Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-fbnjt Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-06T05:15:13.840Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Coherentism

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  25 August 2022

Erik J. Olsson
Affiliation:
Lunds Universitet, Sweden

Summary

Perhaps the most fundamental question of epistemology asks on what grounds our knowledge of the world ultimately rests. The traditional Cartesian answer is that it rests on indubitable facts arrived at through rational insight or introspection. Coherentists reject this answer, claiming instead that knowledge arises from relations of coherence or mutual support: if our beliefs cohere, we can be sure that they are mostly true. The first part of this Element introduces the reader to the main ideas and problems of coherentism. The next part describes the 'probabilistic turn', leading up to recent demonstrations that coherence fails to be conducive to truth. The final part reassesses the current debate about the proper definition of coherence from the standpoint of Rudolf Carnap's methodology of explication. The upshot is a tentative and qualified defence of one of the early coherence measures.
Get access
Type
Element
Information
Online ISBN: 9781009053327
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication: 08 September 2022

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Akiba, K. (2000), “Shogenji’s Probabilistic Measure of Coherence Is Incoherent,” Analysis, 60 (4): 356359.Google Scholar
Alston, W. P. (1993), “Epistemic Desiderata,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 53 (3): 527551.Google Scholar
Angere, S. (2007), “The Defeasible Nature of Coherentist Justification,” Synthese, 157 (3): 321335.Google Scholar
Angere, S. (2008), “Coherence as a Heuristic,” Mind, 117 (465): 126.Google Scholar
Baumann, P. (2016), Epistemic Contextualism: A Defense, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Blanshard, B. (1939), The Nature of Thought, London: Allen & Unwin.Google Scholar
BonJour, L. (1985), The Structure of Empirical Knowledge, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Bovens, L., and Hartmann, S. (2003), Bayesian Epistemology, Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Bovens, L., and Olsson, E. J. (2000), “Coherentism, Reliability and Bayesian Networks,” Mind, 109 (436): 685719.Google Scholar
Bovens, L., and Olsson, E. J. (2002), “Believing More, Risking Less: On Coherence, Truth and Non-trivial Extensions,” Erkenntnis, 57 (2): 137150.Google Scholar
Bovens, L., Fitelson, B., Hartmann, S., and Snyder, J. (2002), “Too Odd (Not) to Be True? A Reply to Olsson,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 53 (4): 539563.Google Scholar
Carnap, R. (1950), Logical Foundations of Probability, Chicago: Chicago University Press.Google Scholar
Chisholm, R. M. (1977), Theory of Knowledge (2nd ed.), Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.Google Scholar
Coady, C. A. J. (1992), Testimony: A Philosophical Study, Clarendon Press: Oxford.Google Scholar
Cordes, M., and Siegwart, G. (2019), “Explication,” in The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Accessed August 20, 2019 at www.iep.utm.edu/explicat.Google Scholar
Cross, C. B. (1999), “Coherence and Truth Conducive Justification,” Analysis, 59 (3): 186193.Google Scholar
Crupi, V., Tentori, K., and Gonzales, M. (2007), “On Bayesian Measures of Evidential Support: Theoretical and Empirical Issues,” Philosophy of Science, 74 (2): 229252.Google Scholar
Davidson, D. (1986), “A Coherence Theory of Knowledge and Truth,” in Truth and Interpretation, LePore, E. (ed.), Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 307319.Google Scholar
Dietrich, F., and Moretti, L. (2005), “On Coherent Sets and the Transmission of Confirmation,” Philosophy of Science, 72 (3): 403424.Google Scholar
Douven, I., and Meijs, W. (2007), “Measuring Coherence,” Synthese, 156 (3): 405425.Google Scholar
