Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
  • Cited by 57
Publisher:
Cambridge University Press
Online publication date:
October 2012
Print publication year:
2012
Online ISBN:
9781139095167

Book description

Time asymmetric phenomena are successfully predicted by statistical mechanics. Yet the foundations of this theory are surprisingly shaky. Its explanation for the ease of mixing milk with coffee is incomplete, and even implies that un-mixing them should be just as easy. In this book the authors develop a new conceptual foundation for statistical mechanics that addresses this difficulty. Explaining the notions of macrostates, probability, measurement, memory, and the arrow of time in statistical mechanics, they reach the startling conclusion that Maxwell's Demon, the famous perpetuum mobile, is consistent with the fundamental physical laws. Mathematical treatments are avoided where possible, and instead the authors use novel diagrams to illustrate the text. This is a fascinating book for graduate students and researchers interested in the foundations and philosophy of physics.

Reviews

'The Road to Maxwell’s Demon is an exceptionally clear and readable book, intended for readers without physics or philosophy backgrounds. It is also a highly original and important contribution to the foundations of physics. It goes against much of the received wisdom and offers novel solutions to many problems: among them, discussions of time asymmetry in classical mechanics, an empiricist alternative to typicality, a criticism of the role of ergodicity, the notion of a physical observer and the irrelevance of information theory to the foundations of statistical mechanics. Readers interested in the foundations of physics will welcome such a fresh outlook on these topics.'

Amit Hagar Source: Metascience

Refine List

Actions for selected content:

Select all | Deselect all
  • View selected items
  • Export citations
  • Download PDF (zip)
  • Save to Kindle
  • Save to Dropbox
  • Save to Google Drive

Save Search

You can save your searches here and later view and run them again in "My saved searches".

