Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-fbnjt Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-19T02:10:19.114Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Mathematical Anti-Realism and Modal Nothingism

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  02 December 2022

Mark Balaguer
Affiliation:
California State University

Summary

This Element defends mathematical anti-realism against an underappreciated problem with that view-a problem having to do with modal truthmaking. Part I develops mathematical anti-realism, it defends that view against a number of well-known objections, and it raises a less widely discussed objection to anti-realism-an objection based on the fact that (a) mathematical anti-realists need to commit to the truth of certain kinds of modal claims, and (b) it's not clear that the truth of these modal claims is compatible with mathematical anti-realism. Part II considers various strategies that anti-realists might pursue in trying to solve this modal-truth problem with their view, it argues that there's only one viable view that anti-realists can endorse in order to solve the modal-truth problem, and it argues that the view in question-which is here called modal nothingism-is true.
Get access
Type
Element
Information
Online ISBN: 9781009346030
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication: 05 January 2023

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Armstrong, D. (1997) A World of States of Affairs, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Azzouni, J. (2004) Deflating Existential Consequence: A Case for Nominalism, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Azzouni, J. (2010) Talking About Nothing, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Baker, A. (2005) “Are there Genuine Mathematical Explanations of Physical Phenomena?Mind 114: 223–38.Google Scholar
Baker, A. (2009) “Mathematical Explanation in Science,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 60: 611–33.Google Scholar
Balaguer, M. (1995) “A Platonist Epistemology,” Synthese 103: 303–25.Google Scholar
Balaguer, M. (1996) “A Fictionalist Account of the Indispensable Applications of Mathematics,” Philosophical Studies 83: 291314.Google Scholar
Balaguer, M. (1998) Platonism and Anti-Platonism in Mathematics, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Balaguer, M. (2009) “Fictionalism, Theft, and the Story of Mathematics,” Philosophia Mathematica 17: 131–62.Google Scholar
Balaguer, M. (2010) “Fictionalism, Mathematical Facts, and Logical Facts,” in Fictions and Models, Woods, J. (ed.), Munich: Philosophia Verlag, pp. 149–89.Google Scholar
Balaguer, M. (2014) “A Guide for the Perplexed: What Mathematicians Need to Know to Understand Philosophers of Mathematics,” The Mathematical Intelligencer 36: 38.Google Scholar
Balaguer, M. (2016) “Full-Blooded Platonism,” in An Historical Introduction to the Philosophy of Mathematics, Marcus, R. and McEvoy, M. (eds.), London: Bloomsbury Press, pp. 719–32.Google Scholar
Balaguer, M. (2021) Metaphysics, Sophistry, and Illusion: Toward a Widespread Non-Factualism, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Benacerraf, P. (1973) “Mathematical Truth,” Journal of Philosophy 70: 661–79.Google Scholar
Bernstein, S. (2016) “Omission Impossible,” Philosophical Studies 173: 2575–89.Google Scholar
Berto, F., French, R., Priest, G., and Ripley, D. (2018) “Williamson on Counterpossibles,” Journal of Philosophical Logic 47: 693713.Google Scholar
Bjerring, J. C. (2014) “On Counterpossibles,” Philosophical Studies 168: 327–53.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boghossian, P. (1997) “Analyticity,” in A Companion to the Philosophy of Language, Hale, B. and Wright, C. (eds.), Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 331–68.Google Scholar
Brogaard, B. and Salerno, J. (2013) “Remarks on Counterpossibles,” Synthese 190: 639–60.Google Scholar
Brouwer, L. E. J. (1983a [1912]) “Intuitionism and Formalism,” in Philosophy of Mathematics, Benacerraf, P. and Putnam, H. (eds.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 7789.Google Scholar
Brouwer, L. E. J. (1983b [1948]) “Consciousness, Philosophy, and Mathematics,” in Philosophy of Mathematics, Benacerraf, P. and Putnam, H. (eds.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 9096.Google Scholar
Bueno, O. (2005) “Dirac and the Dispensability of Mathematics,” Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 36: 465–90.Google Scholar
Bueno, O. (2009) “Mathematical Fictionalism,” in New Waves in Philosophy of Mathematics, Bueno, O. and Linnebo, Ø. (eds.), Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, pp. 5979.Google Scholar
Bueno, O. and Shalkowski, S. (2009) “Modalism and Logical Pluralism,” Mind 118: 295321.Google Scholar
Cameron, R. (2009a) “What’s Metaphysical about Metaphysical Necessity?Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 79: 116.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cameron, R. (2009b) “Truthmakers and Modality,” Synthese 164: 261–80.Google Scholar
