Appiah, Kwame Anthony. The Ethics of Identity (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2005).
Appiah, Kwame Anthony. “Identity, Authenticity, Survival: Multicultural Societies and Social Reproduction,” in Gutmann, Amy, ed., Multiculturalism: Examining the Politics of Recognition (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1994), 149–67.
Archard, David. The Ethics of Identity (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2005).
Archard, David. “Freedom Not to Be Free: The Case of the Slavery Contract in J. S. Mill's On Liberty,” Philosophical Quarterly, 40 (1990), 453–65.
Arneson, Richard J. “Joel Feinberg and the Justification of Hard Paternalism,” Legal Theory, 11 (2005), 259–84.
Arneson, Richard J. “Mill versus Paternalism,” Ethics, 90 (1980), 470–89.
Baum, Bruce. Rereading Power and Freedom in J. S. Mill (Toronto: Toronto University Press, 2000).
Beauchamp, Tom. “Paternalism and Bio-Behavioral Control,” The Monist, 60 (1976), 62–80.
Benatar, David. Better Never to Have Been: The Harm of Coming into Existence (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006).
Benatar, David. “Why It is Better Never to Come into Existence,” American Philosophical Quarterly, 34.3 (1997), 345–55.
Benatar, David. “Why It is Better Never to Come into Existence,” in Benatar, David, ed., Life, Death and Meaning (Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, 2004), 155–68.
Benn, S. I.A Theory of Freedom(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988).
Bentham, Jeremy. Constitutional Code, in The Works of Jeremy Bentham, vol. ix, ed. Bowring, J. (New York: Russell & Russell, 1962).
Bentham, Jeremy. Plan for Parliamentary Reform, in The Works of Jeremy Bentham, vol. iii, ed. Bowring, J. (New York: Russell & Russell, 1962).
Berger, Fred. Happiness, Justice, and Freedom (Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1984).
Bird, Colin. An Introduction to Political Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006).
Bogen, James, and Daniel, Farrell. “Freedom and Happiness in Mill's Defence of Liberty,” Philosophical Quarterly, 28 (1978), 325–38.
Boklage, C. “Survival Probability of Human Conceptions from Fertilization to Term,” International Journal of Fertility, 35 (1990), 75–94.
Bosanquet, Bernard. “The Philosophical Theory of the State,” in Bernard Bosanquet, The Philosophical Theory of the State and Related Essays, ed. Gaus, Gerald F. and Street, William (Indianapolis: St. Augustine Press, 2001), 1–293.
Brink, David. “Mill's Moral and Political Philosophy,” in Zalta, Edward N., ed., Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (2007).
Brink, David. “Millian Principles, Freedom of Expression, and Hate Speech,” Legal Theory, 7 (2001), 119–57.
Brison, S. J. “The Autonomy Defence of Free Speech,” Ethics, 108 (1998), 312–39.
Brock, Dan. “Paternalism and Autonomy,” Ethics, 98 (1988), 550–65.
Brown, D. G. “Mill on Liberty and Morality,” Philosophical Review, 81 (1972), 133–58.
Buchanan, Allen. “Social Moral Epistemology,” Social Philosophy & Policy, 19.2 (2002), 126–52.
Buchanan, Allen, et al., From Chance to Choice (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002).
Burley, Justine. “Exactly the Same but Different,” Nature, 417 (2002), 224–5.
Burley, Justine. “Morality and the New Genetics,” in Burley, Justine, ed., Ronald Dworkin and His Critics (Oxford: Blackwell, 2002), 170–92.
Burley, Justine, and John, Harris. “Human Cloning and Child Welfare,” Journal of Medical Ethics, 25 (1999), 108–13.
Callan, Eamonn. “Political Liberalism and Political Education,” Review of Politics, 58.1 (1996), 5–33.
Caney, Simon. “Consequentialist Defenses of Liberal Neutrality,” The Philosophical Quarterly, 41 (1991), 457–77.
Clayton, Matthew. “Individual Autonomy and Genetic Choice,” in Burley, Justine and Harris, John, eds., A Companion to Genethics (Oxford: Blackwell, 2002), 191–205.
Crisp, Roger. Mill and Utilitarianism (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1997).
“Database of Global Policies on Human Cloning and Germ-Line Engineering,” available at www.glphr.org/genetic/genetic.htm.
