Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-l7hp2 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-29T10:04:22.512Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Laws of Nature

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 March 2023

Tyler Hildebrand
Affiliation:
Dalhousie University, Nova Scotia

Summary

This Element provides an opinionated introduction to the metaphysics of laws of nature. The first section distinguishes between scientific and philosophical questions about laws and describes some criteria for a philosophical account of laws. Subsequent sections explore the leading philosophical theories in detail, reviewing the most influential arguments in the literature. The final few sections assess the state of the field and suggest avenues for future research.
Get access
Type
Element
Information
Online ISBN: 9781009109949
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication: 16 March 2023

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Adams, D. (2018). God and dispositional essentialism: An account of the laws of nature. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 99(2), 293316.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Adlam, E. (2022). Laws of nature as constraints. Foundations of Physics, 52(28), 141.Google Scholar
Anjum, R. L., & Mumford, S. (2018). What tends to be: The philosophy of dispositional modality. London and New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Anscombe, G. (1971). Causality and determination. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Aquinas, . (1972). De veritate. An Aquinas reader (Clark, M., Ed.). New York: Fordham University Press.Google Scholar
Armstrong, D. (1983). What is a law of nature? Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Armstrong, D. (1989a). A combinatorial theory of possibility. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Armstrong, D. (1989b). Universals: An opinionated introduction. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.Google Scholar
Armstrong, D. (1997). A world of states of affairs. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barker, S., & Smart, B. (2012). The ultimate argument against dispositional monist accounts of laws. Analysis, 72(4), 714722.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bechtel, W., & Abrahamsen, A. (2005). Explanation: A mechanistic alternative. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biological Sciences, 36, 421441.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beebee, H. (2000). The non-governing conception of laws of nature. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 61(3), 571594.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beebee, H. (2011). Necessary connections and the problem of induction. Noûs, 45(3), 504527.Google Scholar
Bhogal, H. (2020a). Humeanism about laws of nature. Philosophy Compass, 15(8), 110.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bhogal, H. (2020b). Nomothetic explanation and Humeanism about laws of nature. In Bennett, K. & Zimmerman, D. (Eds.), Oxford studies in metaphysics (Vol. 12, pp. 164202). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Bhogal, H., & Perry, Z. (2017). What the Humean should say about entanglement. Noûs, 51(1), 7494.Google Scholar
Bigelow, J., Ellis, B., & Lierse, C. (1992). The world as one of a kind: Natural necessity and laws of nature. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 43(3), 371388.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bird, A. (2005). The ultimate argument against Armstrong’s contingent necessitation view of laws. Analysis, 65, 147155.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bird, A. (2007). Nature’s metaphysics: Laws and properties. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Bird, A. (2018). The metaphysics of natural kinds. Synthese, 195, 13971426.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bird, A., & Hawley, K. (2011). What are natural kinds? Philosophical Perspectives, 25(1), 205221.Google Scholar
BonJour, L. (1998). In defense of pure reason. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Braddon-Mitchell, D. (2001). Lossy laws. Noûs, 35(2), 260277.Google Scholar
Bricker, P. (2020). Realism without parochialism. In Modal matters: Essays in metaphysics (pp. 4076). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Briggs, R. (2009). The anatomy of the big bad bug. Noûs, 43(3), 428449.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carroll, J. (1994). Laws of nature. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Cartwright, N. (1999). The dappled world: Boundaries of science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Casullo, A. (2003). A priori justification. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Chakravartty, A. (2007). A metaphysics for scientific realism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chakravartty, A. (2017). Scientific ontology: Integrating naturalized metaphysics and voluntarist epistemology. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Chen, E. K. (in press). The past hypothesis and the nature of physical laws. In Loewer, B., Winsberg, E., & Weslake, B. (Eds.), Time’s arrows and the probability structure of the world. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Chen, E. K., & Goldstein, S. (2022). Governing without a fundamental direction of time: Minimal primitivism about laws of nature. In Ben-Menahem, Y. (Ed.), Rethinking laws of nature (pp. 2164). Cham: Springer.Google Scholar
