Article contents
Equality and Human Need
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 01 August 2014
Abstract
This paper has the twofold purpose of exploring how and whether it may be said that value arises from human need and, in particular, how the value of equality may arise from an alleged human need for recognition. It traces two opposite dispositions toward recognition, one seeing it as destructive of the minimum conditions for political life, the other viewing it as the principal agency through which men achieve their humanity. The concept of a basic human need is then exposed to the criticism of “social apperception,” which apparently renders meaningless the concept altogether. Nevertheless, two “faces” of recognition are explored – one affirming that common human nature in virtue of which all men are said to be equal, and the other, affirming the concrete specificity of each individual. The paper concludes by arguing that this second aspect of the drive for recognition, which is viewed by some as the primary political obligation, is actually not a legitimate aspiration of political life.
- Type
- Articles
- Information
- Copyright
- Copyright © American Political Science Association 1977
References
1 Aristotle, Politics, 1253a15.
2 Rokeach, Milton, The Nature of Human Values (New York: Free Press, 1973), p. 20 Google Scholar. On the problem of the synonomous use of the terms “good” and “value,” see Diamond, Martin, “The Dependence of Fact Upon ‘Value,’” Interpretation, Volume 2/3 (Spring, 1972), 229–231 Google Scholar.
3 Hobbes, Thomas, Leviathan, ed. Oakeshott, Michael (New York: Collier, 1962), p. 98 Google Scholar.
4 Ibid., p. 120. Italics mine.
5 Ibid., p. 129.
6 Ibid., p. 99. Cf. also p. 131.
7 ibid., pp. 72–73.
8 Ibid., p. 73. Italics mine.
9 Ibid., p. 55.
10 Cf. Schaar, John H., “Some Ways of Thinking About Equality,” Journal of Politics, Volume 26 (11, 1964), 877–879 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
11 Horace, Epistles, Bk. 1, epistle x, 1.24.
12 See Rousseau, Jean Jacques, The Social Contract and Discourses, trans. Cole, G. D. H. (New York: E. P. Dutton, 1950), pp. 18–19, 38–39, 307–308 Google Scholar; Emile, trans. Foxley, Barbara (New York: Everyman, 1966), pp. 7–8 Google Scholar. Cf. also Charvet, John, “Individual Identity and Social Consciousness in Rousseau's Philosophy,” in Hobbes and Rousseau, ed. Cranston, Maurice and Peters, Richard S. (Garden City, N.Y.: Anchor, 1972), pp. 462–483 Google Scholar; and Charvet, John, “The Idea of Equality as a Substantive Principle of Society,” Political Studies, Vol. 17, No. 1 (03, 1969), 6–7 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
13 Strauss, Leo, On Tyranny (Ithaca, Cornell, 1968), p. 205 Google Scholar. The full quote is: “Both doctrines [i.e., Hobbes's and Hegel's] construct human society by starting from the untrue assumption that man as man is thinkable as a being that lacks awareness of sacred restraints or as a being that is guided by nothing but a desire for recognition.”
14 There is, of course, an analogue in classical thought to Rousseau's depreciation of political life. But, whereas classical philosophy rejects political life in favor of the philosophic life, Rousseau does so in favor of the self, of the sentiment of one's own existence.
15 See Lobkowicz, Nicholas, Theory and Practice (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1967), p. 356 Google Scholar, and also, Avineri, Shlomo, The Social and Political Thought of Karl Marx (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970), pp. 88–89 Google Scholar.
16 Cited in Avineri, p. 90.
17 In what follows, I am indebted for the exposition of Hegel's section in the Phenomenology on Mastery and Slavery to Kojève, Alexandre, Introduction to the Reading of Hegel, ed. Bloom, Allan (New York: Basic Books, 1969), pp. 3–30 Google Scholar.
18 Kojève, p. 6. See also Plamenatz, John, Man and Society (New York: McGraw-Hill, 1963), Vol. II, p. 152 Google Scholar.
19 Kojève, pp.9,11.
20 Kojève, p. 7.
21 Hegel's Philosophy of Right, trans. Knox, Thomas M. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1949), No. 209, p. 134 Google Scholar; also fn. to No. 270, pp. 168–169.
22 Ibid., No. 200, p. 130.
23 See the controversy between Strauss, and Kojève, in Strauss, , On Tyranny, pp. 154–156, 183–184, 221–226 Google Scholar. Cf. Plamenatz, pp. 155–156; Kelly, George A., “Notes on Hegel's ‘Lordship and Bondage,’” in Hegel: A Collection of Critical Essays, ed. MacIntyre, Alasdair (Garden City: Anchor, 1972), pp. 193, 214–217 Google Scholar; and Hook, Sidney, “Hegel Rehabilitated?” in Hegel's Political Philosophy, ed. Kaufmann, Walter (New York: Atherton, 1970), pp. 60–63 Google Scholar.