Please provide a title, maximum of 40 characters.
×

Contents

References

Albert, D. (1992) Quantum Mechanics and ExperienceCambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Google Scholar
Albert, D. (2000) Time and Chance. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Google Scholar | PubMed
Albert, D. (2012). Physics and chance. In Y. Ben-Menahem and M. Hemmo (eds.), Probability in Physics. The Frontiers Collection, Berlin Heidelberg: Springer-Verlag, pp. 17–40. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Alexander, H. G (1956) The Leibniz Clark Correspondence. Manchester: Manchester University Press. Google Scholar
Arnold, V. I. and Avez, A. (1968) Ergodic Problems of Classical Mechanics. New York, Amsterdam: Benjamin. Google Scholar
Arntzenius, F. (2000) Are there really instantaneous velocities?The Monist 83(2), 187–208. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Arntzenius, F. (2004) Time-reversal operations and the direction of time. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 35(1), 31–43. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Arntzenius, F. and Greaves, H. (2009) Time reversal in classical electromagnetism. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 60(3), 557–584. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Beisbart, C. and Hartmann, S. (eds.) (2011) Probabilities in Physics. Oxford: Oxford University Press. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Bell, J. S. (1987) Are there quantum jumps? In J. S. Bell (ed.), Speakable and Unspeakable in Quantum Mechanics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 201–212. Google Scholar
Ben Menahem (2011) The causal family: the place of causality in science. SSRN: http://ssrn.com/abstract=1925493 Google Scholar
Bennett, C. (1973) Logical reversibility of computation. IBM Journal of Research and Development 17, 525–532. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Bennett, C. (1982) The thermodynamics of computation: a review. International Journal of Theoretical Physics 21, 905–940. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Bennett, C. (2003) Notes on Landauer's principle, reversible computation, and Maxwell's Demon. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 34(3), 501–510. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Bergmann, P. G. and Lebowitz, J. L. (1955) New approach to nonequilibrium processes. Physical Review 99, 578–587. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Berkovitz, J., Frigg, R. and Krontz, F. (2006) The ergodic hierarchy, randomness and chaos. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 37, 661–691. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Bernoulli, J. (1713) The Art of Conjecturing, together with Letter to a Friend on Sets in Court Tennis. English translation by Edith Sylla (2005). Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press. Google Scholar
Blatt, J. M. (1959) An alternative approach to the ergodic problem. Progress of Theoretical Physics 22(6), 745–756. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Brading, K. and Castellani, E. (eds.) (2003) Symmetries in Physics: Philosophical Reflections. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Brown, H. and Uffink, J. (2001) The origins of time-asymmetry in thermodynamics: the Minus First Law. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 32(4), 525–538. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Brown, H.Myrvold, W. and Uffink, J. (2009) Boltzmann's H-theorem, its limitations, and the birth of statistical mechanics. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 40, 174–191. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Brush, S. (1976) The Kind of Motion We Call Heat. Amsterdam: North Holland. Google Scholar
Bub, J. (2001) Maxwell's Demon and the thermodynamics of computation. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 32(4), 569–579. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Butterfield, J. (2011) Laws, causation and dynamics at different levels. PhilSci Archive, http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/8745/ Google Scholar
Butterfield, J. and Bouatta, N. (2011) Emergence and reduction combined in phase transitions. PhilSci Archive, http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/8554/ Google Scholar
Callender, C. (1995) The metaphysics of time-reversal: Hutchison on classical mechanics. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 46(3), 331–340. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Callender, C. (1999). Reducing thermodynamics to statistical mechanics: the case of entropy. Journal of Philosophy XCVI, 348–373. Google Scholar
Callender, C. (2001) Taking thermodynamics too seriously. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 32(4), 539–553. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Callender, C. (2004) Measures, explanation and the past: should “special” initial conditions be explained?British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 55, 195–217. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Callender, C. (2007) The emergence and interpretation of probability in Bohmian mechanics. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 38, 351–370. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Costa de Beauregard, O. and Tribus, M. (1974) Information theory and thermodynamics. Helvetica Physica Acta, 47, 238–247. Google Scholar