Davis, Gordon, and Blain, Neufeld. “Political Liberalism, Civic Education, and Educational Choice,” Social Theory and Practice, 33.1 (2007), 47–74.
Devlin, Patrick. The Enforcement of Morals (London: Oxford University Press, 1965).
Donner, Wendy. “Is Cultural Membership a Good? Kymlica and Ignatieff on the Virtues and Perils of Belonging,” in Aiken, William and Haldane, John, eds., Philosophy and Its Public Role: Essays in Ethics, Politics, Society and Culture, St. Andrews Studies in Philosophy and Public Affairs (Exeter: Imprint Academic, 2004), 84–101.
Donner, Wendy. “John Stuart Mill on Education and Democracy,” in Urbinati, Nadia and Zakaras, Alex, eds., J. S. Mill's Political Thought: A Bicentennial Re-Assessment (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007), 250–76.
Donner, Wendy. “John Stuart Mill's Liberal Feminism,” Philosophical Studies, 69 (1993), 155–66.
Donner, Wendy. The Liberal Self: John Stuart Mill's Moral and Political Philosophy (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1991).
Donner, Wendy. “Mill's Theory of Value,” in West, Henry, ed., The Blackwell Guide to Mill's Utilitarianism (Oxford: Blackwell, 2005), 117–83.
Donner, Wendy. “Mill's Utilitarianism,” in Skorupski, John, ed., The Cambridge Companion to Mill (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998), 255–92.
Donner, Wendy, and Richard, Fumerton. Mill (Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell, 2009).
Dworkin, Gerald. “Is More Choice Better than Less?,” in Dworkin, Gerald, The Theory and Practice of Autonomy (Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press, 1988), 62–81.
Dworkin, Gerald. “Moral Paternalism,” Law and Philosophy, 24 (2005), 305–19.
Dworkin, Gerald. “Paternalism,” The Monist, 56 (1972), 64–84.
Dworkin, Ronald. Life's Dominion: An Argument about Abortion, Euthanasia, and Individual Freedom (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1993).
Dworkin, Ronald. “Ronald Dworkin Replies,” in Burley, Justine, ed., Dworkin and His Critics (Oxford: Blackwell, 2004), 362–6.
Dworkin, Ronald. Sovereign Virtue: The Theory and Practice of Equality (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2000).
Dworkin, Ronald. “Sovereign Virtue Revisited,” Ethics, 113 (2002), 106–43.
Dyzenhaus, David. “John Stuart Mill and the Harm of Pornography,” Ethics, 102 (1992), 534–51.
Feinberg, Joel. “The Child's Right to an Open Future,” in Howie, J., ed., Ethical Principles and Social Policy (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1983), 97–122.
Feinberg, Joel. “Legal Paternalism,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 1 (1971), 105–24.
Feinberg, Joel. The Moral Limits of the Criminal Law, 4 vols. (New York: Oxford University Press, 1984–90).
Freeman, Samuel, ed., The Cambridge Companion to Rawls (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003).
Friedman, Marilyn. “Feminism and Modern Friendship: Dislocating the Community,” in Avineri, Shlomo and de-Shalit, Avner, eds., Communitarianism and Individualism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1992), 101–19.
Fuchs, Alan E. “Autonomy, Slavery, and Mill's Critique of Paternalism,” Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 4 (2001), 231–51.
Fuchs, Alan E. “Mill's Theory of Morally Correct Action,” in West, Henry, ed., The Blackwell Guide to Mill's Utilitarianism (Oxford: Blackwell, 2005), 139–58.
Gaus, Gerald F.Justificatory Liberalism (New York: Oxford University Press, 1996).
Gaus, Gerald F. “Liberal Neutrality: A Radical and Compelling Principle,” in Klosko, George and Wall, Steven, eds., Perfectionism and Neutrality (Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield, 2003), 137–65.
Gaus, Gerald F.Modern Liberal Theory of Man (London: Croom-Helm, 1983).
Gaus, Gerald F. “The Moral Necessity of Liberal Neutrality,” in Christiano, Thomas and Christman, John, eds., Contemporary Debates in Political Philosophy (Oxford: Blackwell, forthcoming).
Gaus, Gerald F.Political Theory and Political Concepts (Boulder, CO: Westview, 2000).
Gaus, Gerald F.Social Philosophy (Armonk, NY: M. E. Sharpe, 1999).
George, Robert P.Making Men Moral: Civil Liberties and Public Morality (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993).