Chihara, C. (1990) Constructibility and Mathematical Existence, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Colyvan, M. (2001) The Indispensability of Mathematics, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dodd, J. (2002) “Is Truth Supervenient on Being,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 102: 6985.Google Scholar
Dorr, C. (2008) “There Are No Abstract Objects,” in Contemporary Debates in Metaphysics, Sider, T., Hawthorne, J., and Zimmerman, D. (eds.), Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 1264.Google Scholar
Field, H. (1980) Science without Numbers, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Field, H. (1989) Realism, Mathematics, and Modality, Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Field, H. (1998) “Mathematical Objectivity and Mathematical Objects,” in Contemporary Readings in the Foundations of Metaphysics, MacDonald, C. and Laurence, S. (eds.), Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 387403.Google Scholar
Fine, K. (1994) “Essence and Modality: The Second Philosophical Perspectives Lecture,” Philosophical Perspectives 8: 116.Google Scholar
Fine, K. (2005) Modality and Tense, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Forbes, G. (1985) The Metaphysics of Modality, Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Forbes, G. (1989) Languages of Possibility, Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Frege, G. (1953 [1884]) The Foundations of Arithmetic, J. L. Austin (trans.), Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Frege, G. (1964 [1893–1903]) The Basic Laws of Arithmetic, M. Furth (trans.), Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Frege, G. (1980) Philosophical and Mathematical Correspondence, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Gödel, K. (1983 [1964]) “What Is Cantor’s Continuum Problem?” in Philosophy of Mathematics, Benacerraf, P. and Putnam, H. (eds.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 470–85.Google Scholar
Hellman, G. (1989) Mathematics Without Numbers, Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Heyting, A. (1956) Intuitionism, Amsterdam: North-Holland.Google Scholar
Hilbert, D. (1959 [1899]) Foundations of Geometry, E. Townsend (trans.), La Salle, IL: Open Court.Google Scholar
Hofweber, T. (2005) “Number Determiners, Numbers, and Arithmetic,” Philosophical Review 114: 179225.Google Scholar
Horgan, T. (1984) “Science Nominalized,” Philosophy of Science 51: 529–49.Google Scholar
Kitcher, P. (1984) The Nature of Mathematical Knowledge, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kripke, S. (1980) Naming and Necessity, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Leng, M. (2010) Mathematics and Reality, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. (1986) On the Plurality of Worlds, Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. (1991) Parts of Classes, Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. (1992) “Armstrong on Combinatorial Possibility,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 70: 211–24.Google Scholar
Lewy, C. (1976) Meaning and Modality, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Lowe, E. J. (n.d.) “Metaphysics as the Science of Essence.” Unpublished manuscript.Google Scholar
Ludwig, K. (n.d.) “De Re Necessities.” Unpublished manuscript.Google Scholar
Maddy, P. (1990) Realism in Mathematics, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Mares, E. D. and Fuhrmann, A. (1995) “A Relevant Theory of Conditionals,” Journal of Philosophical Logic 24: 645–65.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Meinong, A. (1904) “Ueber Gegenstandstheorie,” in Untersuchungen zur Gegenstandstheorie und Psychologie, Meinong, A. (ed.), Leipzig: Barth, pp. 151.Google Scholar
Melia, J. (2000) “Weaseling Away the Indispensability Argument,” Mind 109: 455–79.Google Scholar
Mill, J. S. (1843) A System of Logic, London: Longmans, Green, and Company.Google Scholar
Moltmann, F. (2013) “Reference to Numbers in Natural Language,” Philosophical Studies 162: 499536.Google Scholar
Nolan, D. (1997) “Impossible Worlds: A Modest Approach,” Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 38: 535–72.Google Scholar
Parsons, J. (1999) “There Is No ‘Truthmaker’ Argument Against Nominalism,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 77: 325–34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Plantinga, A. (1976) “Actualism and Possible Worlds,” Theoria 42: 139–60.Google Scholar