24 Kojève, Alexandre, “Tyranny and Wisdom,” in Strauss, , On Tyranny, p. 151 Google Scholar.
25 Plamenatz, p. 188.
26 Charvet, , “Equality,” p. 8 Google Scholar.
27 Bay, Christian, “Politics and Pseudopolitics: A Critical Evaluation of Some Behavioral Literature,” in Behavioralism in Political Science, ed. Eulau, Heinz (Chicago: Aldine-Atherton, 1969), p. 112 Google Scholar.
28 Ibid., p. 115. Italics mine.
29 Bodenheimer, Edgar, “Philosophical Anthropology and the Law,” California Law Review, Vol. 59, No. 3 (05, 1971), 662 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
30 Ibid., p. 679. Italics mine.
31 Ibid., pp. 679–680.
32 Ibid., p. 680.
33 Idem., and see also fn. 73.
34 Davies, James C., Human Nature in Politics (New York: John Wiley, 1963), pp. 6–7 Google Scholar. Cf. Rokeach, pp. 11, 14, 20.
35 Davies, p. 7.
36 See Lukes, Steven, Individualism (New York: Harper Torchbooks, 1973), pp. 150–152 Google Scholar, and also Zetterbaum, Marvin, “Human Nature and History,” in Human Nature in Politics, (NOMOS XVII), ed. Pennock, J. Roland and Chapman, John W. (New York: New York University Press, 1977), pp. 225–249.Google Scholar
37 Norman Cameron and Ann Margaret, cited in Spiro, Melford E. “Human Nature in Its Psychological Dimensions,” American Anthropologist, 56 (02, 1954), 19–30, at p. 24CrossRefGoogle Scholar. On the cultural components of such concepts as time, space, motion, object, and people, see Henry, Jules, Pathways to Madness (New York: Vintage, 1973), pp. 11–24 Google Scholar. Cf. Jaspers, Karl, “The Search for Being,” in The Existentialist Tradition, ed. Langiulli, Nino (Garden City, N.Y.: Anchor, 1971), pp. 167–168 Google Scholar.
38 Spiro, p. 25.
39 Ibid., p. 24. Cf. p. 27.
40 Ibid., p. 28. Cf. Rokeach, pp. 14–15.
41 Lee, Dorothy, “Equality of Opportunity as a Cultural Value,” in Lee, , Freedom and Culture (Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall, 1959), p. 44 Google Scholar.
42 Ibid., p. 48. Italics mine. See also in the same volume, “The Conception of Self Among the Wintu Indians,” pp. 131–132, 134.
43 Ibid., p. 46.
44 Lee, Dorothy, “Are Basic Needs Ultimate?”, Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology, 43 (07, 1948), 391–395, at p. 393CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.
45 Idem.
46 Ibid., p. 394.
47 Lukes, p. 51. Cf. Schaar, , “Some Ways”: “The older, pre-eighteenth century idea of a common humanity, often denied but never forgotten, was a moral assertion based not upon a generalization of experience but upon a postulate of reason and an exercise of faith” (pp. 876–877)Google Scholar.
48 Berlin, Isaiah, “Equality as an Ideal,” in Justice and Social Policy, ed. Olafson, Frederick A. (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 1961), p. 150 Google Scholar. See also The Sociology of Georg Simmel, trans, and ed. Wolff, Kurt H. (New York: The Free Press, 1950), pp. 73–74 Google Scholar; and also Haezrahi, Pepita, “The Concept of Man as End-in-Himself,” in Kant: A Collection of Critical Essays, ed. Wolff, Robert P. (Garden City, N.Y.: Anchor, 1967), pp. 302, 311–313 Google Scholar.
49 Berlin, p. 128.
50 Ibid., p. 150.
51 Ibid., p. 148.
52 Schumpeter, Joseph, Capitalism, Socialism and Democracy (New York: Harper Torchbooks, 1962), p. 243 Google Scholar. It is precisely this sentence that Berlin quotes approvingly in his Four Essays on Liberty (London: Oxford University Press, 1969), p. 172 Google Scholar.
53 Cf. Schaar, , “Some Ways,” p. 881 Google Scholar.
54 Spiegelberg, Herbert, “A Defense of Human Equality,” The Philosophical Review, Vol. LIII, No. 2 (03, 1944), 101–124 at p. 106CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Cf. Schutz, Alfred, “Equality and the Meaning Structure of the Social World,” in Aspects of Human Equality, ed. Bryson, Lyman et al. (New York: Harper, 1956), p. 37 Google Scholar.