Coates, A. (2020). Making sense of powerful qualities. Synthese, 198(9), 83478363.Google Scholar
Coates, A. (2021). Essence and the inference problem. Synthese, 198, 915931.Google Scholar
Coates, A. (2022). Tropes, unmanifested dispositions, and powerful qualities. Erkenntnis, 87, 21432160.Google Scholar
Coates, A. (in press). The primitivist response to the inference problem. Dialectica.Google Scholar
Cohen, J., & Callender, C. (2009). A better best system account of lawhood. Philosophical Studies, 145, 134.Google Scholar
Collins, R. (2009). God and the laws of nature. Philo, 12(2), 142171.Google Scholar
Cowling, S. (2017). Abstract entities. New York: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dasgupta, S. (2016). Metaphysical rationalism. Noûs, 50(2), 379418.Google Scholar
Dasgupta, S. (2018). Realism and the absence of value. Philosophical Review, 127(3), 279322.Google Scholar
Demarest, H. (2016). Fundamental properties and the laws of nature. Philosophy Compass, 10(5), 334344.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Demarest, H. (2017). Powerful properties, powerless laws. In Jacobs, J. (Ed.), Causal powers (pp. 3853). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Descartes, R. (1984). The philosophical writings of Descartes (Vol. 3; Cottingham, J., Stoothoff, R., Murdoch, D., & Kenny, A., Eds.). New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Dolbeault, J. (2017). Laws of nature of panpsychism. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 24, 87110.Google Scholar
Dorst, C. (2018). Toward a best predictive system account of laws of nature. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science https://doi.org/10.1093/bjps/axy016.Google Scholar
Dorst, C. (2022). Why do the laws support counterfactuals? Erkenntnis, 87(2), 545566.Google Scholar
Dosanjh, R. (2021). Laws of nature and individuals. Philosophy, 96(1), 4972.Google Scholar
Draper, P. (2017). God, evil, and the nature of light. In Meister, C. & Moser, P. K. (Eds.), The Cambridge companion to the problem of evil (pp. 6984). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Dretske, F. (1977). Laws of nature. Philosophy of Science, 44(2), 248268.Google Scholar
Drewery, A. (2005). Essentialism and the necessity of the laws of nature. Synthese, 144, 381396.Google Scholar
Dumsday, T. (2013). Laws of nature don’t have ceteris paribus clauses, they are ceteris paribus clauses. Ratio, 26(2), 134147.Google Scholar
Dumsday, T. (2019). Dispositionalism and the metaphysics of science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Earman, J., & Roberts, J. (1999). Ceteris paribus, there is no problem of provisos. Synthese, 118, 439478.Google Scholar
Earman, J., & Roberts, J. T. (2005a). Contact with the nomic: A challenge for deniers of Humean supervenience about laws of nature. Part I: Humean supervenience. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 71(1), 122.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Earman, J., & Roberts, J. T. (2005b). Contact with the nomic: A challenge for deniers of Humean supervenience about laws of nature. Part II: The epistemological argument for Humean supervenience. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 71(2), 253286.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eddon, M., & Meacham, C. (2015). No work for a theory of universals. In Loewer, B. & Schaffer, J. (Eds.), A companion to David Lewis (pp. 116137). Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
Ellis, B. (2001). Scientific essentialism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Emery, N. (2017). A naturalist’s guide to objective chance. Philosophy of Science, 84, 480499.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Emery, N. (2019). Laws and their instances. Philosophical Studies, 176(6), 15351561.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fales, E. (1990). Causation and universals. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Fernandes, A. (in press). Naturalism, functionalism and chance: Not a best fit for the Humean. In Hicks, M., Jaag, S., & Loew, C. (Eds.), Humean laws for human agents. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Filomeno, A. (2019). Are non-accidental regularities a cosmic coincidence? Revisiting a central threat to Humean laws. Synthese. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02397-1.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Foster, J. (2004). The divine lawmaker. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
French, S. (2014). The structure of the world: Metaphysics and representation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Friend, T. (2022). The Humean pragmatic turn and the case for revisionary best systems accounts. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 72(11), 126.Google Scholar
Friend, T. (in press). How to be a Humean about symmetries. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science.Google Scholar
Goodman, N. (1955). Fact, fiction, and forecast. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Hàjek, A. (2019). Interpretations of probability. In Zalta, E. N. (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Fall 2019 ed.). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2019/entries/probability-interpret/.Google Scholar
