Published online by Cambridge University Press: 20 November 2018
Debate continues over the Supreme Court's decision in City of Los Angeles Department of Water and Power v. Manhart. As most readers of this article already know, Manhart held illegal an annuity plan in which both sexes would receive equal periodic benefits after retirement although women made larger contributions while working. In collaboration with two colleagues, we defended the decision in another journal.* Although we tried to answer all of Manhart's critics, much of our attention was devoted to our colleague Spencer Kimball, who had published the most thorough and powerful of the attacks on Manhart. He has now published a reply.4 In the interests of having the main arguments on both sides summarized in the same journal, and of correcting misimpressions about the nature and extent of our argument, we offer this comment.
1 435 U.S. 702 (1978).Google Scholar
2 Brilmayer, Lea, Hekeler, Richard W., Laycock, Douglas, & Sullivan, Teresa A., Sex Discrimination in Employer-sponsored Insurance Plans; A Legal and Demographic Analysis, 47 U. Chi. L. Rev. 505 (1980).Google Scholar
3 Kimball, Spencer L., Reverse Sex Discrimination: Manhart, 1979 A.B.F. Res. J. 83.Google Scholar
4 Kimball, Spencer L., Reprise on Manhart, 1980 A.B.F. Res. J. 915.Google Scholar
5 Brilmayer et al., supra note 2, at 508.Google Scholar
6 Id. at 508–23.Google Scholar
7 Id. at 508–11.Google Scholar
8 Id. at 511.Google Scholar
9 Id. at 522–23.Google Scholar
10 Id. at 514–22.Google Scholar
11 Id. at 524–39.Google Scholar
12 Id. at 524–26.Google Scholar
13 Id. at 526, 526–35.Google Scholar
14 Id. at 528–29.Google Scholar
15 Id. at 526–34. Thus, we relied on the long history of sex discrimination only to explain why the statutory policy against sex discrimination is so strong and admits of so few exceptions. We did not “point to the disabilities under which women have suffered historically as a reason for favoring them now,” as Kimball charges. Kimball, supra note 4, at 920.Google Scholar
16 Brilmayer et al., supra note 2, at 533–34.Google Scholar
17 Id. at 534.Google Scholar
18 Kimball, supra note 4, at 918.Google Scholar
19 Id.Google Scholar
20 Id.Google Scholar
21 Id.Google Scholar
22 Brilmayer et al., supra note 2, at 516–17.Google Scholar
23 Id. at 516.Google Scholar
24 Kimball, supra note 4, at 918.Google Scholar
25 Id.Google Scholar
26 See, e.g., Regents of the Univ. of Cal. v. Bakke, 438 U.S. 265, 361 (1978) (Brennan, J., concurring in part).Google Scholar
27 See Kimball, supra note 4, at 915 (characterizing “protecting individuals from disparate treatment” as “the high moral ground,” and “concern about group equality” as the “low ground”). (Emphasis in original.) See also the emphasis on reverse discrimination in the title of Kimball's original article. Kimball, supra note 3, at 83.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
28 See Kimball, supra note 3, at 103–11.Google Scholar
29 Kimball, supra note 4, at 916.Google Scholar
30 Brilmayer et al., supra note 2, at 511 n.26. We originally made this statement to explain the error in Kimball's claim that to consider a person's sex is to treat him more individually than to ignore it. Kimball, supra note 3, at 119. He repeats the claim in his response without acknowledging that we have already discussed it. Kimball, supra note 4, at 916.Google Scholar
31 See the example in Brilmayer et al., supra note 2, at 508.Google Scholar
32 Kimball, supra note 4, at 916.Google Scholar
33 Brilmayer et al., supra note 2, at 513–14.Google Scholar
34 Kimball, supra note 4, at 917.Google Scholar
35 Id.Google Scholar
36 Id.Google Scholar
37 Brilmayer et al., supra note 2, at 512–13.Google Scholar
38 Id. at 513 n.35.Google Scholar
39 Kimball, supra note 4, at 917.Google Scholar
40 See Brilmayer et al., supra note 2, at 513 n.33, 530–33, 539–59.Google Scholar
41 Id. at 513 n.33, 535; Kimball, supra note 3, at 107–8, 118–20.Google Scholar
42 Brilmayer et al., supra note 2, at 542 n.182.Google Scholar
43 Id. at 512.Google Scholar
44 Id. at 507, 532, 538–40.Google Scholar
45 See id. at 539–40 nn.170 & 172 (collecting the literature).Google Scholar
46 Id. at 541.Google Scholar
47 Id. at 542–56.Google Scholar
48 Kimball, supra note 4, at 918–20.Google Scholar
49 Kimball, supra note 3, at 112–13.Google Scholar
50 Kimball, supra note 4, at 919.Google Scholar
51 Id.Google Scholar
52 Differences in mortality rates between the races exceed differences in mortality rates between the sexes in all age groups between 25 and 55. U.S., Department of Health, Education, and Welfare, Public Health Service, National Center for Health Statistics, Vital Statistics of the United States, 1977, vol. 2, § 5: Life Tables at pp. 5–9 to 5–11, table 5–1 (Hyattsville, Md., 1980).Google Scholar
53 Brilmayer et al., supra note 2, at 540.Google Scholar
54 See text at note 17 supra.Google Scholar
55 U.S., Public Health Service, supra note 52, at 5–10 to 5–11.Google Scholar
56 Brilmayer et al., supra note 2, at 540 n.175. Kimball misread this statement, taking it to mean that accurate data would show no race differences at all among the elderly. Kimball, supra note 4, at 919. There is no basis for his assumption about what accurate data would show; it might be that whites would maintain their advantage over blacks at all ages.Google Scholar
57 Brilmayer et al., supra note 2, at 551–59.Google Scholar
58 Kimball, supra note 4, at 919.Google Scholar
59 U.S., Public Health Service, supra note 52, at 5–15.Google Scholar
60 Kimball, supra note 3, at 136.Google Scholar
61 See, e.g., Spirt v. TIAA, 475 F. Supp. 1298, 1316–18 (S.D.N.Y. 1979).Google Scholar
62 See Brilmayer et al., supra note 2, at 558.Google Scholar
63 See, e.g., Peters v. Wayne State Univ., 476 F. Supp. 1343, 1350–51 (E.D. Mich. 1979); Spirt v. TIAA, 475 F. Supp. 1298, 1301–4 (S.D.N.Y. 1979).Google Scholar
64 Kimball, supra note 4, at 917–18.Google Scholar
65 See Kimball, supra note 3, at 92–93 n.27.Google Scholar
66 H.R. 100, 97th Cong., 1st Sess. (1981).Google Scholar