6 of The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, ed. Robson, John M., 309–17. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mill, John S. 1982d. “Notes on the Newspapers.” In Essays on England, Ireland, and the Empire, Vol. 6 of The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, ed. Robson, John M., 149280. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mill, John S. 1982e. “Parliamentary Proceedings of the Session.” In Essays on England, Ireland, and the Empire, Vol. 6 of The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, ed. Robson, John M., 295308. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mill, John S. 1984a. “The Slave Power.” In Essays on Equality, Law, and Education, Vol. 21 of The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, ed. Robson, John M., 143–64. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.Google Scholar
Mill, John S. 1984b. “The Contest in America.” In Essays on Equality, Law, and Education, Vol. 21 of The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, ed. Robson, John M., 125–42. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.Google Scholar
Mill, John S. 1985a. “Bentham.” In Essay on Ethics, Religion and Society, Vol. 10 of The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, ed. Robson, John M., 75116. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.Google Scholar
Mill, John S. 1985b. “Vindication of the French Revolution of February 1848.” In Essays on French History and Historians, Vol. 20 of The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, ed. Robson, John M., 317–63. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mill, John S. 1986a. “Prospects of France, I.” In Newspaper Writings Dec. 1822–July 1831, Vol. 22 of The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, eds. Robson, Ann P. and Robson, John M., 128–34. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mill, John S. 1986b. “French News (9).” In Newspaper Writings Dec. 1822–July 1831, Vol. 22 of The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, eds. Robson, Ann P. and Robson, John M., 224–27. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mill, John S. 1986c. “The Spirit of the Age (1–5).” In Newspaper Writings Dec. 1822–July 1831, Vol. 22 of The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, eds. Ann P. Robson and Robson, John M., 227–34, 238–45, 252–8, 278–82, 289–95, 304–7, 312–6. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mill, John S. 1988a. “The British Constitution (I).” In Journals and Debating Speeches, bk. 1, Vol. 26 of The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, ed. Robson, John M., 358–71. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mill, John S. 1988b. “The Westminster Election of 1865.” In Public and Parliamentary Speeches, Vol. 28 of The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, eds. Robson, John M. and Kinzer, Bruce L., 1344. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mill, John S. 1988c. “Corruption at Elections.” In Public and Parliamentary Speeches, Vol. 28 of The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, eds. Robson, John M. and Kinzer, Bruce L., 911. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mill, John S. 1988d. “Representation of the People (II).” In Public and Parliamentary Speeches, Vol. 28 of The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, eds. Robson, John M. and Kinzer, Bruce L., 5868. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mill, John S. 1988e. “The Reform Meeting in Hyde Park(1–4).” In Public and Parliamentary Speeches, Vol. 28 of The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, eds. Robson, John M. and Kinzer, Bruce L., 96, 98–100, 101–5. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mill, John S. 1988f. “The Westminster Election of 1868(III).” In Public and Parliamentary Speeches, Vol. 28 of The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, eds. Robson, John M. and Kinzer, Bruce L., 334–41. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mill, John S. 1988g. “Personal Representation.” In Public and Parliamentary Speeches, Vol. 28 of The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, eds. Robson, John M. and Kinzer, Bruce L., 176–87. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mill, John S. 1988h. “The Reform Bill (8).” Public and Parliamentary Speeches, Vol. 28 of The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, eds. Robson, John M. and Kinzer, Bruce L., 207–11. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.Google Scholar
Mills, Charles W. 2005. “Ideal Theory’ as Ideology.” Hypatia 20 (3): 165–83.Google Scholar
Mulvad, Andreas Møller, and Stahl, Rune Møller. 2019. “Civilizing Left Populism: Towards a Theory of Plebeian Democracy.” Constellations 26 (4): 591606.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ober, Josiah. 1989. Mass and Elite in Democratic Athens. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pettit, Philip. 2012. On the People’s Terms: A Republican Theory and Model of Democracy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Philips, Menaka. 2019. “Troubling Appropriations: J. S. Mill, Liberalism, and the Virtues of Uncertainty.” European Journal of Political Theory 18 (1): 6888.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Piketty, Thomas. 2014. Capital in the Twenty-First Century, trans. Goldhammer, Arthur. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Pitts, Jennifer. 2005. A Turn to Empire: The Rise of Imperial Liberalism in Britain and France. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rahman, K. Sabeel. 2016. Democracy against Domination. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Rossi, Enzo, and Sleat, Matt. 2014. “Realism in Normative Theory.” Philosophy Compass 9 (10): 689701.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sabl, Andrew. 2017. “Realist Liberalism: An Agenda.” Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 20 (3): 366–84.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sarvasy, Wendy. 1984. “J. S. Mill’s Theory of Democracy for a Period of Transition between Capitalism and Socialism.” Polity 16 (4): 567–87.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Saunders-Hastings, Emma. 2014. “No Better to Give Than to Receive: Charity and Women’s Subjection in J. S. Mill.” Polity 46 (2): 233–54.Google Scholar
Schofield, Philip. 2006. Utility and Democracy: The Political Thought of Jeremy Bentham. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Selinger, William. 2019a. Parliamentarianism: From Burke to Weber. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Selinger, William 2019b. “Fighting Electoral Corruption in the Victorian Era: An Overlooked Dimension of John Stuart Mill’s Political Thought.” European Journal of Political Theory 18 (3): 415–36.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Skocpol, Theda, and Hertel-Fernandez, Alexander. 2016. “The Koch Network and Republican Party Extremism.” Perspectives on Politics 14 (3): 681–99.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sleat, Matt. 2013. Liberal Realism: A Realist Theory of Liberal Politics. Manchester: Manchester University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ten, C. L. 1998. “Democracy, Socialism, and the Working Classes.” In The Cambridge Companion to Mill, ed. Skorupski, John, 372395. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thomas, Alan. 2016. Republic of Equals: Predistribution and Property-Owning Democracy. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thompson, Dennis F. 1976. John Stuart Mill and Representative Government. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Thompson, E. P. 1966. The Making of the English Working Class. New York: Vintage Books.Google Scholar
Urbinati, Nadia. 2019. Me The People: How Populism Transforms Democracy. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Urbinati, Nadia. 2002. Mill on Democracy: From the Athenian Polis to Representative Government. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Vergara, Camila. 2020. “Populism as Plebeian Politics: Inequality, Domination, and Popular Empowerment.” Journal of Political Philosophy 28 (2): 222–46.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Varouxakis, Georgios. 2013. Liberty Abroad: J . S. Mill on International Relations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Müller, Jan-Werner. 2016. What is Populism? Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Waldron, Jeremy. 2016. Political Political Theory: Essays on Institutions . Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Winters, Jeffrey A. 2011. Oligarchy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Winters, Jeffrey A., and Page, Benjamin I.. 2009. “Oligarchy in the United States?Perspectives on Politics 7 (4): 731–51.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Winter, Yves. 2012. “Plebeian Politics: Machiavelli and the Ciompi Uprising.” Political Theory 40 (6): 736–66.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zerilli, Linda M.G. 1994. Signifying Woman: Culture and Chaos in Rousseau, Burke, and Mill. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zucman, Gabriel. 2015. The Hidden Wealth of Nations: The Scourge of Tax Havens, trans. Fagan, Teresa Lavender. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Submit a response

Comments

No Comments have been published for this article.