Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-m6dg7 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-04T19:22:34.030Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Calvin and the Reformation: The Political Education of Protestantism

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  02 September 2013

Sheldon S. Wolin
Affiliation:
University of California (Berkeley)

Extract

The purpose of this essay is to draw attention to two aspects of the political ideas of the sixteenth century Reformation which were important to the development of the Western tradition of political theory. First, like all great transformations, the Reformation stimulated the rethinking of much that had been taken for granted. In terms of political ideas, this centered around a developing crisis in the concept of order and in the Western traditions of civility. The criticism of the papacy by the early reformers had really amounted to a demand for the liberation of the individual believer from a mass of institutional controls and traditional restraints which hitherto had governed his behavior. The medieval church had been many things, and among them, a system of governance. It had sought, not always successfully, to control the conduct of its members through a definite code of discipline, to bind them to unity through emotional as well as material commitments, and to direct the whole religious endeavor through an institutionalized power structure as impressive as any the world had seen. In essence, the Church had provided a rationalized set of restraints designed to mould human behavior to accord with a certain image. To condemn it as the agent of the Antichrist was to work towards the release of human behavior from the order which had formed it. This liberating tendency was encouraged by one of the great ideas of the early reformers, the conception of the church as a fellowship bound together by the ties of faith and united in a common quest for salvation. But the Genossenschaft-idea lacked the complementary notion of the church as a corpus regens, a corporate society welded together by a viable structure of power. The inference remaining was that men could be fashioned to live in an orderly community without the serious and consistent application of force.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © American Political Science Association 1957

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Works of Martin Luther, ed. Jacobs, Charles M., 6 vols. (Philadelphia, 19151932), Vol. 5, p. 81Google Scholar, hereafter cited as Works.

2 de la Tour, P. Imbart, Les origines de la Réformation, 4 vols. (Paris, 19051935), Vol. 4, p. 53Google Scholar.

3 “Letter from Calvin to Sadolet,” Tracts Relating to the Reformation, trans, by Beveridge, Henry, 3 vols. (Edinburgh, 1844), Vol. 1, p. 37Google Scholar.

4 The Institutes of the Christian Religion, trans, by Allen, John, 2 vols. (Philadelphia, n.d.), Vol. 2, pp. 281–83Google Scholar (IV, i, 8–10). Hereafter this will be cited as Inst. and all translations, except where indicated, will be from it.

5 “For unless we are united with all the other members under Christ our Head, we can have no hope of the future inheritance …. But all the elect of God are so connected with each other in Christ, that as they depend upon one head, so they grow up together as into one body, compacted together like members of the same body; being made truly one, as living by one faith, hope, and charity, through the same Divine Spirit, being called not only to the same inheritance of eternal life, but also to a participation of one God and Christ … the saints are united in the fellowship of Christ on this condition, that whatever benefits God confers upon them, they should mutually communicate to each other.” Ibid., Vol. 2, pp. 271–72 (IV, i, 2–3).

6 Commentaries on the Epistle of Paul the Apostle to the Romans, trans, by Owen, John (Edinburgh, 1849), p. 458Google Scholar. Hereafter this will be cited as Commentaries on Romans. On this same point see Bohatec, Josef, Calvins Lehre vom Staat und Kirche (Breslau, 1937), p. 271Google Scholar.

7 “… such care as we take of our own body, we ought to exercise the same care of our brethren, who are members of our body; that as no part of our body can be in any pain without every other part feeling corresponding sensations, so we ought not to suffer our brother to be afflicted with any calamity without our sympathizing in the same.” Inst., Vol. 2, pp. 696–97Google Scholar (IV, xvii, 38). A supplementary bond was also provided by the sacrament of baptism which initiated the member into the “society of the church.” Inst., Vol. 2, pp. 583, 611Google Scholar (IV, xv, 1; xvi, 9).