Dürr, D., Goldstein, S. and Zanghi, N. (1992) Quantum equilibrium and the origin of absolute uncertainty. Journal of Statistical Physics 67(5/6), 843–907. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Dürr, D. (2001) Bohmain mechanics. In J. Bricmont, D. Dürr, M. C. Galavottiet al. (eds.), Chance in Physics: Foundations and Perspectives. Lecture Notes in Physics, Springer-Verlag, pp. 115–132. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Earman, J. (1986) A Primer on Determinism. University of Western Ontario Series in Philosophy of Science, vol. 32, Dordrecht: Reidel. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Earman, J. (2002) What time-reversal invariance is and why it matters. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 16(3), 245–264. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Earman, J. (2006) The Past Hypothesis: not even false. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 37, 399–430. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Earman, J. and Norton, J. (1998) Exorcist XIV: the wrath of Maxwell's Demon. Part I. From Maxwell to Szilard. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 29(4), 435–471. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Earman, J. and Norton, J (1999) Exorcist XIV: the wrath of Maxwell's Demon. Part II. From Szilard to Landauer and beyond. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 30(1), 1–40. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Earman, J. and Redei, M. (1996) Why ergodic theory does not explain the success of equilibrium statistical mechanics. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 47, 63–78. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Eddington, A. (1935) The Nature of the Physical World. London: Everyman's Library, J. M. Dent. Google Scholar
Ehrenfest, P. and Ehrenfest, T. (1912) The Conceptual Foundations of the Statistical Approach in Mechanics. Leipzig; reprinted 1990 New York: Dover. Google Scholar
Einstein, A. (1905) Über die von der molekularkinetischen theorie der wärme geforderte bewegung von in ruhenden flüssigkeiten suspendierten teilchen. Annalen der Physik 17, 549–560. English translation in: R. Furth (ed.) Einstein, Albert, Investigations on the Theory of Brownian Motion, New York: Dover, 1926. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Einstein, A. (1970) Autobiographical notes. In P. A. Schilpp (ed.), Albert Einstein: Philosopher-scientist, vol. 2, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Google Scholar
Fahn, P. N. (1996) Maxwell's Demon and the entropy cost of information. Foundations of Physics 26, 71–93. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Fermi, E. (1936) Thermodynamics. New York: Dover, 1956. Google Scholar
Feynman, R. (1963) The Feynman Lectures on Physics, Addison Wesley. Google Scholar
Feynman, R. (1965) The Character of Physical Law. Cambridge: MIT Press. Google Scholar
Feynman, R. (1996) Feynman Lectures on Computation. London: Penguin. Google Scholar
Fredkin, E. and T.Toffoli, T. (1982) Conservative logic. International Journal of Theoretical Physics 21, 219–253. CrossRef | Google Scholar
French, A. P. and Taylor, E. F. (1978) An Introduction to Quantum Physics. Chapman & Hall. Google Scholar
Frigg, R. (2008) A field guide to recent work on the foundations of statistical mechanics. In D. Rickles (ed.), The Ashgate Companion to Contemporary Philosophy of Physics. London: Ashgate, pp. 99–196. Google Scholar
Frigg, R. and Werndl, C. (2012) A new approach to the approach to equilibrium. In Y. Ben-Menahem and M. Hemmo (eds.), Probability in Physics. The Frontiers Collection, Berlin Heidelberg: Springer-Verlag, pp. 99–114. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Ghirardi, G., Rimini, A. and Weber, T. (1986) Unified dynamics for microscopic and macroscopic systems. Physical Review D 34, 470–479. CrossRef | Google Scholar | PubMed
Gibbs, J. W. (1902) Elementary Principles in Statistical Mechanics. New Haven: Yale University Press. Google Scholar
Goldstein, S. (2001) Botlzmann's approach to statistical mechanics. In J. Bricmont, D. Dürr, M. C. Galavottiet al., eds., Chance in Physics: Foundations and Perspectives. Springer-Verlag. Google Scholar
Goldstein, S. (2012). Typicality and notions of probability in physics. In Y. Ben-Menahem and M. Hemmo (eds.), Probability in Physics. The Frontiers Collection, Berlin Heidelberg: Springer-Verlag, pp. 59–72. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Guttmann, Y. (1999). The Concept of Probability in Statistical Physics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Hacking, I. (1975). The Emergence of Probability. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Google Scholar
Hahn, E. L. (1950). Spin echoes. Physical Review 80, 580–594. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Hahn, E. L. (1953). Free nuclear induction. Physics Today 6(11), 4–9. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Harman, P. M. (1982) Energy, Force and Matter: The Conceptual Development of Nineteenth Century Physics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Hawking, S. W. (1988) A Brief History of Time. London: Bantam Press. Google Scholar