Ewing, A. C. (1934), Idealism: A Critical Survey, London: Methuen.Google Scholar
Fitelson, B. (2003), “A Probabilistic Theory of Coherence,” Analysis, 63 (3): 194199.Google Scholar
Friedman, M. (1974), “Explanation and Scientific Understanding,” The Journal of Philosophy, 11 (1): 519.Google Scholar
Gaifman, H. (1979), “Subjective Probability, Natural Predicates and Hempel’s Ravens,” Erkenntnis, 14 (2): 105147.Google Scholar
Glass, D. H. (2002), “Coherence, Explanation and Bayesian Networks,” in Intelligence, Artificial and Science, Cognitive, O’Neill, M. and Sutcliffe, R. F. E. et al. (eds.) (Lecture Notes in Artificial Intelligence, vol. 2464), Berlin: Springer-Verlag, pp. 177182.Google Scholar
Glass, D. H. (2005), “Problems with Priors in Probabilistic Measures of Coherence,” Erkenntnis, 63 (3): 375385.Google Scholar
Glass, D. H. (2007), “Coherence Measures and Inference to the Best Explanation,” Synthese, 157 (3): 257296.Google Scholar
Goldman, A. I. (1979), “What Is Justified Belief?”, in Justification and Knowledge, Pappas, G. (ed.), Boston: D. Reidel, pp. 125.Google Scholar
Goldman, A. I. (1999), Knowledge in a Social World, New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Good, I. J. (1984), “The Best Explicatum for Weight of Evidence,” Journal of Statistical Computation and Simulation, 19: 294299.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haack, S. (2009), Evidence and Inquiry: A Pragmatist Reconstruction of Epistemology, Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books.Google Scholar
Halbach, V. (2003), “Can We Grasp Consistency?”, in The Epistemology of Lehrer, Keith, Olsson, E. J. (ed.), Philosophical Studies Series, 95, Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, pp. 7587.Google Scholar
Harris, A. J. L., and Hahn, U. (2009), “Bayesian Rationality in Evaluating Multiple Testimonies: Incorporating the Role of Coherence,” Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 35 (5): 13661372.Google Scholar
Hendricks, V. F. (2006), Mainstream and Formal Epistemology, New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hilpinen, R. (1991), “Inquiry, Argumentation and Knowledge,” in The Logic of Theory Change, A. Fuhrmann and M. Morreau (eds.), Lecture Notes in Computer Science (Lecture Notes in Artificial Intelligence), vol. 465. Berlin and Heidelberg: Springer, pp. 118.Google Scholar
Huemer, M. (1997), “Probability and Coherence Justification,” Southern Journal of Philosophy, 35 (4): 463472.Google Scholar
Huemer, M. (2007), “Weak Bayesian Coherentism,” Synthese, 157 (3): 337346.Google Scholar
Huemer, M. (2011), “Does Probability Theory Refute Coherentism?”, Journal of Philosophy, 108 (1): 3554.Google Scholar
Kemeny, J., and Oppenheim, P. (1952), “Degree of Factual Support,” Philosophy of Science, 19 (4): 307324.Google Scholar
Keynes, J. (1921), A Treatise on Probability, London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Klein, P., and Warfield, T. A. (1994), “What Price Coherence?”, Analysis, 54 (3): 129132.Google Scholar
Klein, P., and Warfield, T. A. (1996), “No Help for the Coherentist,” Analysis, 56 (2): 118121.Google Scholar
Kornblith, H. (1989), “The Unattainability of Coherence,” in The Current State of the Coherence Theory, Bender, J. (ed.), Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, pp. 207214.Google Scholar
Koscholke, J. (2013), “Last Measure Standing: Evaluating Test Cases for Probabilistic Coherence Measures,” unpublished manuscript.Google Scholar
Koscholke, J. (2016), “Evaluating Test Cases of Probabilistic Measures of Coherence,” Erkenntnis, 81: 155181.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Koscholke, J., and Jekel, M. (2017), “Probabilistic Coherence Measures: A Psychological Study of Coherence Assessment,” Synthese, published online January 11, 2016, doi: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0996-6.Google Scholar
Koscholke, J., and Schippers, M. (2016), “Against Relative Overlap Measures of Coherence,” Synthese, first online September 15, 2015, doi: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0887-x.Google Scholar
