Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-rcrh6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-24T17:06:39.209Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The U.S. Health Delivery System: Inefficient and Unfair to Children

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  24 February 2021

Loretta M. Kopelman
Affiliation:
Department of Medical Humanities, East Carolina University, Greenville, N.C.27858
Michael G. Palumbo
Affiliation:
Department of Economics, University of Houston, Houston, Texas, 77204-5882

Extract

What proportion of health care resources should go to programs likely to benefit older citizens, such as treatments for Alzheimer’s disease and hip replacements, and what share should be given to programs likely to benefit the young, such as prenatal and neonatal care? What portion should go to rare but severe diseases that plague the few, or to common, easily correctable illnesses that afflict the many? What percentage of funds should go to research, rehabilitation or to intensive care? Many nations have made such hard choices about how to use their limited funds for health care by explicitly setting priorities based on their social commitments. In the United States, however, allocation of health care resources has largely been left to personal choice and market forces. Although the United States spends around 14% of its gross national product (GNP) on health care, the United States and South Africa are the only two industrialized countries that fail to provide citizens with universal access.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © American Society of Law, Medicine and Ethics and Boston University 1997

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 See Brock, Dan W., Some Unresolved Ethical Issues in Priority Setting of Mental Health Services, in What Price Mental Health? the Ethics and Priority of Setting of Mental Health Services 216, 216 (Boyle, P.J. & Callahan, Daniel eds., 1995)Google Scholar; Kilner, John F., Allocation of Health-Care Resources, in Encyclopedia of Bioethics 1067, 1067 (Reich, Warren Thomas ed., 1995)Google Scholar.

2 See Kilner, supra note 1, at 1067 (stating that the U.S.’s allocation decisions result from mil lions of individual clinical decisions and various market forces).

3 See Maynard, Alan & Bloor, Karen, Introducing a Market to the United Kingdom’s National Health Service, 334 New Eng. J. Med. 604, 604 (1996)CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed (displaying bar chart showing that United States spends 13.8% of GNP on health care).

4 See Brock, supra note 1, at 216.

5 See Maynard & Bloor, supra note 3, at 604 (stating that the United Kingdom’s health care system “provides universal access" and displaying bar chart showing that the United Kingdom spends 7.1% of GNP on health care).

6 See id. (displaying Canada’s percentage of GNP spent on health care). Maynard and Bloor also point out that Australia and Germany spend approximately 8.5% of their respective GNPs on health care. See id. France spends just over nine percent of its GNP on health care. See id.

7 See McDonough, John E. et al., Health Care Reform Stages a Comeback in Massachusetts, 336 New Eng. J. Med. 148, 148 (1997)CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed (stating that over 40 million Americans lack health insur ance).

8 See Kogan, Michael D. et al., The Effect of Gaps in Health Insurance on Continuity of a Regular Source of Care Among Preschool-Aged Children in the United States, 274 JAMA 1429, 1429 (1995)CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed (stating that “between 9 million and 10 million" children under 18 years of age are uninsured).

9 See id. (stating that roughly one quarter of U.S. children under three years old were without health insurance for at least one month).

10 See McDonough et al., supra note 7, at 149.

11 See Budetti, Peter P., Health Reform for the 21st Century? It May Have to Wait Until the 21st Century, 277 JAMA 193, 194 (1997)CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

12 See Standing up for Children, Consumer Rep., June 1996, at 9, 9Google Scholar.

13 See Berman, Steven, An Unintended Consequence of Health Care System Reform Efforts, 274 JAMA 1472, 1472CrossRefGoogle Scholar(stating that over three million children lost private insurance coverage between 1991 and 1993); Kogan et al., supra note 8, at 1429 (stating that between nine and ten million chil dren under 18 years of age have no insurance).

14 See Starfleld, Barbara, Childhood Morbidity: Comparisons, Clusters, and Trends, 88 Pe Diatrics 519, 522 (1991)Google Scholar (citing statistics that the United States has the highest rate of deaths in female children among Australia, Canada, Great Britain, Japan, Netherlands and Sweden).

15 See Standing up for Children, supra note 12, at 9.

16 See Starfield, supra note 14, at 521 (stating that low-income children are two to three times more likely to be of low birth weight).

17 See Berman, supra note 13, at 1472-73 (explaining that having a gap in insurance coverage affects access to and quality of needed medical care).

18 See id. (stating that children without a regular source of care, presumably caused by lack of health insurance, have higher rates for illness care).

19 See Starfield, Barbara, Child Health and Public Policy, in Children and Health care: Moral and Social Issues 7, 9 (Kopelman, Loretta M. & Moskop, John C. eds., 1989)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Starfield, supra note 14, at 521.