Hemmo, M. and Pitowsky, I. (2007) Quantum probability and many worlds. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 38, 333–350. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Hemmo, M. and Shenker, O. (2001) Can we explain thermodynamics by quantum decoherence?Studies in the History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 32, 555–568. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Hemmo, M. and Shenker, O. (2003) Quantum decoherence and the approach to equilibrium (Part I). Philosophy of Science 70, 330–358. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Hemmo, M. and Shenker, O. (2005) Quantum decoherence and the approach to equilibrium (Part II). Studies in the History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 36, 626–648. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Hemmo, M. and Shenker, O. (2006) Von Neumann's entropy does not correspond to thermodynamic entropy. Philosophy of Science 73(2), 153–174. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Hemmo, M. and Shenker, O. (2010) Maxwell's Demon. The Journal of Philosophy 107, 389–411. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Hemmo and Shenker (2011a) Introduction to the philosophy of statistical mechanics: can probability explain the arrow of time in the Second Law of thermodynamics?Philosophy Compass 6/9, 640–651. Google Scholar
Hemmo, M. and Shenker, O. (2011b) Szilard's perpetuum mobile. Philosophy of Science 78, 264–283. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Hemmo, M. and Shenker, O. (2012) Measures over initial conditions. In Y. Ben-Menahem and M. Hemmo (eds.), Probability in Physics. The Frontiers Collection, Berlin Heidelberg: Springer-Verlag, pp. 87–98. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Hutchison, K. (1993) Is classical mechanics really time-reversible and deterministic?British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 44, 341–347. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Jauch, J. M. and Baron, J. G. (1972) Entropy, information and Szilard's paradox. Helvetica Physica Acta 45, 220–232. Google Scholar
Jaynes, E. T. (1957) Information theory and statistical mechanics. Physical Review 106, 620–630 (Part I); Physical Review108, 171–190 (Part 2). CrossRef | Google Scholar
Jaynes, E. T. (1965) Gibbs vs. Boltzmann entropies. American Journal of Physics, 33, 391. Reprinted in Jaynes, E. (1983), Papers on Probability, Statistics and Statistical Physics. Dordrecht: Reidel, pp. 79–88. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Knott, C. G. (1911) Life and Scientific Work of Peter Guthrie Tait. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Google Scholar
Kolmogorov, A. N. (1933) Foundations of the Theory of Probability, English translation 1956. Chelsea Publ. Co., New York. Google Scholar
Kripke, S. (1980) Naming and Necessity. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press. Google Scholar
Lanczos, C. (1970) The Variational Principles of Mechanics. Toronto: University of Toronto Press. Google Scholar
Landau, L. D. and Lifshitz, E. M. (1980) Statistical Physics Part 1, Course in Theoretical Physics vol. 5. 3rd ed. Translation by J. B. Sykes and M. J. Kearsley. Oxford: Butterworth-Heinemann. Google Scholar
Landauer, R. (1961) Irreversibility and heat generation in the computing process. IBM Journal of Research and Development 3, 183–191. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Landauer, R. (1992) Information is physical. Proceedings of PhysComp 1992, Workshop on Physics and Computation. Los Alamitos: IEEE Computers Society Press, pp. 1–4. Google Scholar
Landauer, R. (1996) The physical nature of information. Physics Letters A, 217, 188–193. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Lanford, O. E. (1975) Time evolution of large classical systems. In J. Moser (ed.), Dynamical Systems, Theory and Applications. Berlin: Springer, pp.1–111. Google Scholar
Lanford, O. E. (1976) On the derivation of the Boltzmann equation, Asterisque 40, 117–137. Google Scholar
Lanford, O. E. (1981) The hard sphere gas in the Boltzmann–Grad limit. Physica 106A, 70–76. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Lebowitz, J. (1993) Boltzmann's entropy and time's arrow. Physics Today, September, 32–38. Google Scholar
Leff, H. S. and Rex, A. (2003) Maxwell's Demon 2: Entropy, Classical and Quantum Information, Computing. Bristol: Institute of Physics Publishing. Google Scholar
Loewer, B. (2001) Determinism and chance. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 32, 609–620. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Malament, D. (2004) On the time reversal invariance of classical electromagnetic theory. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 35B (2), 295–315. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Maroney, O. (2005) The (absence of a) relationship between thermodynamic and logical reversibility. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 36, 355–374. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Maudlin, T. (2005) The Metaphysics Within Physics. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Google Scholar
Maudlin, T. (2007) What could be objective about probabilities?Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 38, 275–291. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Maxwell, J. C. (1868) Letter to W. G. Tait. In C. G. Knott, Life and Scientific Work of William Guthrie Tait. London: Cambridge University Press, 1911. Google Scholar