Glover, Jonathan. Choosing Children (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006).
Gray, John. “John S. Mill, Traditional and Revisionist Interpretations,” Literature of Liberty, 2 (1979), 7–37.
Gray, John. Mill's On Liberty: A Defence (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1983).
Gray, John. Two Faces of Liberalism (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2000).
Green, Leslie. “Internal Minorities and Their Rights,” in Kymlicka, Will, ed., The Rights of Minority Cultures (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995), 257–72.
Green, T. H. “Lecture on ‘Liberal Legislation’ and Freedom of Contract,” in Harris, Paul and Morrow, John, eds., Lectures on the Principles of Political Obligation and Other Writings (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986), 194–212.
Gutmann, Amy. “Civic Education and Social Diversity,” Ethics, 105.3 (1995), 557–79.
Harris, John. “Clones, Genes, and Human Rights,” in Burley, Justine, ed., The Genetic Revolution and Human Rights (New York: Oxford University Press, 1999), 61–94.
Harris, John. On Cloning (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 2004).
Harris, John. “Procreative Beneficence: Why We Should Select the Best Children,” Bioethics, 15 (2001), 413–26.
Harris, John, and Savulescu, Julian. “The Creation Lottery: Final Lessons from Natural Reproduction: Why Those Who Accept Natural Reproduction Should Accept Cloning and Other Frankenstein Reproductive Technologies,” Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics, 13 (2004), 90–5.
Hart, H. L. A.Law, Liberty and Morality (Oxford: Oxford University Press; Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1963).
Hodson, John D. “The Principle of Paternalism,” American Philosophical Quarterly, 14 (1977), 61–9.
Hoffman, Eva. The Secret (London: Secker & Warburg, 2001).
Holm, Søren. “A Life in the Shadow: One Reason Why We Should Not Clone Humans,” Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics, 7.2 (1998), 160–2.
Hurka, Thomas. “Indirect Perfectionism: Kymlicka on Liberal Neutrality,” Journal of Political Philosophy, 3 (1995), 36–57.
Husak, Douglas N. “Legal Paternalism,” in LaFollette, Hugh, ed., The Oxford Handbook of Practical Ethics (New York: Oxford University Press, 2003), 387–412.
Jacobsen, Daniel. “Mill on Liberty, Speech, and the Free Society,” Philosophy & Public Affairs, 29 (2000), 276–309.
Jaenisch, Rudolf. “Human Cloning – The Science and Ethics of Nuclear Transplantation,” New England Journal of Medicine, 351.27 (2004), 2787–91.
Javitt, Gail H., Kristen, Suthers, and Kathy, Hudson. “Cloning: A Policy Analysis,” Genetics and Public Policy Center (rev. June 2006), available at www.DNApolicy.org.
Kass, Leon. “The Wisdom of Repugnance,” The New Republic, June 2, 1997, 17–26.
Kleinig, John. Paternalism (Totowa, NJ: Rowman & Allanheld, 1984).
Kubler-Ross, Elisabeth. The Wheel of Life: A Memoir of Living and Dying (New York: Scribner, 1997).
Kymlicka, Will. Contemporary Political Philosophy: An Introduction (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990; 2nd edn. 2002).
Kymlicka, Will. “Liberal Individualism and Liberal Neutrality,” Ethics, 99.3 (1989), 833–905.
Kymlicka, Will. Liberalism, Community, and Culture (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1989).
Kymlicka, Will. Multicultural Citizenship: A Liberal Theory of Minority Rights (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1995).
Kymlicka, Will. Politics in the Vernacular: Nationalism, Multiculturalism, and Citizenship (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001).
Larmore, Charles. Patterns of Moral Complexity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987).
Larmore, Charles. “Political Liberalism,” in Larmore, Charles, The Morals of Modernity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), 121–51.
Leridon, H.Human Fertility: The Basic Components (Chicago: Chicago University Press, 1977).
Locke, John. Second Treatise of Government (1690), ed. Macpherson, C. B. (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing, 1980).
Lyons, David. “Liberty and Harm to Others,” reprinted in Lyons, Rights, Welfare, and Mill's Moral Theory (New York: Oxford University Press, 1994), 89–108.
Macedo, Stephen. Diversity and Distrust: Civic Education in a Multicultural Democracy (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2000).
MacIntyre, Alasdair. After Virtue (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1981).