8 Commentaries on Romans, pp. 458–59.

9 Works, Vol. 4, pp. 234–37Google Scholar; and see the Augsburg Confession (1530), Pt. II, art. VII in Schiff, Philip (ed.), The Creeds of Christendom, 3 vols. (New York, 1877), Vol. 3, p. 58 ff.Google Scholar

10 D. Martin Luthers Werke (Weimar Ausgabe, 1888–), Vol. 30, Pt. II, pp. 435, 462Google Scholar.

11 Works, Vol. 2, pp. 37–8, 52Google Scholar.

12 Note the analogies drawn by Calvin between religious and political institutions; Inst., Vol. 2, p. 483 ffGoogle Scholar. (IV, xi).

13 Inst., Vol. 2, pp. 477–83Google Scholar (IV, x, 27–29; IV, xi, 1).

14 Inst., Vol. 1, pp. 52, 218, 220, 232Google Scholar (I, ii, 1; xvi, 1–3; xvii, 1). The substance of these passages is that God is not “idle and almost asleep” but “engaged in continuous action.”

15 Inst., Vol. 2, pp. 89–90, 770–71Google Scholar (III, xix, 14; IV, xx, 1).

16 Calvani Opera, ed. Baum, G., Cunitz, E., and Reuss, E., 59 vols. (Braunschweig, 18631900), Vol. 2, pp. 622–23Google Scholar; Vol. 4, p. 358 (Inst., III, xix, 15Google Scholar). These volumes form part of the Corpus Reformatorum, and hereafter they will be cited as Opera.

17 Inst., Vol. 2, p. 90Google Scholar (III, xix, 15).

18 Inst., Vol. 2, pp. 422–23Google Scholar (IV, viii, 8).

19 Inst., Vol. 1, p. 74Google Scholar (I, v, 11).

20 Inst., Vol. 2, p. 452Google Scholar (IV, x, 5).

21 Inst., IV, x, 27Google Scholar. Here I have followed the translation of Henry Beveridge in his edition, 2 vols. (Grand Rapids, Mich., 1953), Vol. 2, p. 434.

22 Inst., Vol. 2, p. 439Google Scholar (IV, xi, 1), Beveridge translation. Calvin consciously sought to widen the power of jurisdiction by tracing it back to the Jewish Sanhedrin and thereby capitalizing on the extensive authority of that body.

23 Inst., Vol. 2, pp. 503–4Google Scholar (IV, xii, 1).

24 See the discussion of Mesnard, Pierre, L'Essor de la philosophie politique au XVIe siècle, 2nd ed. (Paris, 1952), p. 283 ff.Google Scholar

25 Inst., Vol. 2, pp. 273–74Google Scholar (IV, i, 4). It is important to note that the ultimate power of excommunication was placed specifically in the hands of the higher officers of the church, that is, the pastors and the Council of Elders. The power was specifically excluded from the province of the magistrates and the congregation.

26 De Civitate Dei, Lib. XVIII, cap. 51.

27 Inst., Vol. 1, pp. 35–6Google Scholar (Ded. Epist.), 86–7 (I, vii, 1–2); Vol. 2, pp. 417–19 (IV, viii, 2–4); “Letter to Sadolet,” Tracts, Vol. 1, p. 50Google Scholar.

28 Foster, Herbert D., “Calvin's Program for a Puritan State in Geneva,” Collected Papers of Herbert D. Foster (privately printed, 1929), p. 64Google Scholar; Doumergue, Emile, Jean Calvin. Les hommes et les choses de son temps, 7 vols. (Lausanne, 18991928), Vol. 5, p. 188 ffGoogle Scholar; Mesnard, op. cit., p. 301 ff.