North, J. (2011) Time in thermodynamics. In C. Callender (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Time. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 312–350. Google Scholar
Penrose, O. (1970) Foundations of Statistical Mechanics. New York: Pergamon Press. Google Scholar
Peres, A. (1993) Quantum Theory: Concepts and Methods. Dordrecht: Kluwer. Google Scholar
Pitowsky, I. (1992) Why does physics need mathematics? A comment. In E. Ulmann-Margalit (ed.), The Scientific Enterprise, Dordrecht, Kluwer, pp. 163–167. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Pitowsky, I. (2012) Typicality and the role of the Lebesgue measure in statistical mechanics. In Y. Ben-Menahem and M. Hemmo (eds.), Probability in Physics. The Frontiers Collection, Berlin Heidelberg: Springer-Verlag, pp. 41–58. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Price, H. (1996) Time's Arrow and Archimedes' Point: New Directions for the Physics of Time. New York: Oxford University Press. Google Scholar
Putnam, H. (1967) Psychological predicates. In W. H. Capital and D. D. Merrill (eds.), Art, Mind and Religion. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press; reprinted and retitled: The nature of mental states. In H. Putnam, Mind, Language, and Reality, Philosophical Papers, vol. 2, 2nd edition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press (1979). Google Scholar
Reichenbach, H. (1956) The Direction of Time. Berkeley: University of California Press. Google Scholar
Ridderbos, K. (2002) The coarse graining approach to statistical mechanics: how blissful is our ignorance?Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 33(1), 65–77. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Ridderbos, K. and Redhead, M. (1998) The spin echo experiments and the Second Law of thermodynamics. Foundations of Physics 28(8), 1237–1270. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Russell, B. (1912) On the notion of cause. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society New Series 13, 1–26. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Russell, B. (1921) The Analysis of Mind, Lecture IX. Google Scholar
Shalizi, C. R. and Moore, C. (2003) What is a macrostate? Subjective observations and objective dynamics. arXiv:cond-mat/0303625v1 [cond-mat.stat-mech]. Google Scholar
Shenker, O. (1999) Maxwell's Demon and Baron Munchausen: free will as a perpetuum mobile. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 30, 347–372. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Sklar, L. (1973) Statistical explanation and ergodic theory. Philosophy of Science 40, 194–212. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Sklar, L. (1993) Physics and Chance. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Sklar, L. (2000) Theory and Truth (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Google Scholar
Szilard, L. (1929). On the decrease in entropy in a thermodynamic system by the intervention of intelligent beings. In: H. S. Leff and A. Rex, A. (eds.), Maxwell's Demon 2: Entropy, Classical and Quantum Inforamtion, Computing. Bristol: Institute of Physics Publishing, 2003, pp. 110–119. Google Scholar
Swendsen, R. H. (2011) How physicists disagree on the meaning of entropy. American Journal of Physics 79, 342–348. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Tolman, R. (1938) The Principles of Statistical Mechanics. New York: Dover, 1979. Google Scholar
Tribus, M. and McIrvine, E.C. (1971) Energy and information. Scientific American 224, 179–186. Google Scholar
Tumulka, R. (2006) A relativistic version of the Ghirardi–Rimini–Weber Model. Journal of Statistical Physics 125, 821–840. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Uffink, J. (2001) Bluff your way in the Second Law of thermodynamics. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 32, 305–394. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Uffink, J. (2006) Compendium to the foundations of classical statistical physics. In J. Butterfield and J. Earman (eds.), Handbook for the Philosophy of Physics, Part B, pp. 923–1074. Google Scholar
Uffink, J. (2008) Boltzmann's work in statistical physics. In E. N. Zalta (ed.) The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2008 Edition), http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/statphys-Boltzmann. Google Scholar
Uffink, J. and Valente, G. (2010) Time's arrow and Lanford's theorem. Seminaire Poincaré XV Le Temps, 141–173. Google Scholar
van Fraassen, B. (1989) Laws and Symmetry. Oxford: Clarendon Press. CrossRef | Google Scholar
von Neumann, J. (1932) Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics, English translation by R. T. Beyer (1955). Princeton: Princeton University Press. Google Scholar
von Plato, J. (1994) Creating Modern Probability. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Walker, G. H. and Ford, J. (1969) Amplitude instability and ergodic behaviour for conservative nonlinear oscillator Systems. Physical Review 188, 416–32. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Winsberg, E. (2004). Can conditioning on the “Past Hypothesis” militate against the reversibility objections?Philosophy of Science 71, 489–504. CrossRef | Google Scholar
Zurek, W. (1990). Algorithmic information content, Chuch–Turing thesis, physical entropy and Maxwell's Demon. In W. Zurek (ed.), Complexity, Entropy and the Physics of Information. Redwood: Addison Wesley. Google Scholar

Metrics

Usage data cannot currently be displayed.