Macleod, Colin. “Agency, Goodness, and Endorsement: Why We Can't Be Forced to Flourish,” Imprints, 7 (2003), 131–60.
McLuhan, Marshall. Understanding Media: The Extensions of Man, ed. Lapham, L. H. (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1994).
Malm, Heidi. “Feinberg's Anti-paternalism and the Balancing Strategy,” Legal Theory, 11 (2005), 193–212.
Mill, James. “Essay on Government” (1824), in Lively, Jack and Rees, John, eds., Utilitarian Logic and Politics (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1978), 53–95.
Mill, John Stuart, Auguste Comte and Positivism (1865), in The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, gen. ed. Robson, John M., vol. x: Essays on Ethics, Religion and Society (Toronto: University of Toronto Press; London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1969), 261–368.
Mill, John Stuart, Autobiography (1873), in The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, vol. i: Autobiography and Literary Essays, ed. Robson, John M. and Stillinger, Jack, introduction by Robbins, Lord (Toronto: University of Toronto Press; London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1981), 1–290.
Mill, John Stuart, The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, 33 vols., gen. ed. Robson, John M. (Toronto: University of Toronto Press; London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1963–91).
Mill, John Stuart, Considerations on Representative Government (1861), in The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, vol. xix: Essays on Politics and Society, Part II, ed. Robson, John M., introduction by Brady, Alexander (Toronto: University of Toronto Press; London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1977), 371–577.
Mill, John Stuart, The Later Letters of John Stuart Mill (1849–1873), vols. xiv–xviiof The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, ed. Mineka, Francis E. and Lindley, Dwight N. (Toronto: University of Toronto Press; London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1972).
Mill, John Stuart, Nature (1874), in The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, vol. x: Essays on Ethics, Religion, and Society, ed. Robson, John M., introduction by Priestley, F. E. L. (Toronto: University of Toronto Press; London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1985), 373–402.
Mill, John Stuart, On Liberty (1859), in The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, vol. xviii: Essays on Politics and Society, Part I, ed. Robson, John M., introduction by Brady, Alexander (Toronto: University of Toronto Press; London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1977), 213–310.
Mill, John Stuart, Principles of Political Economy with Some of Their Applications to Social Philosophy, Part II (1848), vol. iii of The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, ed. Robson, John M., introduction by Bladen, V. W. (Toronto: University of Toronto Press; London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1965).
Mill, John Stuart, “Sedgwick's Discourse” (1835), in The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, vol. x: Essays on Ethics, Religion and Society, ed. Robson, John M. (Toronto: University of Toronto Press; London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1969), 31–74.
Mill, John Stuart, The Subjection of Women (1869), in The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, vol. xxi: Essays on Equality, Law, and Education, ed. Robson, John M., introduction by Collini, Stefan (Toronto: University of Toronto Press; London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1984), 259–340.
Mill, John Stuart, A System of Logic Ratiocinative and Inductive (1843; 8th edn. 1871), vols. vii–viii of The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, ed. Robson, John M., introduction by McRae, R. F. (Toronto: University of Toronto Press; London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1973).
Mill, John Stuart, Utilitarianism (1861), in The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, vol. x: Essays on Ethics, Religion and Society, ed. Robson, John M. (Toronto: University of Toronto Press; London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1969), 203–59.
Mill, John Stuart, “Theism” (1874), in The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, vol. x: Essays on Ethics, Religion and Society, ed. Robson, John M. (Toronto: University of Toronto Press; London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1969), 429–89.
Murphy, Jeffrie. “Incompetence and Paternalism,” Archiv fur Rechts- und Sozialphilosophie, 60 (1974), 465–86.
Nagel, Thomas. “Rawls and Liberalism,” in Freeman, Samuel, ed., The Cambridge Companion to Rawls (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003), 62–85.
Narveson, Jan. The Libertarian Idea (Calgary: Broadview Press, 2001).
Nozick, Robert. Anarchy, State, and Utopia (New York: Basic Books, 1974).
Nussbaum, Martha C.Hiding from Humanity: Disgust, Shame, and the Law (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2004).
Nussbaum, Martha C. “Little C,” in Nussbaum, Martha C. and Sunstein, C. R., eds., Clones and Clones: Facts and Fantasies about Human Cloning (New York: Norton, 1998), 338–46.
