Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-dh8gc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-07T19:25:37.206Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false
This chapter is part of a book that is no longer available to purchase from Cambridge Core

4 - Epistemological relativism

Paul O'Grady
Affiliation:
Trinity College, Dublin
Get access

Summary

There are a multiplicity of different positions to which the term epistemological relativism has been applied. However, the basic idea common to all forms denies that there is a single, universal means of assessing knowledge claims that is applicable in all contexts. Many traditional epistemologists have striven to uncover the basic process, method or set of rules that allows us to hold true beliefs. Think, for example, of Descartes's attempt to find the rules for the direction of the mind, Hume's investigation into the science of mind or Kant's description of his epistemological Copernican revolution. Each philosopher attempted to articulate universal conditions for the acquisition of true beliefs. Epistemological relativism can be best expressed negatively, just as ontological relativism was expressed in Chapter 3. It rejects an absolutist conception of epistemological justification: that always and everywhere there is a sole fundamental way by which beliefs are justified.

The multiplicity of positions labelled epistemological relativism arises due to the fact that the rejection of this absolutist view yields a variety of possible positions of varying degrees of strength. Philosophers have differed greatly in the amount of relativity they allow into the epistemological process. At a level that hardly anyone rejects, there is a degree of relativity in perceptual knowledge, depending on the perceptual apparatus and location of the individual. Yet perceptual relativism is often regarded as a primitive feature of cognition, below the level at which questions about the justification of belief arises and which is compatible with an absolutist conception of justification.

Type
Chapter
Information
Relativism , pp. 89 - 130
Publisher: Acumen Publishing
Print publication year: 2002

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×