Hall, N. (2004). Two mistakes about credence and chance. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 82, 93111.Google Scholar
Hall, N. (2015). Humean reductionism about laws of nature. In Loewer, B. & Schaffer, J. (Eds.), A companion to David Lewis (pp. 262277). Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hattab, H. (2018). Early modern roots of the philosophical concept of a law of nature. In Ott, W. & Patton, L. (Eds.), Laws of nature (pp. 1841). New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Heil, J. (2003). From an ontological point of view. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hicks, M. T. (2018). Dynamic Humeanism. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 69(4), 9831007.Google Scholar
Hicks, M. T. (2019). What everyone should say about symmetries. Philosophy of Science, 86(5), 12841294.Google Scholar
Hicks, M. T. (2021). Breaking the explanatory circle. Philosophical Studies, 178(2), 533557.Google Scholar
Hicks, M. T., & Schaffer, J. (2017). Derivative properties in fundamental laws. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 68, 411450.Google Scholar
Hicks, M. T., & van Elswyk, P. (2015). Humean laws and circular explanation. Philosophical Studies, 172(2), 433443.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hildebrand, T. (2013). Can primitive laws explain? Philosophers’ Imprint, 13(15), 115.Google Scholar
Hildebrand, T. (2016). Two types of quidditism. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 94(3), 516532.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hildebrand, T. (2018). Natural properties, necessary connections, and the problem of induction. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 96(3), 668689.Google Scholar
Hildebrand, T. (2019a). Naturalness constraints on best systems accounts of laws. Ratio, 32(3), 163172.Google Scholar
Hildebrand, T. (2019b). Scientific practice and the epistemology of governing laws. Journal of the American Philosophical Association, 5(2), 174188.Google Scholar
Hildebrand, T. (2020a). Individuation and explanation: A problem for dispositionalism. Philosophical Studies, 177, 38633883.Google Scholar
Hildebrand, T. (2020b). Non-Humean theories of natural necessity. Philosophy Compass, 15(5), 114.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hildebrand, T. (2020c). Platonic laws of nature. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 50(3), 365381.Google Scholar
Hildebrand, T., & Metcalf, T. (2022). The nomological argument for the existence of God. Noûs, 56, 443472. https://doi.org/10.1111/nous.12364.Google Scholar
Hoffman, J., & Rosenkrantz, G. (2022). Omnipotence. In Zalta, E. N. (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2022 ed.). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2022/entries/omnipotence/.Google Scholar
Huemer, M. (2017). There is no pure empirical reasoning. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 93(3), 592613.Google Scholar
Hume, D. (1748/2000). An enquiry concerning human understanding: Critical edition (Beauchamp, Tom L., Ed.). Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Ioannidis, S., Livianos, V., & Psillos, S. (2021). No laws and (thin) powers in, no (governing) laws out. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 11(6), 126.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ismael, J. (2015). How to be Humean. In Loewer, B. & Schaffer, J. (Eds.), A companion to David Lewis (pp. 188205). Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jaag, S., & Loew, C. (2018). Making best systems Best for Us. Synthese. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-1829-1.Google Scholar
Jacobs, J. (2011). Powerful qualities, not pure powers. The Monist, 94(1), 81102.Google Scholar
Jenkins, C. (2008). A priori knowledge: Debates and developments. Philosophy Compass, 3(3), 436450.Google Scholar
Keinanen, M., & Tahko, T. (2019). Bundle theory with kinds. The Philosophical Quarterly, 69(277), 838857.Google Scholar
Kimpton-Nye, S. (2017). Humean laws in an unHumean world. Journal of the American Philosophical Association, 3(2), 129147.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kimpton-Nye, S. (2021). Reconsidering the dispositional essentialist canon. Philosophical Studies, 178, 34213441.Google Scholar
Kistler, M. (2006). Causation and laws of nature. London and New York: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kment, B. (2014). Modality and explanatory reasoning. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Koslicki, K. (2013). Ontological dependence: An opinionated survey. In Schneiter, B., Hoeltje, M., & Steinberg, A. (Eds.), Varieties of dependence: Ontological dependence, grounding, supervenience, response-dependence (basic philosophical concepts) (pp. 3164). Munich: Philosophia Verlag.Google Scholar
Kovacs, D. M. (2020). The oldest solution to the circularity problem for Humeanism about laws of nature. Synthese, 198(9), 121.Google Scholar
Lange, M. (1995). Are there natural laws concerning particular biological species? The Journal of Philosophy, 92(8), 430451.Google Scholar
Lange, M. (2009). Laws and lawmakers. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lange, M. (2013). Grounding, scientific explanation, and Humean laws. Philosophical Studies, 164, 255261.Google Scholar
