Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-8bhkd Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-09T16:24:19.974Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Chapter 1 - Introduction to Pure Inductive Logic

from Part 1 - The Basics

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 May 2015

Jeffrey Paris
Affiliation:
University of Manchester
Alena Vencovská
Affiliation:
University of Manchester
Get access

Summary

Before a cricket match can begin the tradition is that the umpire tosses a coin and one of the captains calls, heads or tails, whilst the coin is in the air. If the captain gets it right s/he chooses which side opens the batting. There never seems to be an issue as to which captain actually makes this call (otherwise we would have to toss a coin and make a call to decide who makes the call, and in turn toss a coin and make a call to decide who makes that call and so on) since it seems clear that this procedure is fair. In other words both captains are giving equal probability to the coin landing heads as to it landing tails no matter which of them calls it. The obvious explanation for this is that both captains are, subconsciously perhaps, appealing to the symmetry of the situation.

At the same time they are, it seems, also tacitly making the assumption that all the other information they possess about the situation, for example the weather, the gender of the referee, even past successes at coin calling, is irrelevant, at least if it doesn't involve some specific knowledge about this particular coin or the umpires's ability to influence the outcome. Of course if we knew that on the last 8 occasions on which this particular umpire had tossed up this same coin the result had been heads we might well consider that that was relevant.

Forming beliefs, or subjective probabilities, in this way by considering symmetry, irrelevance, relevance, can be thought of as logical or rational inference. This is something different from statistical inference. The perceived fairness of the coin toss is clearly not based on the captains' knowledge of a long run of past tosses by the umpire which have favoured heads close to half the time. Indeed it is conceivable that this long run frequency might not give an average of close to half heads, maybe this coin is, contrary to appearances, biased.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2015

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×