Koscholke, J., Schippers, M., and Stegman, A. (2019), “New Hope for Relative Overlap Measures of Coherence,” Mind, 128 (512): 12611284.Google Scholar
Lehrer, K. (1990), Theory of Knowledge, 1st ed., Boulder, CO: Westview Press.Google Scholar
Lewis, C. I. (1946), An Analysis of Knowledge and Valuation, LaSalle, IL: Open Court.Google Scholar
Lycan, W. G. (1988), Judgment and Justification, New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Lycan, W. G. (2002), “Explanation and Epistemology,” in The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology, Moser, P. K. (ed.), New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 408–433.Google Scholar
Lycan, W. G. (2012), “Explanationist Rebuttals (Coherentism Defended Again),” The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 50 (1): 520.Google Scholar
Meijs, W. (2006), “Coherence as Generalized Logical Equivalence,” Erkenntnis, 64 (2): 231252.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Meijs, W., and Douven, I. (2005), “Bovens and Hartmann on Coherence,” Mind, 114 (454): 355363.Google Scholar
Meijs, W., and Douven, I. (2007), “On the Alleged Impossibility of Coherence,” Synthese, 157 (3): 347360.Google Scholar
Moretti, L. (2007), “Ways in Which Coherence Is Confirmation Conducive,” Synthese, 157 (3): 309319.Google Scholar
Moretti, L., and Akiba, K. (2007), “Probabilistic Measures of Coherence and the Problem of Belief Individuation,” Synthese, 154 (1): 7395.Google Scholar
Nozick, R. (1981), Philosophical Explanations, Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Olsson, E. J. (2001), “Why Coherence Is Not Truth-Conducive,” Analysis, 61 (3): 236241.Google Scholar
Olsson, E. J. (2002a), “Corroborating Testimony, Probability and Surprise,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 53 (2): 273288.Google Scholar
Olsson, E. J. (2002b), “Corroborating Testimony and Ignorance: A Reply to Bovens, Fitelson, Hartmann and Snyder,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 53 (4): 565572.Google Scholar
Olsson, E. J. (2002c), “What Is the Problem of Coherence and Truth?”, The Journal of Philosophy, 99 (5): 246272.Google Scholar
Olsson, E. J. (2005), Against Coherence: Truth, Probability, and Justification, Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Olsson, E. J. (2015), “Gettier and the Method of Explication: a 60 Year Old Solution to a 50 Year Old Problem,” Philosophical Studies 172 (1), 1: 5772.Google Scholar
Olsson, E. J. (2017a), “Explicationist Epistemology and Epistemic Pluralism,” in Pluralism, Epistemic, Coliva, A. and Pedersen, N. J. L. L. (eds.), Palgrave Macmillian, pp. 2346.Google Scholar
Olsson, E. J. (2017b), “Coherentism,” in Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Memory, Bernecker, S. and Michaelian, K. (eds.), New York: Routledge, pp. 310322.Google Scholar
Olsson, E. J. (2021a), Kunskapsteori: En Historisk och Systematisk Introduktion, Lund: Studentlitteratur AB.Google Scholar
Olsson, E. J. (2021b), “Coherentist Theories of Epistemic Justification,” The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2021 Edition), Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2021/entries/justep-coherence.Google Scholar
Olsson, E. J. (2022), “Hilpinen’s Theory of Inquiry,” in Agency, Norms, Inquiry, and Artifacts: Essays in Honor of Risto Hilpinen, McNamara, P. et al. (eds.), Synthese Library 454, 175191.Google Scholar
Olsson, E. J., and Schubert, S. (2007), “Reliability Conducive Measures of Coherence,” Synthese, 157 (3): 297308.Google Scholar
Pearl, J. (1988), Probabilistic Reasoning in Intelligent Systems: Networks of Plausible Inference, San Francisco: Morgan Kaufmann Publishers.Google Scholar
Popper, K. R. (1954), “Degree of Confirmation,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 5 (18), 143149.Google Scholar
Quine, W. and Ullian, J. (1970), The Web of Belief, New York: Random House.Google Scholar