20 See Starfield, supra note 14, at 519-22.

21 See Budetti, supra note 11, at 193.

22 See id. at 194.

23 See McDonough et al., supra note 7, at 149.

24 Budetti, supra note 11, at 194.

25 HUME, DAVID, Enquiries Concerning the Human Understanding and Concerning the Principles of Morals 183-92 (Bigge, L.A. Seiby- ed., 2d ed. 1966)Google Scholar. These two conditions are not sufficient, but only necessary, because any just scheme must take into account such contingent fea tures as social resources and priorities.

26 See id.

27 See id.

28 See id. at 188. Hume called justice the cautious, jealous virtue because it was not based solely on the good heart, but concerns that all are treated impartially. See id. at 183-84. As we get to know the parties involved, and become interested rather than disinterested, we tend to lose our impartiality. See id. at 185-86.

29 See id. at 192-204.

30 See G.A. Res. 1386 U.N. GAOR, 14th Sess., Supp. No. 16, at 19, U.N. Doc. A/4354 (1959).

31 See Loretta M. Kopelman, Children: Health-Care and Research Issues, in ENCYCLOPEDIA OF BlOETHICS, supra note 1, at 357, 363-67.

32 There are, of course, other important moral and social values that affect the quality of chil dren’s well-being or opportunities, such as guardians’ duties, rights and choices. Guardians’ authority, however, is not absolute and where guardians endanger children’s well-being or opportunities through abuse or neglect, the state can step in to protect the child. See id. at 358-61.

33 See id. at 363-67. Portions of this section were adapted from this work.

34 See id.

35 For fuller discussion see generally Brock, supra note 1 (discussing ethical issues in mental health care priority setting); Norman Daniels, Rationing Fairly: Programmatic Considerations, 7 bioethics 224 (discussing four fairness problems associated with rationing).

36 See, e.g., Brock, supra note 1, at 216; Kopelman, supra note 31, at 357, 363 (citing Starfield, supra note 19).

37 See Kopelman, supra note 31, at 363 (discussing resource allocation for children’s health).

38 See John Stuart Mill, Utilitarianism 22 (Oskar Post ed., 1957) (1863)Google Scholar. The following is a summary of points made in this work, especially Chapter II, What Utilitarianism Is.

39 See Starfield, supra note 14, at 525.

40 U.S. Dep't Health & human Servs., Pub. no. 91-50212, Healthy People 2000: National Health Promotion and Disease Prevention Objectives 251 (1994)).

41 See Callahan, Daniel, What Kind of Life: the Limits of Medical Progress 202-06, 237-49 (1990)Google Scholar; Callahan, Daniel, Terminating Treatment: Age as a Standard, Hastings Ctr. Rep., Oct./Nov. 1987, at 21, 22-25CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

42 For a fuller discussion see Mckie, John et al., Allocating Healthcare by QALYs: The Rele vance of Age, 5 Cambridge Q. of Healthcare Ethics 534, 535 (1996)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

43 See Kilner, supra note 1, at 1073.

44 See Brock, Dan W., Utilitarianism, in and Justice for all 217, 219 (Regan, Tom & VanDeVeer, Donald eds., 1982)Google Scholar.

45 See Brock, supra note 1, at 221-23; Kopelman, supra note 31, at 363-64.

46 See Brock, supra note 44, at 219-20.

47 See MILL, supra note 38, at 52-79; Buchanan, Allen, Justice: A Philosophical Review, in Justice and Health Care 3, 4 (Shelp, Earl E. ed., 1981)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

48 See Childress, James F., Who Shall Live When Not All Can Live?, 53 Soundings 339, 348-9 (1970)Google Scholar.

49 See Kopelman, supra note 31, at 364.

50 See id. (citing Veatch, Robert M., The Foundations of Justice: Why the Retarded and the Rest of Us Have Claims to Equality 123-36 (1986)Google Scholar; Childress, supra note 48, at 347- 54).

51 See Kopelman, supra note 31, at 364-65.

52 For further discussion on how they try to do this and criticisms see VEATCH, supra note 50, at 189; Brock, supra note 1, at 221.

53 See Starfield, supra note 14, at 520.

54 See id. at 520-21.

55 See Buchanan, supra note 47, at 10-13.

56 See Kopelman, supra note 31, at 365; see also LOCKE, JOHN, Treatise of Civil Government 18-33 (Sherman, C.L. ed., 1937) (1689)Google Scholar; ANARCHY, ROBERT NOZICK, State and Utopia 120-46 (1974)Google Scholar.