Okin, Susan Moller. Justice, Gender, and the Family (New York: Basic Books, 1989).
Okin, Susan Moller. Is Multiculturalism Bad for Women? (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1999).
Okin, Susan Moller. “Whose Traditions? Which Understandings?,” in Okin, Susan Moller, Justice, Gender, and the Family (New York: Basic Books, 1989), 41–73.
O'Neill, Onora. Autonomy and Trust in Bioethics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002).
O'Rourke, K. C.John Stuart Mill and Freedom of Expression: The Genesis of a Theory (London: Routledge, 2001).
Peffer, Rodney. Marxism, Morality, and Social Justice (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1989).
Pendlebury, Michael. “In Defense of Moderate Neutralism,” Journal of Social Philosophy, 33.3 (2002), 360–76.
Pettit, Philip. Republicanism: A Theory of Freedom and Government (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1997).
Pettit, Philip. A Theory of Freedom: From the Psychology to the Politics of Agency (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001).
Pogge, Thomas. John Rawls: His Life and Theory of Justice (New York: Oxford University Press, 2007).
Rawls, John. Collected Papers, ed. Freeman, Samuel (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999).
Rawls, John. “The Domain of the Political and Overlapping Consensus,” in Collected Papers, ed. Freeman, Samuel (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999), 473–96.
Rawls, John. “The Idea of Public Reason Revisited,” in Collected Papers, ed. Freeman, Samuel (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999), 573–615.
Rawls, John. Justice as Fairness, ed. Kelly, Erin (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2001).
Rawls, John. Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993).
Rawls, John. A Theory of Justice (Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press, 1971; rev. edn. 1999).
Raz, Joseph. The Morality of Freedom (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986).
Riley, Jonathan. “Introduction” to Mill, John Stuart, Principles of Political Economy, and Chapters on Socialism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998), vii–xlvii.
Riley, Jonathan. Liberal Utilitarianism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988).
Riley, Jonathan. Mill on Liberty (London: Routledge, 1998).
Riley, Jonathan. “Mill: On Liberty,” in Shand, J., ed., Central Works of Philosophy (Chesham: Acumen, 2005), vol. iii, 127–57.
Riley, Jonathan. “Mill's Doctrine of Freedom of Expression,” Utilitas, 17 (2005), 147–79.
Riley, Jonathan. “Mill's Neo-Athenian Model of Liberal Democracy,” in Urbinati, N., and Zakaras, A., eds., J. S. Mill's Political Thought: A Bicentennial Reassessment (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2007).
Riley, Jonathan. Mill's Radical Liberalism (London: Routledge, forthcoming).
Riley, Jonathan. “Utilitarian Liberalism: Between Gray and Mill,” Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy, 9 (2006), 117–35.
Robertson, John. Children of Choice: Freedom and the Reproductive Technologies (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1994).
Rosenblum, Nancy L.Another Liberalism: Romanticism and the Reconstruction of Liberal Thought (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987).
Rousseau, Jean-Jacques. “The Social Contract” (1762), in The Basic Political Writings, tr. Cress, Donald A. (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing, 1987), 139–227.
Rudisill, John Patrick. “The Neutrality of the State and its Justification in Rawls and Mill,” Auslegung, 23 (2000), 153–68.
Sartorius, Rolf E.Individual Contact and Social Norms (Encina and Belmont, CA: Dickenson, 1975).
Scanlon, T. M. “A Theory of Freedom of Expression,” Philosophy & Public Affairs, 1 (1972), 204–26.
Schwartz, Pedro. The New Political Economy of J. S. Mill (London: Weidenfeld & Nicholson, 1972).
Scoccia, Danny. “Paternalism and Respect for Autonomy,” Ethics, 100 (1990), 318–34.
Sen, Amartya. “Two Confusions, and Counting,” The Globe and Mail, August 23, 2006,
Sher, George. Beyond Neutrality: Perfectionism and Politics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997).
Shiffrin, Seana Valentine. “Paternalism, Unconscionability Doctrine, and Accommodation,” Philosophy & Public Affairs, 29 (2000), 205–50.
Shiffrin, Seana Valentine. “Wrongful Life, Procreative Responsibility, and the Significance of Harm,” Legal Theory, 5 (1999), 117–48.
Skinner, Quentin. “The Idea of Negative Liberty,” in Rorty, Richard, Schneewind, J. B., and Skinner, Quentin, eds., Philosophy of History: Essays on the Historiography of Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1984), 193–221.