Priest, G. (2003) “Meinongianism and the Philosophy of Mathematics,” Philosophia Mathematica 11: 315.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Priest, G. (2005) Towards Non-Being, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. (1967) “The Thesis That Mathematics Is Logic,” in Bertrand Russell, Philosopher of the Century, Schoenman, R. (ed.), London: Allen and Unwin, pp. 273303.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. (1971) Philosophy of Logic, New York: Harper and Row.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. (1983 [1967]) “Mathematics without Foundations,” in Philosophy of Mathematics, 2nd ed., Benacerraf, P. and Putnam, H. (eds.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, . pp. 295311.Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. O. (1983 [1936]) “Truth by Convention,” in Philosophy of Mathematics, 2nd ed., Benacerraf, P. and Putnam, H. (eds.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 329–54.Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. O. (1961a [1948]) “On What There Is,” in From a Logical Point of View, 2nd ed., New York: Harper and Row, pp. 119.Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. O. (1961b [1951]) “Two Dogmas of Empiricism,” in From a Logical Point of View, 2nd ed., New York: Harper and Row, pp. 2046.Google Scholar
Rayo, A. (2008) “On Specifying Truth-Conditions,” Philosophical Review 117: 385443.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rayo, A. (2013) The Construction of Logical Space, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Resnik, M. (1980) Frege and the Philosophy of Mathematics, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Resnik, M. (1997) Mathematics as a Science of Patterns, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Rosen, G. (1990) “Modal Fictionalism,” Mind 99: 327–54.Google Scholar
Rosen, G. (2001) “Nominalism, Naturalism, Epistemic Relativism,” in Philosophical Topics XV (Metaphysics), Tomberlin, J. (ed.), Malden, MA: Blackwell, pp. 6091.Google Scholar
Routley, R. (1980) Exploring Meinong’s Jungle and Beyond, Canberra: RSSS, Australian National University.Google Scholar
Russell, B. (1903) Principles of Mathematics, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Shalkowski, S. (1994) “The Ontological Ground of Alethic Modality,” Philosophical Review 103: 669–88.Google Scholar
Shapiro, S. (1997) Philosophy of Mathematics: Structure and Ontology, New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sidelle, A. (1989) Necessity, Essence, and Individuation, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Sider, T. (2003) “Reductive Theories of Modality,” in The Oxford Handbook of Metaphysics, Loux, M. and Zimmerman, D. (eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 180208.Google Scholar
Sider, T. (2011) Writing the Book of the World, Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Stalnaker, R. (1976) “Possible Worlds,” Nous 10: 6575.Google Scholar
Strawson, P. F. (1950) “On Referring,” Mind 59: 320–44.Google Scholar
Tallant, J. (2009) “Ontological Cheats Might Just Prosper,” Analysis 69: 422–30.Google Scholar
Thomasson, A. (2009) “Non-Descriptivism about Modality: A Brief History and Revival,” Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic, and Communication 4: 126.Google Scholar
Thomasson, A. (2020) Norms and Necessity, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Vetter, B. (2018) Potentiality: From Dispositions to Modality, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Warren, J. (2015) “The Possibility of Truth by Convention,” Philosophical Quarterly 65: 8493.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williamson, T. (2007) The Philosophy of Philosophy, Oxford: Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. (1956) Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics, Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Yablo, S. (2002a) “Go Figure: A Path Through Fictionalism,” Midwest Studies in Philosophy 25: 72102.Google Scholar
Yablo, S. (2002b) “Abstract Objects: A Case Study,” Noûs 36 (Supplementary Volume 1): 220–40.Google Scholar
Yablo, S. (2005) “The Myth of the Seven,” in Fictionalism in Metaphysics, Kalderon, M. (ed.), New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 88115.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Yablo, S. (2017) “If-Thenism,” Australasian Philosophical Review 1: 115–32.Google Scholar
Zalta, E. (1999) “Natural Numbers and Natural Cardinals as Abstract Objects: A Partial Reconstruction of Frege’s Grundgesetze in Object Theory,” Journal of Philosophical Logic 28: 619–60.Google Scholar

Save element to Kindle

To save this element to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Mathematical Anti-Realism and Modal Nothingism
  • Mark Balaguer, California State University
  • Online ISBN: 9781009346030
Available formats
×

Save element to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Mathematical Anti-Realism and Modal Nothingism
  • Mark Balaguer, California State University
  • Online ISBN: 9781009346030
Available formats
×

Save element to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Mathematical Anti-Realism and Modal Nothingism
  • Mark Balaguer, California State University
  • Online ISBN: 9781009346030
Available formats
×