29 In Doumergue's magisterial work on Calvin there is a spirited defense of the thesis that Calvin's theory of the church embodied a strong “representative” element. Yet Doumergue's argument is weakened by his failure to ask: what and whom do the officers of the church represent? He is content, instead, to indicate the several passages where Calvin provided for congregational approval of certain church officers. The difficulty here is that election is not the same as representation, especially when it is not accompanied by a power of recall. Hence even though Calvin declared that the ministers constituted a corpus ecclesiae repraesentans (Opera, Vol. 14, p. 681Google Scholar), his meaning was that the ministers represented the purposes of the church as defined by Scripture. He did not mean that the ministers represented the wills or separate interests of the members of the congregation, hence Doumergue's attempt to relate the Calvinist theory of the church to modern representative government is not convincing. See his discussion, Vol. 5, pp. 158–62.

30 Inst., Vol. 2, pp. 318–19Google Scholar (IV, iii, 2); see also ibid., p. 317 (IV, iii, 1).

31 Inst., Vol. 2, p. 424Google Scholar (IV, viii, 9).

32 Inst., Vol. 2, p. 417Google Scholar (IV, viii, 2).

33 The authority and dignity of the pastoral office, according to Calvin, belonged not “to the persons themselves, but to the ministry over which they were appointed, or to speak more correctly, to the Word, the ministration of which was committed to them.” Inst., Vol. 2, p. 424Google Scholar (IV, viii, 9). American constitutional lawyers will recognize in this a forerunner of the role the Supreme Court in the nineteenth century claimed for itself when interpreting the Constitution in the exercise of its power of judicial review.

34 Inst., Vol. 1, p. 223Google Scholar (I, xvi, 4).

35 Inst., Vol. 1, p. 233Google Scholar (I, xvii, 1).

36 Inst., Vol. 2, p. 771Google Scholar (IV, xx, 2).

37 Inst., Vol. 2, p. 90Google Scholar (III, xix, 25).

38 “Had we remained in the state of natural integrity such as God first created, the order of justice would not have been necessary. For each would then have carried the law in his own heart, so that no constraint would have been needed to keep us in check. Each would be his own rule and with one mind we would do what is good. Hence justice is a remedy of this human corruption. And whenever one speaks of human justice let us recognize that in it we have the mirror of our perversity, since it is by force we are led to follow equity and reason.” Opera, Vol. 27, p. 409Google Scholar. See also Opera, Vol. 7, p. 84Google Scholar; Vol. 49, p. 249; Vol. 52, p. 267; and the discussion in Chenevière, , La pensée politique de Calvin (Paris, 1937), pp. 9394Google Scholar.

39 Inst., Vol. 1, p. 294Google Scholar (II, ii, 13).

40 Inst., Vol. 2, p. 774Google Scholar (IV, xx, 4).

41 Inst., Vol. 2, p. 90Google Scholar (III, xix, 15); Vol. 2, p. 771 (IV, xx, 2).

42 Inst., Vol. 2, p. 90Google Scholar (III, xix, 15); Vol. 2, pp. 772–73 (IV, xx, 3).

43 Inst., Vol. 2, p. 772Google Scholar (IV, xx, 2).

44 Inst., Vol. 2, p. 772Google Scholar (IV, xx, 2). I have slightly changed the translation; see the text in Opera, Vol. 2, p. 1094Google Scholar. In connection with this point it is interesting to note how Calvin reversed the usual argument and asserted that obedience to human superiors helped to habituate men to obedience to God. Inst., Vol. 2, p. 433Google Scholar (II, viii, 35).

45 Cited in Doumergue, op. cit., Vol. 5, p. 45.

46 Compare Calvin's use of the corpus mysticum to that of the fifteenth century writer SirFortescue, John, De Laudibus Legum Anglie, edited and translated by Chrimes, S. B. (Cambridge, 1949)Google Scholar, cap. xiii. The whole problem of the influence of the Eucharist on political ideas remains to be explored. Some suggestive points are to be found in two articles by Kantorowicz, Ernst H., “Pro Patria Mori in Medieval Political Thought,” American Historical Review, Vol. 56, pp. 472–92 (April, 1951)CrossRefGoogle Scholar, and Mysteries of State: An Absolutist Concept and Its Late Mediaeval Origins,” Harvard Theological Review, Vol. 48, pp. 6591 (Jan., 1955)CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Fundamental for this problem is de Lubac, Henri, Corpus Mysticum, 2nd ed. (Paris, 1949)Google Scholar.

