Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-s2hrs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-09T07:23:53.256Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

2 - Race and the science of difference in the age of genomics

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  18 December 2014

Sandra Soo-Jin Lee
Affiliation:
Stanford University
Karim Murji
Affiliation:
The Open University, Milton Keynes
John Solomos
Affiliation:
University of Warwick
Get access

Summary

After all, I believe one of the great truths to emerge from this triumphant expedition inside the human genome is that in genetic terms all human beings, regardless of race, are more than 99.9 percent the same. What that means is that modern science has confirmed what we first learned from ancient faiths. The most important fact of life on this earth is our common humanity.

New York Times, 27 June 2000

The beginning of the second millennium coincided with the highly celebrated completion of the draft of the human genome. In conclusion of the race to identify the entire genetic sequence of a representative human genome in 2000, President Clinton, flanked by then director of the National Human Genome Research Institute, Francis Collins, and Craig Venter, then president of Celera Genomics, took the opportunity to reject any assertion of a genetic basis for race. In the epigraph, President Clinton recites a position that becomes the 99.9 per cent mantra among leading researchers in genomics and the general media on lessons learned from the completion of the Human Genome Project (HGP): race does not exist in our genes – we are all the same. Given this unequivocal chorus on race and genetics, it is surprising that more than a decade of developments in human genetics and biomedicine have resulted in a dogged focus on the search for population differences at the molecular level. Although the scientific community has repeatedly affirmed that the vast majority of the human genome is synonymous among human beings, scientists continue to emphasize that the key to understanding the genetic basis for common, complex diseases and variability in drug response lies in the minutiae of genetic differences among groups. Inspecting the incongruity of the mantra of sameness and the increasing salience of racial and ethnic identification of research populations is useful in identifying how concepts of race are operationalized and, in particular, how ‘technologies of racialization’ that highlight, demarcate and exact difference from the human body – phenotypical characteristics such as skin tone, eye shape and blood type – are increasingly supplanted by molecular signatures.

Type
Chapter
Information
Theories of Race and Ethnicity
Contemporary Debates and Perspectives
, pp. 26 - 39
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2014

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

American Association of Physical Anthropologists. (1996). Statement of biological aspects of race. American Journal of Physical Anthropology, 101, 569–70.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bonilla-Silva, E. (2006). Racism without Racists: Color-Blind Racism and the Persistence of Racial Inequality in the United States. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.Google Scholar
Brandt, A. (1985). Racism and research: the case of the Tuskegee Syphilis Study. In Leavitt, J. Walzer and Numbers, R. L., eds, Sickness and Health in America: Readings in the History of Medicine and Public Health. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, pp. 331–46.Google Scholar
Cavalli-Sforza, L. L., Menozzi, P. and Piazza, A. (1994). The History and Geography of Human Genes. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Clayton, E. W. (1995). Why the use of anonymous samples for research matters. Journal of Law, Medicine, and Ethics, 23(4), 375–77.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Dikötter, F. (1998). Race culture: recent perspectives on the history of eugenics. American Historical Review, 103(2), 467–78.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Epstein, S. (2008). Inclusion: The Politics of Difference in Medical Research. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Faden, R. and Beauchamp, T. (1986). A History and Theory of Informed Consent. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Foster, M. and Sharp, R. (2000). Genetic research and cultural specific risks: one size does not fit all. Trends in Genetics, 16(2), 93–95.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fujimura, J. and Rajagapolan, R. (2011). Different differences: the use of ‘genetic ancestry’ versus race in biomedical human genetic research. Social Studies of Science, 41(1), 5–30.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Galton, F. (1987). Eugenics: its definition, scope, and aims. American Journal of Sociology, 10(1), 1–25.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gamble, V. (1997). Under the shadow of Tuskegee: African Americans and health care. American Journal of Public Health, 87(11), 1773–78.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gillborn, D. (1995). Racism, identity and modernity: pluralism, moral antiracism and plastic ethnicity. International Studies in Sociology of Education, 5(1), 3–23.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Greely, H. (2001). Human genomics research: new challenges for research ethics. Perspectives in Biology and Medicine, 44(2), 221–29.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Jones, J. H. (1981). Bad Blood: The Tuskegee Syphilis Experiment. London: Free Press.Google Scholar
Juengst, E. (1998). Groups as gatekeepers to genetic research: conceptually confusing, morally hazardous and practically useless. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal, 8(2), 183–200.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kass, N. and Sugarman, J. (1996). Are research subjects adequately protected?Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal, 6(3), 271–82.Google ScholarPubMed
Koenig, B., Lee, S. S.-J. and Richardson, S. (2008). Revisiting Race in a Genomic Age. New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press.Google Scholar
Lee, S. S.-J., Mountain, J. and Koenig, B. (2001). The meaning of ‘race’ in the new genomics: implications for health disparities research. Yale Journal of Health Policy, Law and Ethics, 1, 33–75.Google Scholar
Lewontin, R. C. (1982). Human Diversity. New York: Scientific American.Google Scholar
Omi, M. and Winant, H. (1994). Racial Formation in the United States, 2nd edn. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Risch, N., Burchard, E., Ziv, E. and Tang, H. (2002). Categorization of humans in biomedical research: genes, race and disease. Genome Biology, 3(7), 1–12.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sankar, P. (2010). Forensic DNA phenotyping: reinforcing race in law enforcement. In I. Whitmarsh and D. Jones, eds, What’s the Use of Race?, pp. 49–62.
Sankar, P., Cho, M. K. and Mountain, J. (2007). Race and ethnicity in genetic research. American Journal of Medical Genetics, 9(143A), 961–70.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stepan, N. L. (1996). The Hour of Eugenics: Race, Gender, and Nation in Latin America. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Tutton, R., Smart, A., Ashcroft, R., Martin, P. and Ellison, G. T. H. (2010). From self-identity to genotype: the past, present, and future of ethnic categories in postgenomic science. In I. Whitmarsh and D. Jones, eds, What’s the Use of Race?, pp. 125–46.
Wailoo, K. (2000). Dying in the City of the Blues: Sickle Cell Anemia and the Politics of Race and Health. Raleigh: University of North Carolina Press.Google Scholar
Wailoo, N., Nelson, A. and Lee, C. (2012). Genetics and the Unsettled Past. New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press.Google Scholar
Weigmann, K. (2001). In the name of science. EMBO Reports, 21(101), 871–75.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weijer, C. (1999). Protecting communities in research: philosophical and pragmatic challenges. Cambridge Quarterly of Health Care Ethics, 8(4), 501–13.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Weiss, K. (1995). Genetic Variation and Human Disease. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Whitmarsh, I. and Jones, D., eds. (2010). What’s the Use of Race?Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Wilcox, A. J., Taylor, J. A. and Sharp, R. R. (1999). Genetic determinism and the overprotection of human subjects. Nature Genetics, 21(4), 362.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Zack, N. (2001). Race and philosophical meaning. In Boxhill, B., ed., Race and Racism. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 43–57.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×