Book contents
- Frontmatter
- Contents
- Preface
- Introduction
- 1 Space and spatial relations
- 2 Hands, knees and absolute space
- 3 Euclidean and other shapes
- 4 Geometrical structures in space and spacetime
- 5 Shapes and the imagination
- 6 The aims of conventionalism
- 7 Against conventionalism
- 8 Reichenbach's treatment of topology
- 9 Measuring space: fact or convention?
- 10 The relativity of motion
- Bibliography
- Index
6 - The aims of conventionalism
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 04 December 2009
- Frontmatter
- Contents
- Preface
- Introduction
- 1 Space and spatial relations
- 2 Hands, knees and absolute space
- 3 Euclidean and other shapes
- 4 Geometrical structures in space and spacetime
- 5 Shapes and the imagination
- 6 The aims of conventionalism
- 7 Against conventionalism
- 8 Reichenbach's treatment of topology
- 9 Measuring space: fact or convention?
- 10 The relativity of motion
- Bibliography
- Index
Summary
A general strategy
The theory of philosophical method which Reichenbach defends is called conventionalism. It faces us with a new danger to our realist conclusion. Many philosophers are conventionalists at present; certainly very many of those who write on the philosophy of space and time are. Conventionalism is a label covering various kindred doctrines. Some of these, like Reichenbach's, seem to have their basis in theories of human knowledge though it isn't quite clear just how. Others, like Adolf Grünbaum's, do not. This chapter pictures the aims which most conventionalist doctrines share and it looks at some of the ideas of method that figure in their arguments. It lays out these main ideas in a largely uncritical way. There is point in a mainly expository beginning, since my disagreement with conventionalists is twofold. First, I want to argue, in chapter 7, that conventionalism is mistaken as a theory of method. Second, I wish to go on, in chapters 8 and 9, to argue that, whether or not conventionalist methods are correct, they do not yield what is claimed for them.
Well then, we want to know what conventionalism is, exactly. Let us first see what it appears to be roughly. If we pick up its main outlines first, we can go into details in different areas in a more coherent, intelligible way. We want a broad impression, to start with, of how Reichenbach thinks he can deal with the examples described in §§5.10 and 5.11. Let me paint his picture in a few bold brush strokes, first turning to the case of spherical space.
- Type
- Chapter
- Information
- The Shape of Space , pp. 139 - 159Publisher: Cambridge University PressPrint publication year: 1994