55 Schaar, , “Some Ways,” p. 875 Google Scholar.
56 See, e.g., Selznick, Philip, “Natural Law and Sociology,” in Natural Law and Modern Society (Cleveland: World Publishing, 1963), pp. 168–169 Google Scholar.
57 Sentiments proclaiming the absolute value of the individual can also be found in Hegel. See The Philosophy of Hegel, ed. Friedrich, Carl J. (New York: Modern Library, 1954), p. 20 Google Scholar.
58 Williams, Bernard, “The Idea of Equality,” in Philosophy, Politics, and Society, (Second Series), ed. Laslett, Peter and Runciman, Walter G. (Oxford, Blackwell, 1962), p. 115 Google Scholar. But see Williams's demurrer, pp. 116–117, and cf. Charvet, , “Idea of Equality,” pp. 11–13 Google Scholar; Haezrahi, p. 294 and fn. 5; Spiegelberg, p. 108; Simmel, pp. 72–73; Hassner, Pierre, “Immanuel Kant,” in History of Political Philosophy, (2nd ed.), ed. Strauss, Leo and Cropsey, Joseph (Chicago: Rand McNally, 1972), pp. 559, 561 Google Scholar.
59 See fn. 36 above.
60 Lukes, p. 126.
61 Idem. Cf. Schaar, “Some Ways,” p. 880.
62 Lukes, p. 126.
63 Lukes, p. 133.
64 Williams, pp. 112–114.
65 Schaar, , “Some Ways,” p. 880 Google Scholar.
66 Lukes, pp. 146ff.
67 Schaar, , “Some Ways,” p. 885 Google Scholar.
68 Simmel, pp. 67–68. See also, ibid., pp. 58–84.
69 Lukes, p. 149.
70 Schaar, , “Some Ways,” p. 886 Google Scholar.
71 Ibid., p. 887. Cf., ibid., p. 884.
72 Ibid., p. 895. See also Schaar's description of the political, p. 889. Cf. Zetterbaum, Marvin, Tocqueville and the Problem of Democracy (Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press, 1967), pp. 142–144 Google Scholar.
73 Schaar, , “Some Ways,” p. 890 Google Scholar.
74 Lukes, pp. 152–153. Italics mine.
75 Ibid., pp. 146, 151, 152.
76 Cf. Schaar, , “Some Ways,” p. 877–879, and the following quotation at p. 893 Google Scholar: “The constitutionalists … have offered a specifically political way of thinking about equality, a way which owes little to observation or to the moral sense. Their everyman is a construct, not an empirical portrait. … We cannot, without vast intellectual confusion and surprising practical consequences, deal with the construct either as an empirical generalization, or as a full guide to the making of public policy, or as an ethical justification for equal treatment.” See also Charvet, , “Individual Identity,” p. 483 Google Scholar; Charvet, , “Idea of Equality,” p. 13 Google Scholar.
77 Zetterbaum, Marvin, “Self and Political Order,” Interpretation, Vol. 1, No. 2 (Spring, 1971), 240–246 Google Scholar. See also, Lukes, pp. 152–153.
78 See the controversy on this point between Strauss, and Kojève, , in Strauss, , On Tyranny, pp. 165–175, 218–221 Google Scholar.
79 Plato, Republic, 472d.
80 Schaar, John H., “Equality of Opportunity, and Beyond,” in Contemporary Political Theory, ed. de Crespigny, Anthony and Wertheimer, Alan (Chicago: Atherton, 1970), p. 151 Google Scholar. Cf. Schaar, , “Some Ways,” p. 877 Google Scholar.
81 Schaar, , “Some Ways,” pp. 891–892 Google Scholar.
82 Ibid., p. 881. But cf. Schaar, , “Equality of Opportunity,” p. 152 Google Scholar.
83 Lukes,p. 132.
84 Buber, Martin, Between Man and Man (New York: Macmillan, 1965), p. 61 Google Scholar.
85 Ibid., p. 62. Cf. Aristotle, Politics, 1261b16-1262a14.
86 Buber, Martin, The Knowledge of Man (New York: Harper Torchbooks, 1965), pp. 72–73 Google Scholar.
87 Lukes, p. 153.
88 Ibid., p. 146.
89 Idem.
90 Schaar, , “Equality of Opportunity,” p. 152 Google Scholar.
- 2
- Cited by
Comments
No Comments have been published for this article.