Lange, M. (2018). Transitivity, self-explanation, and the explanatory circularity argument against Humean accounts of natural law. Synthese, 195(3), 13371353.Google Scholar
Laplace, P.-S. (1814/1999). A philosophical essay on probabilities (Dale, Andrew, Ed. and Trans.). New York: Springer.Google Scholar
Lazarovici, D. (2020). Typical Humean worlds have no laws [preprint]. http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/17469/.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. (1973). Counterfactuals. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. (1983). New work for a theory of universals. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 61(4), 343377.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. (1986a). On the plurality of worlds. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. (1986b). Philosophical papers (Vol. 2). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. (1994). Humean supervenience debugged. Mind, 412, 473490.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. (1999). Papers in metaphysics and epistemology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Locke, J. (1689/1975). The Clarendon edition of the works of John Locke: An essay concerning human understanding Nidditch, P. H. (, Ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Loewer, B. (1996). Humean supervenience. Philosophical Topics, 24, 101127.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Loewer, B. (2007). Laws and natural properties. Philosophical Topics, 35(1–2), 313328.Google Scholar
Loewer, B. (2021). The package deal account of laws and properties (PDA). Synthese, 199, 10651089.Google Scholar
Lowe, E. (1989). Kinds of being. New York: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Lowe, E. (2006). The four-category ontology. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Manson, N. A. (2009). The fine-tuning argument. Philosophy Compass, 4(1), 271286.Google Scholar
Maudlin, T. (2007). The metaphysics within physics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
McKenzie, K. (2022). Fundamentality and grounding. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Mellor, D. (2005). Probability: A philosophical introduction. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Mill, J. S. (1875/1987). A system of logic. London: Longmans.Google Scholar
Miller, E. (2015). Humean scientific explanation. Philosophical Studies, 172(5), 13111332.Google Scholar
Mitchell, S. D. (2000). Dimensions of scientific law. Philosophy of Science, 67(2), 242265.Google Scholar
Molnar, G. (1969). Kneale’s argument revisited. The Philosophical Review, 78(1), 7989.Google Scholar
Molnar, G. (2003). Powers: A study in metaphysics (Mumford, S., Ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Mumford, S. (2004). Laws in nature. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Newton, I. (2014). Philosophical writings: Revised edition (Janiak, A., Ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Oderberg, D. S. (2007). Real essentialism. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Ott, W. (2009). Causation and laws of nature in early modern philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Ott, W., & Patton, L. (2018). Intuitions and assumptions in the debate over laws of nature. In Ott, W. & Patton, L. (Eds.), Laws of nature (pp. 117). New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Paul, L. A. (2012). Metaphysics as modeling: The handmaiden’s tale. Philosophical Studies, 160(1), 129.Google Scholar
Psillos, S. (2018). Laws and powers in the Frame of Nature. In Ott, W. & Patton, L. (Eds.), Laws of nature (pp. 80107). New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Quine, W. (1948). On what there is. Review of Metaphysics, 2, 2138.Google Scholar
Quine, W. (1951). Two dogmas of empiricism. The Philosophical Review, 60, 2043.Google Scholar
Ramsey, F. (1978). Universals of law and of fact. In Mellor, D. (Ed.), Foundations, (pp. 128132). London and Henley: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Raven, M. (2015). Ground. Philosophy Compass, 10(5), 322333.Google Scholar
Reutlinger, A., Schurz, G., Hüttemann, A., & Jaag, S. (2021). Ceteris Paribus laws. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Fall 2021 ed.). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2021/entries/ceteris-paribus/.Google Scholar
Roberts, J. (2008). The law-governed universe. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Rodriguez-Pereyra, G. (2002). Resemblance nominalism. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Ruby, J. E. (1986). The origins of scientific “law.Journal of the History of Ideas, 47(3), 341359.Google Scholar
Sánchez, V. G. (in press). From nomic Humeanism to normative relativism. Philosophical Perspectives.Google Scholar
Schaffer, J. (2016). It is the business of laws to govern. Dialectica, 70(4), 577588.Google Scholar
Schrenk, M. (2006). A theory for special science laws. In Bohse, H. & Walter, S. (Eds.), Selected papers contributed to the sections of gap 6, sixth international conference for the society of analytical philosophy. Paderborn: Mentis.Google Scholar
Schrenk, M. (2010). The powerlessness of necessity. Noûs, 44(4), 725739.Google Scholar