47 Inst., Vol. 1, pp. 790–91Google Scholar (III, x, 6).

48 Inst., Vol. 1, p. 757 (III, vii, 5).Google Scholar

49 Inst., Vol. 1, p. 294Google Scholar (II, ii, 13).

50 Inst., Vol. 1, pp. 295–96Google Scholar (II, ii, 14–15); pp. 298–99 (II, ii, 17–18); p. 366 (II, v, 19).

51 Inst., Vol. 1, p. 295Google Scholar (II, ii, 13).

52 Inst., Vol. 1, p. 296Google Scholar (II, ii, 15).

53 Inst., Vol. 1, p. 306Google Scholar (II, ii, 13). The translation has been slightly changed; see the text in Opera, Vol. 2, p. 197Google Scholar.

54 Inst., Vol. 1, p. 397Google Scholar (II, viii, 1).

55 Inst., Vol. 2, p. 789Google Scholar (IV, xx. 16).

56 Inst., Vol. 2, p. 787Google Scholar (IV, xx, 14). The phrase is derived from Cicero, , De Legibus, IIIGoogle Scholar, 1.2 and is related to the classical tradition of the ruler as lex animata; see Goodenough, Erwin R., “The Political Philosophy of Hellenistic Kingship,” Yale Classical Studies, Vol. 1 (1928), p. 55 ff.Google Scholar

57 See Mesnard, op. cit., pp. 285–89; Chenevière, op. cit., p. 298.

58 Opera, Vol. 52, p. 267Google Scholar.

59 Commentaries on Romans, p. 481.

60 Ibid., p. 480.

61 Commentary on the Book of Psalms, trans. Anderson, James, 5 vols. (Edinburgh, 18451849), Vol. 3, p. 106Google Scholar; Inst., Vol. 2, pp. 801–2Google Scholar (IV, xx, 27).

62 Given the lofty ends served by allegiance—“God had not intended men to live pêle-mêle” (Opera, Vol. 51, p. 800Google Scholar)—it is not surprising to find Calvin hostile to contract theory. This was not owing to any desire on his part to release rulers from their obligations, but rather to his belief that social duties ought not to be the subject of a crude bartering arrangement. Inst., Vol. 2, pp. 801802Google Scholar (IV, xx, 27).

63 Inst., Vol. 2, p. 805Google Scholar (IV, xx, 32).

64 Inst., Vol. 2, p. 790Google Scholar (IV, xx, 16); p. 798 (IV, xx, 24).

65 “Catechism of 1537,” Opera, Vol. 22, p. 74Google Scholar.

66 Inst., Vol. 2, p. 805Google Scholar (IV, xx, 32).

67 Inst., Vol. 2, p. 804Google Scholar (IV, xx, 31); Opera, Vol. 4, p. 1160Google Scholar.

68 Opera, Vol. 29, pp. 557, 636–37Google Scholar; Chenevière, op. cit., pp. 346–47.

69 Works, Vol. 5, pp. 5152Google Scholar.

70 Inst., Vol. 2, pp. 773, 787Google Scholar (IV, xx, 3, 14).

71 Opera, Vol. 43, p. 374Google Scholar; and the discussion of McNeill, John T., “The Democratic Element in Calvin's Thought,” Church History, Vol. 18, pp. 153–71 (Sept., 1949)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

72 Woodhouse, A. S. P. (ed.), Puritanism and Liberty (London, 1938), p. 53Google Scholar.

73 Commentaries on Romans, p. 459.

74 Inst., Vol. 2, p. 272Google Scholar (IV, i, 3).

Submit a response

Comments

No Comments have been published for this article.