Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-7cvxr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-25T00:52:25.948Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Aristotle on the Conditions for and Limits of the Common Good

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 August 2014

Thomas W. Smith*
Affiliation:
Villanova University

Abstract

Contemporary debates over liberal political theory should encourage renewed investigation of the common good, and it is appropriate to begin by interrogating Aristotle's account. Aristotle argues that injustice stands in the way of the common good. Injustice is motivated by both overgrasping for scarce external goods, such as money, honor, and power, and by excessive desires. Aristotle argues that the common good requires a reorientation away from external goods to satisfying activities that do not diminish in the sharing. He sketches an analogical account of familial and political relationships that leads us to wonder what the political conditions are for the common good. Reflecting on these conditions not only points to the strict limits of the common good but also speaks to both sides in debates over liberal theory.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © American Political Science Association 1999

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

Ackerman, Bruce. 1980. Social Justice in the Liberal State. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Ackrill, J. L. 1980. “Aristotle on Eudaimonia.” In Essays on Aristotle's Ethics, ed. Rorty, Amélie. Berkeley: University of California Press. Pp. 1534.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aristotelis, . 1986. Politica. Ed. Ross, W.D.Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Aristotelis, . 1988. Ethica Nicomachea. Ed. Bywater, I.Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Aristotle, . 1982. The Art of Rhetoric. Trans. Freese, J.H.Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Aristotle, . 1985. Nicomachean Ethics. Trans. Irwin, Terence. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett.Google Scholar
Aristotle, . 1989. Posterior Analytics and Topics. Trans. Tredennick, H. and Forster, E. S.Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Aristotle, . 1992. Athenian Constitution, Eudemian Ethics, Virtues and Vices. Trans. Rackham, H.Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Bellah, Robert Richard Madsen, Sullivan, William, Swidler, Ann, and Tipton, Steven. 1985. Habits of the Heart: Individualism and Commitment in American Life. New York: Harper and Row.Google Scholar
Berry, Wendell. 1977. The Unsettling of America: Culture and Agriculture. San Francisco, CA: Sierra Club Books.Google Scholar
Berry, Wendell. 1992. Sex, Economy, Freedom, and Community. New York: Pantheon Books.Google Scholar
Bodéüs, Richard. 1993. The Political Dimensions of Aristotle's Ethics. Trans. Garrett, J. E.Albany: State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
Booth, William James. 1993. Households: On the Moral Architecture of the Economy. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burrell, David. 1973. Analogy and Philosophical Language. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Casey, John. 1990. Pagan Virtue: An Essay in Ethics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Cohen, David. 1995. Law, Violence, and Community in Classical Athens. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cooper, John. 1980. “Aristotle on Friendship.” In Essays on Aristotle's Ethics, ed. Rorty, Amélie O.Berkeley: University of California Press. Pp. 301–40.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cooper, John. 1986. Reason and the Human Good in Aristotle. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett.Google Scholar
DeKonnick, Charles. 1943. De la primauté du bien commun, contre les personnalistes. Québec: Éditions de L'Université Laval.Google Scholar
Dupré, Louis. 1993. “The Common Good and the Open Society.” Review of Politics 55 (Fall): 687712.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Etzioni, Amitai, ed. 1998. The Essential Communitarian Reader. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
Finnis, John. 1980. Natural Law and Natural Rights. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
Flannery, Austin, ed. 1996. The Sixteen Basic Documents of Vatican II: Constitutions, Decrees, Declarations. Northport, NY: Costello.Google Scholar
Goerner, E. A. 1966. “The Notion of Christendom and the Problem of Justice.” Continuum 3 (Winter): 436–53.Google Scholar
Goerner, E. A., and Thompson, Walter J. 1996. “Politics and Coercion.” Political Theory 24 (November): 620–52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hardie, W. F. R. 1968. Aristotle's Ethical Theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hauerwas, Stanley, and Pinches, Charles. 1997. Christians among the Virtues: Theological Conversations and Modern Ethics. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
Hobbes, Thomas. [1668] 1994. Leviathan. Ed. Curley, Edwin. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett.Google Scholar
Holmes, Stephen. 1993. The Anatomy of Antiliberalism. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Keys, Mary M. 1995. “Personal Dignity and the Common Good: A Twentieth Century Thomistic Dialogue.” In Catholicism, Liberalism and Communitarianism: The Catholic Intellectual Tradition and the Moral Foundations of Democracy, ed. Grasso, Kenneth, Bradley, Gerard V., and Hunt, Robert P.Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield. Pp. 173–95.Google Scholar
Kraut, Richard. 1989. Aristotle on the Human Good. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Locke, John. [1690] 1959. An Essay Concerning Human Understanding. Ed. Fraser, Alexander. New York: Dover.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lowi, Theodore. 1995. The End of the Republica Era. Norman: University of Oklahoma Press.Google Scholar