Rescher, N. (1958), “Theory of Evidence,” Philosophy of Science, 25 (1), 8394.Google Scholar
Rescher, N. (1973), The Coherence Theory of Truth, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Rips, L. J. (2001), “Two Kinds of Reasoning,” Psychological Science, 12 (2), 129134.Google Scholar
Roche, W. (2010), “Coherentism, Truth, and Witness Agreement,” Acta Analytica, 25 (2): 243257.Google Scholar
Roche, W. (2013a), “Coherence and Probability: A Probabilistic Account of Coherence,” In Araszkiewicz, M. & Savelka, J. (eds.), Coherence: Insights from Philosophy, Jurisprudence and Artificial Intelligence (pp. 5991). Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
Roche, W. (2013b), “On the Truth-Conduciveness of Coherence,” Erkenntnis, 79 (S3): 119.Google Scholar
Schippers, M. (2014a), “Probabilistic Measures of Coherence: From Adequacy Constraints Towards Pluralism,” Synthese, 191 (16): 38213845.Google Scholar
Schippers, M. (2014b), “Incoherence and Inconsistency,” Review of Symbolic Logic, 7 (3), 511528.Google Scholar
Schippers, M., and Siebel, M. (2015), “Inconsistency as a Touchstone for Coherence Measures,” Theoria: Revista de Teoria, Historia y Fundamentos de la Ciencia, 30 (1): 1141.Google Scholar
Schubert, S. (2011), “Coherence and Reliability: The Case of Overlapping Testimonies,” Erkenntnis, 74 (2), 263275.Google Scholar
Schubert, S. (2012a), “Coherence Reasoning and Reliability: A Defense of the Shogenji Measure,” Synthese, 187 (2): 305319.Google Scholar
Schubert, S. (2012b), “Is Coherence Conducive to Reliability?”, Synthese, 187(2): 607621.Google Scholar
Schubert, S., and Olsson, E. J. (2013), “Coherence and Reliability in Judicial Reasoning,” in Coherence: Insights from Philosophy, Jurisprudence and Artificial Intelligence, Araszkiewicz, M. and Savelka, J. (eds.), Law and Philosophy Library 107, Springer, pp. 3358.Google Scholar
Schupbach, J. N. (2008), “On the Alleged Impossibility of Bayesian Coherentism,” Philosophical Studies, 141 (3): 323331.Google Scholar
Schupbach, J. N. (2011), “New Hope for Shogenji’s Coherence Measure,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62 (1): 125142.Google Scholar
Shogenji, T. (1999), “Is Coherence Truth-Conducive?,” Analysis, 59 (4): 338345.Google Scholar
Shogenji, T. (2007), “Why Does Coherence Appear Truth-Conducive,” Synthese, 157 (3): 361372.Google Scholar
Shogenji, T. (2012), “The Degree of Epistemic Justification and the Conjunction Fallacy,” Synthese, 184 (1), 2948.Google Scholar
Shogenji, T. (2013), “Coherence of the Contents and the Transmission of Probabilistic Support,” Synthese, 190 (13): 25252545.Google Scholar
Siebel, M. (2004), “On Fitelson’s Measure of Coherence,” Analysis, 64 (2): 189190.Google Scholar
Siebel, M., and Wolff, W. (2008), “Equivalent Testimonies as a Touchstone of Coherence,” Synthese 161 (2), 167182.Google Scholar
Sosa, E. (1980), “The Raft and the Pyramid: Coherence Versus Foundations in the Theory of Knowledge,” Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 5 (1): 326.Google Scholar
Thagard, P. (1989), “Explanatory Coherence,” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3): 435467.Google Scholar
Thagard (2000), Coherence in Thought and Action, Cambridge, MA: The Massachusetts Institute of Technology Press.Google Scholar
Weinberg, J. M., Nischols, S., and Stich, S. (2001), “Normativity and Epistemic Intuitions,” Philosophical Topics 29 (1–2): 429460.Google Scholar

Save element to Kindle

To save this element to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Coherentism
  • Erik J. Olsson, Lunds Universitet, Sweden
  • Online ISBN: 9781009053327
Available formats
×

Save element to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Coherentism
  • Erik J. Olsson, Lunds Universitet, Sweden
  • Online ISBN: 9781009053327
Available formats
×

Save element to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Coherentism
  • Erik J. Olsson, Lunds Universitet, Sweden
  • Online ISBN: 9781009053327
Available formats
×