Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-g8jcs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-28T22:34:40.807Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Hugo Grotius on Ethics and War

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 August 2014

Steven Forde*
Affiliation:
University of North Texas

Abstract

Interest in the thought of Hugo Grotius on international law and ethics is justified inasmuch as he attempted to define a theoretical position between an idealism he thought counterproductive and an amoral realism he found unacceptable. Grotius constructed a system in which the moral authority of natural law was combined with the flexibility of human law. This required him to develop a special understanding of the nature and relation of these two types of law. In giving the law of nations, as a product of human will, the authority to suspend provisions of natural law, he provided for a code of international conduct that could permit injustice where necessary, without abandoning moral ideals altogether.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © American Political Science Association 1998

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

Aquinas, Thomas. 1952. The Summa Theologiae. 2 vols. Trans., Fathers of the English Province, rev. Sullivan, Daniel J.. Chicago: Encyclopaedia Britannica (Great Books of the Western World).Google Scholar
Aristotle, . 1977. Politics. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press (Loeb Classical Library).Google Scholar
Buckle, Stephen. 1991. Natural Law and the Theory of Property: Grotius to Hume. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Bull, Hedley. 1990. “The Importance of Grotius in the Study of international Relations.” In Hugo Grotius and International Relations, ed. Bull, Hedley, Kingsbury, Benedict, and Roberts, Adam. New York: Oxford University Press. Pp. 6593.Google Scholar
Cicero, . 1975. De Officiis. Trans. Miller, Walter. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press (Loeb Classical Library).Google Scholar
Finnis, John. 1980. Natural Law and Natural Rights. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Fortin, Ernest. 1996a. “Augustine, Thomas Aquinas, and the Problem of Natural Law.” In Classical Christianity and the Political Order. New York: Rowman & Littlefield. Pp. 199222.Google Scholar
Fortin, Ernest. 1996b. “Natural Law.” In Human Rights, Virtue, and the Common Good: Untimely Meditations on Religion and Politics. New York: Rowman & Littlefield. Pp. 159–64.Google Scholar
Gentili, Alberico. [1612] 1933. De Iure Belli Libri Tres. Trans. Rolfe, John C.. Washington, DC: Carnegie Endowment for International Peace.Google Scholar
Grotius, Hugo. [1604] 1950. De Iure Paedae Commentarius: Commentary on the Law of Prize and Booty. Trans. Williams, Gwladys L. and Zeydel, Walter H.. Washington, DC: Carnegie Endowment for International Peace.Google Scholar
Grotius, Hugo. [1625] 1925. The Law of War and Peace: De Jure Belli ac Pacis Libri Tres. Trans. Kelsey, Francis W.. Washington, DC: Carnegie Endowment for International Peace (reprinted, no date, by Bobbs-Merrill, New York).Google Scholar
Haakonssen, Knud. 1985. “Hugo Grotius and the History of Political Thought.” Political Theory 13(May):239–65.Google Scholar
Haakonssen, Knud. 1996. Natural Law and Moral Philosophy: From Grotius to the Scottish Enlightenment. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Justinian, . 1987. Justinian's Institutes. Trans. Birks, Peter and McLeod, Grant. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel. [1795] 1983. “To Perpetual Peace: A Philosophical Sketch.” In Perptual Peace and Other Essays, trans. Humphrey, Ted. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett. Pp. 107–43.Google Scholar
Kingsbury, Benedict. 1997. “A Grotian Tradition of Theory and Practice? Grotius, Law, and Moral Skepticism in the Thought of Hedley Bull.” QLR (publication of the Law Review Association of Quinnipiac College School of Law) 17(Spring):334.Google Scholar
Kosai, Naoya. 1993. “The Laws of War.” In A Normative Approach to War: Peace War, and Justice in Hugo Grotius, ed. Onuma, Yasuaki. New York: Oxford University Press. Pp. 244–75.Google Scholar
Lauterpacht, H. 1985. “The Grotian Tradition in International Law.” In International Law: A Contemporary Perspective, ed. Falk, Richard, Kratochwil, Friedrich, and Mendlovitz, Saul H.. Boulder, CO: Westview.Google Scholar
Nederman, Cary J. 1996. “Property and Protest: Political Theory and Subjective Rights in Fourteenth-Century England.” Review of Politics 58(Spring):323–44.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nussbaum, Arthur. 1950. A Concise History of the Law of Nations. New York: MacMillan.Google Scholar
Olivecrona, Karl. 1971. Law as Fact, 2d ed. London: Steven & Sons.Google Scholar
Olivecrona, Karl. 1977. “Die zwei Schichten im naturrechtlichen Denken.” Archiv für Rechts- und Sozialphilosophie, 63:1, 79102.Google Scholar
Onuma, Yasuaki. 1993a. “Agreement.” In A Normative Approach to War: Peace War, and Justice in Hugo Grotius, ed. Onuma, Yasuaki. New York: Oxford University Press. Pp. 174220.Google Scholar
Onuma, Yasuaki. 1993b. “Conclusion: Law Dancing to the Accompaniment of Love and Calculation.” In A Normative Approach to War: Peace War, and Justice in Hugo Grotius, ed. Onuma, Yasuaki. New York: Oxford University Press. Pp. 333–70.Google Scholar
Rabkin, Jeremy. 1997. “Grotius, Vattel and Locke: An Older View of Liberalism and Nationality.” Review of Politics 59(Spring):293322.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rousseau, Jean-Jacques. [1755] 1964. Second Discourse. In The First and Second Discourses, ed. Masters, Roger, trans. Masters, Judith. New York: St. Martin's. Pp. 76228.Google Scholar
Rousseau, Jean-Jacques. [1762] 1978. On the Social Contract. Ed. Masters, Roger, trans. Masters, Judith. New York: St. Martin's.Google Scholar
Strauss, Leo. 1953. Natural Right and History. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Suárez, , Francisco, S.J. [1612] 1944. A Treatise on Laws and God the Lawgiver. Trans. Williams, Gwladys L. (Carnegie Endowment edition). New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Tanaka, Tadashi. 1993. “Temperamenta (Moderation).” In A Normative Approach to War: Peace War, and Justice in Hugo Grotius, ed. Onuma, Yasuaki. New York: Oxford University Press. Pp. 276307.Google Scholar
Tuck, Richard. 1979. Natural Rights Theories: Their Origin and Development. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Tuck, Richard. 1993. Philosophy and Government 1572–1651. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Villey, Michel. 1962. Leçons d'histoire de la philosophie du droit. Paris: Dalloz.Google Scholar
Villey, Michel. 1964. La genèse du droit subjectif chez Guillaume d'Occam. Archives de philosophie du droit 9:97127.Google Scholar
Vitoria, Francisco de. [1539] 1991. On the Law of War. In Francisco de Vitoria: Political Writings, ed. Pagdon, Anthony and Lawrance, Jeremy. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Wight, Martin. 1966. “Western Values in International Relations.” In Diplomatic Investigations, ed. Butterfield, Herbert and Wight, Martin. London: George Allen and Unwin.Google Scholar
Zuckert, Michael P. 1989. “Bringing Philosophy Down from the Heavens: Natural Right in the Roman Law.” Review of Politics 51(1):7085.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zuckert, Michael P. 1994. Natural Rights and the New Republicanism. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Submit a response

Comments

No Comments have been published for this article.