Schrenk, M. (2017). The emergence of better best system laws. Journal for the General Philosophy of Science, 48, 469483.Google Scholar
Schurz, G. (2011). Review of Nature’s Metaphysics: Laws and Properties. Erkenntnis, 74, 137142.Google Scholar
Segal, A. (2020). Humeanisms: Metaphysical and epistemological. Synthese, 199(1–2), 905925.Google Scholar
Sellars, W. (1956). Empiricism and the philosophy of mind. In Feigl, H. & Scriven, M. (Eds.), Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science (Vol. 1, pp. 253329). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Shoemaker, S. (1980). Causality and properties. In van Inwagen, P. (Ed.), Time and cause. Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing.Google Scholar
Shumener, E. (2019). Laws of nature, explanation, and semantic circularity. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 70(3), 787815.Google Scholar
Shumener, E. (in press). The power to govern. Philosophical Perspectives.Google Scholar
Sider, T. (2011). Writing the book of the world. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Skow, B. (2016). Reasons why. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Stanford, K. (2021). Underdetermination of scientific theory. In Zalta, E. N. (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Winter 2021 ed.). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2021/entries/scientific-underdetermination/.Google Scholar
Strawson, G. (1989). The secret connexion: Causation, realism, and David Hume. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Strawson, G. (2015). Humeanism. Journal of the American Philosophical Association, 1(1), 96102.Google Scholar
Swinburne, R. (2006). Relations between universals, or divine laws? Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 84(2), 179189.Google Scholar
Swoyer, C. (1982). The nature of natural laws. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 60(3), 203223.Google Scholar
Tahko, T. (2015). An introduction to metametaphysics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Tahko, T. (2021). Unity of science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Tan, P. (2020). Ideal laws, counterfactual preservation, and the analyses of lawhood. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 98(3), 574589.Google Scholar
Tooley, M. (1977). The nature of laws. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 7(4), 667698.Google Scholar
Tooley, M. (2011). The skeptical challenges of Hume and Berkeley: Can they be answered? Proceedings of the American Philosophical Association, 85(2), 2746.Google Scholar
Tugby, M. (2013a). Graph-theoretic models of dispositional structures. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 27(1), 2339.Google Scholar
Tugby, M. (2013b). Platonic dispositionalism. Mind, 122(486), 451480.Google Scholar
Tugby, M. (2017). The problem of retention. Synthese, 194(6), 20532075.Google Scholar
Tugby, M. (2021). Grounding theories of powers. Synthese, 198(12), 1118711216.Google Scholar
van Cleve, J. (2018). Brute necessity. Philosophy Compass, 13, 143.Google Scholar
van Fraassen, B. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
van Fraassen, B. (1989). Laws and symmetry. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vetter, B. (2009). Review of Nature’s Metaphysics: Laws and Properties. Logical Analysis and History of Philosophy, 12, 320328.Google Scholar
Vetter, B. (2012). Dispositional essentialism and the laws of nature. In Bird, A., Ellis, B., & Sankey, H. (Eds.), Properties, powers, and structures: Issues in the metaphysics of realism. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Vogt, L. (2022). Nominalist dispositional essentialism. Synthese, 200(156), 129.Google Scholar
Wang, J. (2016). The nature of properties: Causal essentialism. Philosophy Compass, 11(3), 168176.Google Scholar
Weisberg, J. (2019). Odds and ends: Introducing probability and decision theory with a visual emphasis. https://jonathanweisberg.org/vip/.Google Scholar
Whittle, A. (2009). Causal nominalism. In Handfield, T. (Ed.), Dispositions and causes (pp. 242285). Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Williams, N. (2019). The powers metaphysic. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Wilsch, T. (2021). Governing laws of nature: Guidance and production. Philosophical Studies, 178(3), 909933.Google Scholar
Wilson, J. (2010). What is Hume’s dictum, and why believe it? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 80, 595637.Google Scholar
Wilson, M. (1987). What is a law of nature? (book review). The Philosophical Review, 96(3), 435441.Google Scholar
Woodward, J. (2018). Laws: An invariance-based account. In Ott, W. & Patton, L. (Eds.), Laws of nature (pp. 158180). New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

Save element to Kindle

To save this element to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Laws of Nature
  • Tyler Hildebrand, Dalhousie University, Nova Scotia
  • Online ISBN: 9781009109949
Available formats
×

Save element to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Laws of Nature
  • Tyler Hildebrand, Dalhousie University, Nova Scotia
  • Online ISBN: 9781009109949
Available formats
×

Save element to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Laws of Nature
  • Tyler Hildebrand, Dalhousie University, Nova Scotia
  • Online ISBN: 9781009109949
Available formats
×