Skinner, Quentin. Liberty Before Liberalism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998).
Skinner, Quentin. “The Paradoxes of Political Liberty,” in Miller, David, ed., Liberty (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991), 183–205.
Skorupski, John, Why Read Mill Today? (London: Routledge, 2006).
Solan, Lawrence M. “Private Language, Public Laws: The Central Role of Legislative Intent in Statutory Interpretation,” Georgetown Law Journal, 93.2 (2005), 427–85.
Steiner, Hillel. An Essay on Rights (Oxford: Blackwell, 1994).
Stephen, James Fitzjames. Liberty, Equality, Fraternity (1874), ed. White, R. J. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1967).
Strum, P.When the Nazis Came to Skokie: Freedom for Speech We Hate (Lawrence: University Press of Kansas, 1999).
Sumner, L. W.The Hateful and the Obscene: Studies in the Limits of Free Expression (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 2004).
Taylor, Charles. “Atomism,” in Avineri, Shlomo and de-Shalit, Avner, eds., Communitarianism and Individualism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1992), 29–50.
Taylor, Charles. The Ethics of Authenticity (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1991).
Taylor, Charles. “The Politics of Recognition,” in Gutmann, Amy, ed., Multiculturalism: Examining the Politics of Recognition (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1994), 25–73.
Taylor, Robert. S. “Rawls's Defense of the Priority of Liberty: A Kantian Reconstruction,” Philosophy & Public Affairs, 31.3 (2003), 246–71.
Ten, C. L.Mill on Liberty (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1980).
Ten, C. L.Was Mill a Liberal? (Singapore: Marshall Cavendish Academic, 2004).
Thoreau, Henry David. “Walden; or, Life in the Woods” (1854), in Sayre, Robert F., ed., A Week on the Concord and Merrimack Rivers; Walden, or, Life in the Woods; The Maine Woods; Cape Cod (New York: Library of America, 1985), 321–587.
Urbinati, Nadia. Mill on Democracy: From the Athenian Polis to Representative Government (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2002).
Urbinati, Nadia, and Zakaras, Alex. J. S. Mill's Political Thought: A Bicentennial Reassessment (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007).
Viroli, Maurizio. Republicanism, tr. Shugaar, Antony (New York: Hill & Wang, 2002).
Waldron, Jeremy. “Cultural Responsibility and Civic Responsibility,” in Kymlicka, Will and Norman, Wayne, eds., Citizenship in Diverse Societies (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000), 155–74.
Waldron, Jeremy. “Legislation and Moral Neutrality,” in Waldron, Jeremy, Liberal Rights (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), 149–67.
Waldron, Jeremy. “Mill on the Contagious Diseases Acts,” in Urbinati, Nadia and Zakaras, Alex, eds., J. S. Mill's Political Thought: A Bicentennial Reassessment (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007), 11–42.
Waldron, Jeremy. “One Law for All: The Logic of Cultural Accommodation,” Washington and Lee Law Review, 59 (2003), 3–34.
Walzer, Michael. “Mill's ‘A Few Words on Non-Intervention’ – A Commentary,” in Urbinati, Nadia and Zakaras, Alex, eds., J. S. Mill's Political Thought: A Bicentennial Reassessment (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007), 347–56.
West, Henry, ed. The Blackwell Guide to Mill's Utilitarianism (Oxford: Blackwell, 2005).
Wilkinson, T. M. “Against Dworkin's Endorsement Constraint,” Utilitas, 15 (2003), 175–93.
Wilkinson, T. M. “Dworkin on Paternalism and Well-Being,” Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, 16 (1996), 433–44.
Wilmut, Ian. “The Age of Biological Control,” in Burley, Justine, ed., The Genetic Revolution and Human Rights (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999), 19–28.
Wilson, Woodrow. Message to Congress, 63rd Congress, 2nd Session, Senate Doc. No. 566 (Washington, 1914).
Wolff, Robert Paul. The Poverty of Liberalism (Boston: Beacon Press, 1968).
Young, Robert. “Autonomy and Paternalism,” in Patten, Steven C., ed., New Essays in Ethics and Public Policy, Canadian Journal of Philosophy, sup. vol. 8 (1982), 47–66.
Young, Robert. Personal Autonomy: Beyond Negative and Positive Liberty (London: Croom-Helm, 1986).