Macedo, Stephen. 1992. Liberal Virtues: Citizens, Virtue, and Community in Liberal Constitutionalism. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
Macedo, Stephen. 1998. “Transformative Constitutionalism and the Case of Religion: Defending the Moderate Hegemony of Liberalism.” Political Theory 26 (February): 5680.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
MacIntyre, Alasdair. 1984. After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
MacIntyre, Alasdair. 1988. Whose Justice? Which Rationality? Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
MacIntyre, Alasdair. 1990. “The Privatization of the Good.” Review of Politics 52 (Summer): 344–77.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mara, Gerald. 1987. “The Role of Philosophy in Aristotle's Political Science.” Polity 19 (Spring): 375401.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mara, Gerald. 1995. “The Near Made Far Away: The Role of Cultural Criticism in Aristotle's Political Theory.” Political Theory 23 (Spring): 280303.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mill, John Stuart. [1859] 1947. On Liberty. Ed. Castell, Aubrey. Arlington Heights, IL: Harlan Davidson.Google Scholar
Millbank, John. 1990. Theology and Social Theory: Beyond Secular Reason. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Nadon, Christopher. 1996. “Aristotle and the Republican Paradigm.” Review of Politics 58 (Fall): 677–98.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nichols, Mary. 1992. Citizens and Statesmen: A Study of Aristotle's Politics. Savage, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
Novak, Michael. 1989. Free Persons and the Common Good. New York: Madison Books.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, Martha. 1986. The Fragility of Goodness. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Ober, Josiah. 1989. Mass and Elite in Democratic Athens. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
O'Connor, David. 1988. “Aristotelian Justice as Personal Virtue.” In Midwest Studies in Philosophy, Volume XIII, ed. French, Peter and Uehling, Theodore. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press. Pp. 417–27.Google Scholar
O'Connor, David. 1991. “The Aetiology of Justice.” In Essays on the Foundations of Aristotelian Political Science, ed. Lord, Carnes and O'Connor, David. Berkeley: University of California Press. Pp. 136–90.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pangle, Thomas. 1992. The Ennobling of Democracy: The Challenge of the Postmodern Age. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins Press.Google Scholar
Price, A.W. 1989. Love and Friendship in Plato and Aristotle. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
Rawls, John. 1971. A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rawls, John. 1993. Political Liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Rourke, Thomas. 1996. “Michael Novak and Yves Simon on the Common Good and Capitalism.” Review of Politics 58 (Spring): 229–58.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Salkever, Stephen. 1990a. Finding the Mean. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Salkever, Stephen. 1990b. “‘Lopp'd and Bound’: How Liberal Theory Obscures the Goods of Liberal Practices.” In Liberalism and the Good, ed. Douglas, R. Bruce, Mara, Gerald M., and Richardson, Henry S.New York: Routledge. Pp. 167202.Google Scholar
Salkever, Stephen. 1991. “Women, Citizens and Soldiers: Plato and Aristotle on the Politics of Virility.” In Essays on the Foundations of Aristotelian Political Science, ed. Lord, Carnes and O'Connor, David. Berkeley: University of California Press. Pp. 165–90.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Salkever, Stephen. 1998. “The Deliberative Model of Democracy and Aristotle's Ethics of Natural Questions.” Bryn Mawr College. Typescript.Google Scholar
Sandel, Michael. 1982. Liberalism and the Limits of Justice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Schollmeier, Paul. 1994. Other Selves: Aristotle on Personal and Political Friendship. Albany: State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
Simpson, Peter. 1998. A Philosophical Commentary on Aristotle's Politics. Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press.Google Scholar
Smith, Thomas W. 1994. “The Protreptic Character of the Nicomachean Ethics.” Polity 57 (Winter): 307–30.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sorabji, Richard. 1980. “Aristotle on the Role of Intellect in Virtue.” In Essays on Aristotle's Ethics, ed. Rorty, Amélie. Berkeley: University of California Press. Pp. 202–20.Google Scholar
Taylor, Charles. 1989. Sources of the Self: The Making of the Modern Identity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Tessitore, Aristede. 1996. Reading Aristotle's Ethics: Virtue, Rhetoric, and Political Philosophy. Albany: State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
Thompson, Walter J. 1994. “Aristotle: Philosophy and Politics, Theory and Practice.” American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 68 (Supplement): 109–24.Google Scholar
Thucydides, . 1983. The Peloponnesian War. Trans. Warner, Rex. New York: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
Walker, A. D. M. 1979. “Aristotle's Account of Friendship in the Nicomachean Ethics.” Phronesis 24 (2): 180–96.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Walzer, Michael. 1983. Spheres of Justice. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Williamson, Robert, ed., 1986. Lectures and Essays by Jacob Klein. Annapolis, MD: St. John's Press.Google Scholar
Voegelin, Eric. 1978. Anamnesis. Trans. Niemeyer, Gerhart. Columbia: University of Missouri Press.Google Scholar
Yack, Bernard. 1993. The Problems of a Political Animal. Berkeley: University of California Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Submit a response

Comments

No Comments have been published for this article.