57 See Engelhardt, H. Tristram Jr., The Search for a Universal System of Ethics: Post-Modern Disappointments and Contemporary Possibilities, in Ethical Problems in Dialysis and Transplantation 3-19 (Kjellstrand, Carl M. & Dossetor, John B. eds., 1992)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; MORREIM, E. HAAVI, Balancing Act: The New Medical Ethics of Medicine’s New Economics 23 (1991)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

58 See Engelhardt, supra note 57, at 10.

59 See Kopelman, supra note 31, at 365.

60 For example, Part B of Medicare is optional, yet is heavily subsidized with public funds for those who can afford it.

61 See Kopelman, supra note 31, at 366.

62 Rawls, John, A Theory of Justice (1971)Google Scholar [hereinafter rawls, A Theory of Justice].

63 Rawls, John, Political Liberalism (1993)Google Scholar [hereinafter rawls, political liberalism].

64 See RAWLS, A theory of Justice, supra note 62, at 11-12.

65 See rawls, political liberalism, supra note 63, at 291.

66 See Daniels, Norman, Just Health Care 111-12 (1985)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

67 See id. at 41-42 (distinguishing “positive" and “negative" notions of equal opportunity).

68 See id. at 24-26.

69 See Kopelman, supra note 31, at 366; see also Daniels, supra note 66, at 32-35 (discussing disease and opportunity).

70 See VEATCH, supra note 50, at 14.

71 See rawls, political liberalism, supra note 63, at 126. For further discussion in the utilitarian context, see Brock, supra note 1, at 219-21.

72 See DANIELS, supra note 66, at 221-29; Brock, supra note 1, at 217; Daniels, supra note 35, at 228-29.

73 See DANIELS, supra note 66, at 14-15; Brock, supra note 1, at 219-21; Daniels, supra note 35, at 228-29.

74 See Brock, supra note 1, at 218-19; Kilner, supra note 1, at 1073.

75 See generally 1-2 Adam Smith, The Wealth of Nations (Ernest Rhys ed., E.P. Dutton & Co. 1910) (1776).

76 See Samuelson, Paul A., Foundations of Economic Analysis (1947)Google Scholar.

77 Indeed, this proposition, commonly referred to as “The Fundamental Theorem of Welfare Economics,” is one of the basic tenets of neoclassical economic theory. The allocation of resources is said to be (Pareto) efficient if (and only if) improving any member’s welfare necessarily reduces the welfare of any other member of society. Thus, by definition, there does not exist a unanimously preferred allocation to an efficient allocation of resources. See generally id. at 212-17.

This section of the article draws heavily on the seminal work of Arrow, Kenneth J., Uncertainty and the Welfare Economics of Medical Care, 53 Am. Economic Rev. 941 (1963)Google Scholar. We wish to acknowledge Andrew Austin and Chinhui Juhn for valuable comments on a previous draft of this section. A good general introduction to these issues may be found in Rosen, Harvey S., Public Finance 38-54 (1995)Google Scholar.

78 See Arrow, supra note 77, at 941-42.

79 See rosen, supra note 77, at 90-97.

80 See Arrow, supra note 77, at 944.

81 See HUDSON, ROBERT P., Disease and Its Control: the Shaping of Modern Thought at xi, 163 (1983)Google Scholar.

82 See id. at 189-90.

83 See id. at 59.

84 For further discussion of these points, see HUDSON, supra note 81, at 63.

85 See id. at 169-92 (describing how society’s conception of disease dictates public health dis ease prevention measures). “[The] idea developed that society collectively had a special responsi bility ... in the protection of the common health.” Id. at 170-71.

86 See id. "[A] proper blend of governmental intervention and restraint could lead human be ings to do what was best for themselves, individually and collectively.” Id. at 178.

87 See ROSEN, supra note 77, at 94.

88 See id. at 52.

89 Information imperfections and health uncertainties seem equally relevant for the considera tion of child or adult patients, though the rest of our paper focuses on the former group.

90 Arrow, supra note 77, at 951.

91 See id.

92 See id. at 940.

93 For further discussion, see Pellegrino, Edmund D. & Thomasma, David C., The Virtues of Medical Practice 31-48 (1993)Google Scholar.

94 See MORREIM, supra note 57, at 148.

95 Id.

96 See id. at 2.

97 Id. at 144.

98 See Arrow, supra note 77, at 946.

99 See id.

100 See id. at 948-19.

101 The “right price" would be just high enough to earn a competitive profit level for the in surer and just low enough to be a good deal for the consumer. See id. at 969-73 app. (for a proof).

102 Arrow’s analysis actually is much more general than we imply here. See generally id. at 961-64. He describes several additional reasons asymmetric information between insurance provid ers and customers leads to inefficient levels of coverage in equilibrium by recognizing how complex (and, ultimately, infeasible) optimally written policies must be. Here, we simply describe the sim plest case, adverse selection, as an example of asymmetric information in health insurance markets.

103 Additionally, it should be noted, Arrow describes why it is not surprising that the market for health care cannot be considered perfectly competitive. See id. at 947. According to the fundamental welfare theorem, competition is a necessary condition for markets to operate efficiently. See id. at 944.